This is intriguing stuff, Joe and I'd like to hear more about what you have in 
mind.

First, I'm not sure what sort of special relationship the two  psychological 
laws in question need to bear to the method of tenacity.  If they're in fact 
psychological (i.e. psychical) laws, then it would be unsurprising if the other 
methods of inquiry made important use of them.  I thought that the only special 
connection between the laws and tenacity is that the method tries to deploy 
those laws especially simply and directly.

Next, can you help me see more clearly how the passage you quote in support of 
your suggestion that Peirce has in mind laws concerning the properties of 
neural tissue, etc. is supposed to yield *two* psychological (in any sense of 
""psychological," since you rightly point out that idioscopic laws might be 
fair game at this point) laws?  I don't love my interpretation and would like 
to find a way of reading Peirce as clearer and less sloppy about this issue.  
But I don't see how your reading leaves us with two laws that Peirce could have 
expected the reader to extract from the text.

Thanks to you and to both Jims and the other participants; Ithis discussion 
makes me resolve to do less lurking on the list (though I've so resolved 
before).

Jeff

-----Original Message-----
From: Joseph Ransdell <[EMAIL PROTECTED]>
To: "Peirce Discussion Forum" <peirce-l@lyris.ttu.edu>
Date: Tue, 3 Oct 2006 15:57:59 -0700 (PDT)
Subject: [peirce-l] Re: What "fundamenal psychological laws" is Peirce 
referring to?

Jeff Kasser says:
  
 JK:  First, as to the question in the heading of your initial message, it 
seems to me that Peirce can only be referring to the antecedents of the two 
conditional statements that motivate the method of tenacity in the first place. 
 These are stated in the first sentence of Section V of "Fixation."  "If the 
settlement of opinion is the sole object of inquiry, and if belief is of the 
nature of a habit, why should we not attain the desired end, by taking any 
answer to a question which we may fancy, and constantly reiterating it to 
ourselves, dwelling on all which may conduce to that belief, and learning to 
turn with contempt and hatred from anything which might disturb it."  In the 
context of the paper, this would seem to make fairly straightforward sense of 
the idea that tenacity rests on "two fundamental psychological laws."  Peirce 
sure seems to think that it should be apparent to the reader on which "laws" 
tenacity rests, and so I don't think we're to wander too far afield
 from the paper itself in determining which the laws are.
  
  REPLY:
  
 JR:  The more I think about it the less plausible it seems to me that either 
of these is what he meant by the two "psychological laws".  What would the 
second one be: If x is a belief then  x is a habit?  That doesn't even sound 
like a law.  And as regards the first, what exactly would it be?  If a belief 
is arrived at then inquiry ends?  Or: If inquiry has ended then a belief has 
been arrived at?  But nothing like either of these seems much  like something 
he might want to call a psychological law.   Moreover, why would he single out 
the method of tenacity as based on these when they are equally pertinent to all 
four methods?  He does say earlier that "the FEELING of believing  is a more or 
less sure indication of there being established in our nature some habit which 
will determine our actions".  That is more like a law, in the sense he might 
have in mind, but that has to do with a correlation between a feeling and an 
occurrence of a belief establishment and, again,
 there is no special relationship there to the method of tenacity in particular.
  
 I suggest that the place to look is rather at the simple description of the 
method of tenacity he gives at the very beginning of his discussion of it when 
he says 
  
 "… why should we not attain the desired end by taking as answer to a question 
any we may fancy, and constantly reiterating it to ourselves, dwelling on all 
which may conduce to that belief, and learning to turn with contempt and hatred 
from anything that might disturb it?"  
  
 This involves reiteration of effort with anticipation of it having a result in 
consequence of it , and thus implicitly makes reference to a possible 
sequential regularity of a lawlike nature.   The two psychological laws might 
then be idioscopic rather than coenoscopic laws, having to do with the 
responsiveness of neural tissue to repeated stimulation and the like, which 
Peirce would know something about.  It doesn't make any difference that it is 
not cenoscopic or properly philosophical since he is referring to it as 
something the devotee of tenacity exploits, not as something logic is based 
upon.  This means that in referring to the two laws he is NOT referring to the 
basic principle that inquiry is driven by doubt, construed as constituted by 
what would be logically described as a formal contradiction. 
  
