Tor Forde gave a URL to an essay by a man named Immanual Wallerstein:  It
takes about 5 minute to read so if you don't have the time or interest, just
skip it.  I found it an excellent summary of what we have been trying to
identify with this thread which seems to have no relation to FW, except I
would postulate that an "earthquake in science" could very well provide new
ideas for social organizations of which the concept, implementation and
doing of work can be radically rethought.  Like Jay, I finally declare my
participation in thread over, but I feel it has been a worthwhile exercise,
unlike one poster who claimed it was "portentous".  Beauty is in the eye of
the beholder.


Respectfully,

Thomas Lunde

"The Structures of Knowledge, or How Many Ways May We Know?"
by Immanuel Wallerstein ([EMAIL PROTECTED])

[Presentation at "Which Sciences for Tomorrow? Dialogue on the Gulbenkian
Report: Open the Social Sciences," Stanford University, June 2-3, 1996.]

The Report of the Gulbenkian Commission bears the title, Open the Social
Sciences. The title bears witness to the sense of the Commission that the
social sciences have become closed off, or have closed themselves off, from
a full understanding of social reality, and that the methods which the
social sciences had historically developed in order to pursue this
understanding may themselves today be obstacles to this very understanding.
Let me try to summarize what I think the Report says about the past 200
years, and then turn to what this implies for what we should now do.

The Commission saw the enterprise of the social sciences as an historical
construction, institutionalized primarily in the period 1850-1945. We
emphasized that this construction was therefore quite recent, and that the
way in which social science was constructed was neither inevitable nor
unchangeable. We tried to explain what elements in the nineteenth-century
world led those who constructed this edifice to make the decisions that were
made concerning the distinctions that were created between a named list of
"disciplines." We sought to outline the underlying logic that accounted for
why the multiple disciplines adopted various epistemologies and why each
chose certain practical methodologies as their preferred ones. We also tried
to explain why the post-1945 world found this logic constraining and set in
motion a series of changes in the academy which had the effect of
undermining the distinctions among the disciplines.

The picture that we drew of the history of the social sciences was that of a
U-shaped curve. Initially, from 1750-1850, the situation was very confused.
There were many, many names being used as the appellations of
proto-disciplines, and none or few seemed to command wide support. Then, in
the period 1850- 1945, this multiplicity of names was reduced to a small
standard group clearly distinguished the ones from the others. In our view,
there were only six such names that were very widely accepted throughout the
scholarly world. But then, in the period from 1945 on, the number of
legitimate names of fields of study has been once again expanding and there
is every sign that the number will continue to grow. Furthermore, whereas in
1945 there still seemed to be clear demarcations that separated one
discipline from another, these distinctions have in the subsequent period
been steadily eroded, so that today there is considerable de facto overlap
and confusion. In short, we have in a sense returned to the situation of
1750-1850 of a large number of categories which do not provide a useful
taxonomy.
But this overlap and confusion is the least of our problems. This process of
defining the categories of the social sciences has been occurring within the
context of a much larger turmoil that goes beyond the social sciences and
implicates the entire world of knowledge. We have been living for 200 years
in a structure of the organization of knowledge in which "philosophy" and
"science" have been considered distinctive, indeed virtually antagonistic,
forms of knowledge. It is salutary to remember that this was not always so.
This division between the so-called "two cultures" is also a rather recent
social construction, only a bit older than that which divided up the social
sciences into a specified list of disciplines. It was in fact virtually
unknown anywhere in the world before the middle of the eighteenth century.

The secularization of society, which has been a continuing feature of the
development of the modern world-system, expressed itself in the world of
knowledge as a two-step process. The first step was the rejection of
theology as the exclusive, or even the dominant, mode of knowing. Philosophy
replaced theology; that is, humans replaced God as the source of knowledge.
In practice, this meant a shift of locus of the authorities who could
proclaim the validity of knowledge. In place of priests who had some special
access to the word of God, we honored rational men who had some special
insight into natural law, or natural laws. This shift was not enough for
some persons, who argued that philosophy was merely a variant of theology:
both proclaimed knowledge as being ordained by authority, in the one case of
priests, in the other of philosophers. These critics insisted on the
necessity of evidence drawn from the study of empirical reality. Such
evidence, they said, was the basis of another form of knowledge they called
"science." By the eighteenth century, these protagonists of "science" were
openly rejecting "philosophy" as merely deductive speculation, and
proclaiming that their form of knowledge was the only rational form.

On the one hand, this rejection of philosophy seemed to argue a rejection of
authorities. It was in that sense "democratic." The scientists seemed to be
saying that anyone could establish knowledge, provided he (or she) used the
right "methods." And the validity of any knowledge that any scientists
asserted could be tested by anyone else, simply by replicating the empirical
observations and manipulation of data. Since this method of asserting
knowledge seemed to be capable of generating practical inventions as well,
it laid claim to being a particularly powerful mode of knowing. It was not
long therefore before "science" achieved a dominant place in the hierarchy
of knowledge production.

There was one major problem, however, in this "divorce" between philosophy
and science. Theology and philosophy had both traditionally asserted that
they could know two kinds of things: both what was true and what was good.
Empirical science did not feel it had the tools to discern what was good;
only what was true. The scientists handled this difficulty with some
panache. They simply said they would try only to ascertain what was true and
they would leave the search for the good in the hands of the philosophers
(and the theologians). They did this knowingly and, to defend themselves,
with some disdain. They asserted that it was more important to know what was
true. Eventually some would even assert that it was impossible to know what
was good, only what was true. This division between the true and the good
constituted the underlying logic of the "two cultures." Philosophy (or more
broadly, the humanities) was relegated to the search for the good (and the
beautiful). Science insisted that it had the monopoly on the search for the
true.

There was a second problem about this "divorce." The path of empirical
science was in fact less "democratic" than it seemed to claim. There rapidly
arose the question of who was entitled to adjudicate between competing
scientific claims to truth. The answer that the scientists gave was that
only the community of scientists could do this. But since scientific
knowledge was inevitably and increasingly specialized, this meant that only
subsets of scientists (those in each subspecialty) were deemed part of the
group that had a claim to judge the validity of scientific truth. In point
of fact, these groups were no larger than the group of philosophers who had
previously claimed the ability to judge each other's insights into natural
law or laws.
There was a third problem about this "divorce." Most persons were unwilling
truly to separate the search for the true and the good. However hard
scholars worked to establish a strict segregation of the two activities, it
ran against the psychological grain, especially when the object of study was
social reality. The desire to reunify the two searches returned
clandestinely, in the work of both scientists and philosophers, even while
they were busy denying its desirability, or even possibility. But because
the reunification was clandestine, it impaired our collective ability to
appraise it, to criticize it, and to improve it.
All three difficulties were kept in check for 200 years, but they have
returned to haunt us in the last third of the twentieth century. The
resolution of these difficulties constitutes today our central intellectual
task.

There have been two major attacks on the trimodal division of knowledge into
the natural sciences, the humanities, and the social sciences. And neither
of these attacks has come from within the social sciences. These attacks
have come to be called "complexity studies" (in the case of the natural
sciences) and "cultural studies" (in the case of the humanities). In
reality, staring from quite different standpoints, both of these movements
have taken as their target of attack the same object, the dominant mode of
natural science since the seventeenth century, that is, that form of science
which is that based on Newtonian mechanics.

To be sure, in the early twentieth century Newtonian physics had been
challenged by quantum physics. But quantum physics still shared the
fundamental premise of Newtonian physics that physical reality was
determined and had temporal symmetry, that therefore these processes were
linear, and that fluctuations always returned to equilibria. In this view,
nature was passive, and scientists could describe its functioning in terms
of eternal laws, which could eventually be asserted in the form of simple
equations. When we say that science as a mode of knowing became dominant in
the nineteenth century, it is this set of premises of which we are speaking.
That which could not be fit into this set of premises, for example, entropy
(which is the description of necessary transformations in matter over time),
was and is interpreted as an example of our scientific ignorance, which
could and would eventually be overcome. Entropy was seen as a negative
phenomenon, a sort of death of material phenomena.