 Now, as regards that principle, the idea that inquiry -- thinking in the sense 
of "I just can't seem to think today" or "he is a competent thinker" -- is 
driven by doubt in the form of an exerienced  contradiction is not a modern 
idea but has its origins at the very beginning of philosophy in the West in the 
practice of the dialectical craft of Socrates.   Let me quote myself, from a 
paper I wrote a few years back, on the Socratic tradition in philosophy, which 
I claim to be the proper logical tradition to which we should be putting Peirce 
in relation
  
      In its origins Socratic dialectic probably developed as a
      modification of practices of eristic dispute that made use 
      of the reductio techniques of the mathematicians, perhaps 
      as especially modified by the Parmenidean formalists.
      Socratic dialectic differs importantly from the earlier
      argumentation, though, in at least two major respects, 
      first, by conceiving of the elenchic or refutational aspect of 
      the argumentation not as a basis from which one could then
      derive a positive conclusion either as the contradictory of 
      the proposition refuted, as in reductio argumentation, or 
      by affirming the alternative because it was the sole 
      alternative available, but rather as inducing an aporia or
      awareness of an impasse in thought: subjectively, a 
      bewilderment or puzzlement. Second, it differs also by using 
      the conflicting energies held in suspense in the aporia as the
      motivation of inquiry.  (Ransdell, "Peirce and the Socratic 
      Tradition in Philosophy", Proceedings of the Peirce Society, 2000)
  
  http://members.door.net/arisbe/menu/library/aboutcsp/ransdell/socratic.htm
  
 Peirce could take this for granted not because of some well known 
psychological laws but because of the adoption (in a modified form) of the 
basic dialectical principle by Hegel and others, following upon the use of it 
in the Kantian philosophy in the transcendental dialectic of pure reason in the 
First Critique.  I do not say that this should also satisfy us today as 
sufficient to persuade us to the acceptance of the thesis that inquiry is 
driven by doubt, construed as a "dissatisfaction at two repugnant 
propositions".  But it is possible that Peirce did, at the time of composition 
of the Fixation article, think that this would be regarded as being something 
no one would be likely to dispute, or at least as something which no reader of 
the Popular Science Monthly would be likely to dispute.  (That Journal was, as 
I understand it, a rough equivalent of the present day Nature as regards its 
targeted audience, whereas the Scientific American at that time was oriented 
more
 towards applications and inventions than theoretical science.)  It is not 
obvious that logic should be based in a theory of inquiry, but it is not clear 
to me that Peirce regarded that as something which had to be argued for.  In 
any case, none of this affects your thesis about Peirce not regarding the 
Fixation as suffering from psychologism.      
  
 I have a couple of other comments to make, Jeff, but I will put them in 
another message which I probably won't write before tomorrow.
   
  Joe Ransdell
  [EMAIL PROTECTED]

----- Original Message ----
From: Jeff Kasser <[EMAIL PROTECTED]>
To: Peirce Discussion Forum <peirce-l@lyris.ttu.edu>
Sent: Sunday, October 1, 2006 3:04:13 PM
Subject: [peirce-l] Re: What "fundamenal psychological laws" is Peirce 
referring to?

              Joe and other listers,
  
 Thanks, Joe, for your kind words about my paper.  I fear that you make the 
paper sound a bit more interesting than it is, and you certainly do a better 
job of establishing its importance than I did.  It's something of a cut-and 
paste job from my dissertation, and I'm afraid the prose is sometimes rather 
"dissertationy," which is almost never a good thing.
  
 First, as to the question in the heading of your initial message, it seems to 
me that Peirce can only be referring to the antecedents of the two conditional 
statements that motivate the method of tenacity in the first place.  These are 
stated in the first sentence of Section V of "Fixation."  "If the settlement of 
opinion is the sole object of inquiry, and if belief is of the nature of a 
habit, why should we not attain the desired end, by taking any answer to a 
question which we may fancy, and constantly reiterating it to ourselves, 
dwelling on all which may conduce to that belief, and learning to turn with 
contempt and hatred from anything which might disturb it."  In the context of 
the paper, this would seem to make fairly straightforward sense of the idea 
that tenacity rests on "two fundamental psychological laws."  Peirce sure seems 
to think that it should be apparent to the reader on which "laws" tenacity 
rests, and so I don't think we're to wander too far afield from
 the paper itself in determining which the laws are.
  
 This interpretation does have two disadvantages, however.  If my paper is at 
all close to right, then Peirce considered these laws "psychical" rather than 
"psychological," in the 1870's as well as in the 1860's and in the latter half 
of his career (I don't mean that he had the term "psychical" available in 1877, 
however).  But this is one of those places where the fact that Peirce was 
writing for *Popular Science Monthly* can perhaps be invoked to account for 
some terminological sloppiness.  A second consideration is a bit more 
troublesome, however.  It's not easy to see how Peirce could have considered 
"the settlement of opinion is the sole object of inquiry" a psychical or a 
psychological law.  It seems charitable here to see Peirce as writing a bit 
casually once again and to construe him as meaning that the statement in 
question is a normative truth more or less forced on us by psychological (i.e. 
psychical) facts.  But, as the following quote from another of your
 messages indicates, Peirce was pretty quick to close the is/ought gap with 
respect to this issue:
  
  The following axiom requires no comment, beyond the remark that it seems 
often to be forgotten. Where there is no real doubt or disagreement there is no 
question and can be no real investigation.  
 So perhaps he really meant that a statement about the aim of iqnuiry could be 
a (coenscopic) psychological law.  This raises an issue you mention in yet 
another message, viz.  what exactly makes doubts "paper" or otherwise 
inappropriate.  There's been some good work done on this issue, but I think 
Peirce's confidence that the coenscopic data rather directly warrants his 
methodological conclusions is puzzling and I'm trying to wrestle with this 
problem these days.
  
 I'd like to add to remarks about your message concerning my 1999 paper, 
neither of which amounts to a disagreement.  First, I'm inclined to supplement 
your valuable considerations about the coenscopic sense of "mind."  You focus 
on some of our locutions concerning minds like ours, and I'd just add the 
Peircean thought that the coenscopic notion of "mindedness" extends to cases at 
some remove from the human exemplar.  Even something as simple as a sensor is 
going to, as Peirce sees matters, need belief-like states (ways of storing 
information, assumptions about what the world is like, etc.) and doubt-like 
states (ways in which the world can get the sensor's attention).  This needs 
some working out, but Peirce seems to think that the doubt-belief theory will 
hold of anything that can play a certain role (perhaps picked out 
communicatively) in inquiry.
  
 Finally, I should note that I'm perhaps less confident than you are, Joe, that 
Peirce's apparent complaints about the "psychological" basis of "Fixation" and 
"How To" are primarily admissions of a rhetorical failure in allowing those who 
don't understand psychologism to accuse Peirce thereof.  That may account for 
some such passages, but I suspect that in some cases Peirce had in mind his 
preferred (at the time) notion of a philosophical grounding (in phenomenology 
or semiotics or the normative sciences, etc.) and was faulting himself for not 
providing a sufficiently "deep" argument for some of his methodological claims, 
especially the pragmatic maxim.  But you and I are in agreement on the central 
point, which is that Peirce was not accusing himself of anything worth calling 
psychologism.

  Best to all,

  Jeff






---
Message from peirce-l forum to subscriber [EMAIL PROTECTED]





---
Message from peirce-l forum to subscriber archive@mail-archive.com

Reply via email to