Since the late nineteenth century, but especially in the last twenty years,
a large group of natural scientists has been challenging these premises.
They see the future as intrinsically indeterminate. They see equilibria as
exceptional, and see material phenomena as moving constantly far from
equilibria. They see entropy as leading to bifurcations which bring new
(albeit unpredictable) orders out of chaos, and therefore the process is not
one of death but of creation. They see auto-organization as the fundamental
process of all matter. And they resume this in two basic slogans: not
temporal symmetry but the arrow of time; not simplicity as the ultimate
product of science, but rather the explanation of complexity.
It is important to see what complexity studies is and what it is not. It is
not a rejection of science as a mode of knowing. It is a rejection of a
science based on a nature that is passive, in which all truth is already
inscribed in the structures of the universe. What it is rather is the belief
that "the possible is 'richer' than the real."[1] It is the assertion that
all matter has a history, and it is its sinuous history which presents
material phenomena with the successive alternatives between which each
"chooses" throughout its existence. It is not the belief that it is
impossible to know, that is, to understand how the real world operates. It
is the assertion that this process of understanding is far more complex that
science traditionally asserted that it was.

[1] Ilya Prigogine, La fin des certitudes (Paris: Odile Jacob, 1996), p. 67.

Cultural studies attacked the same determinism and universalism under attack
by the scientists of complexity. But for the most part those who put forward
these views neglected to distinguish between Newtonian science and the
science of complexity, or in many cases to be aware of the latter. Cultural
studies attacked universalism primarily on the grounds that the assertions
about social reality that were made in its name were not in fact universal.
It represented an attack against the views of the dominant strata in the
world-system which generalized their realities into universal human
realities, and thereby "forgot" whole segments of humanity, not only in the
substantive statements but in the very epistemology of their research.
At the same time, cultural studies represented an attack on the traditional
mode of humanistic scholarship, which had asserted universal values in the
realm of the good and the beautiful (the so-called canons), and analyzed
texts internally as incarnating these universal appreciations. Cultural
studies insists that texts are social phenomena, created in a certain
context, and read or appreciated in a certain context.

Classical physics had sought to eliminate certain "truths" on the grounds
that these seeming anomalies merely reflected the fact that we were still
ignorant of the underlying universal laws. Classical humanities had sought
to eliminate certain appreciations of "the good and beautiful" on the
grounds that these seeming divergences of appreciation merely reflected the
fact that those who made them had not yet acquired good taste. In objecting
to these traditional views in the natural sciences and the humanities, both
movements complexity studies and cultural studies sought to "open" the field
of knowledge to new possibilities that had been closed off by the
nineteenth-century divorce between science and philosophy.

Where then does social science fit in this picture? In the nineteenth
century, the social sciences, faced with the "two cultures," internalized
their struggle as a Methodenstreit. There were those who leaned toward the
humanities and utilized what was called an idiographic epistemology. They
emphasized the particularity of all social phenomena, the limited utility of
all generalizations, the need for empathetic understanding. And there were
those who leaned towards the natural sciences and utilized what was called a
nomothetic epistemology. They emphasized the logical parallel between human
processes and all other material processes. They sought to join physics in
the search for universal, simple laws that held across time and space.
Social science was like someone tied to two horses galloping in opposite
directions. Social science had no epistemological stance of its own and was
torn apart by the struggle between the two colossi of the natural sciences
and the humanities.

Today we find we are in a very different situation. On the one hand,
complexity studies is emphasizing the arrow of time, a theme that has always
been central to social science. It emphasizes complexity, and admits that
human social systems are the most complex of all systems. And it emphasizes
creativity in nature, thus extending to all nature what was previously
thought to be a unique feature of homo sapiens.

Cultural studies is emphasizing the social context within which all texts,
all communications, are made, and are received. It is thus utilizing a theme
that has always been central to social science. It emphasizes the
non-uniformity of social reality and the necessity of appreciating the
rationality of the other.

These two movements offer social science an incredible opportunity to
overcome its derivative and divided character, and to place the study of
social reality within an integrated view of the study of all material
reality. Far from being torn apart by horses galloping in opposite
directions, I see both complexity studies and cultural studies as moving in
the direction of social science. In a sense, what we are seeing is the
"social scientiza- tion" of all knowledge.

Of course, like all opportunities, we shall only get fortuna if we seize it.
What is now possible is a rational restructuring of the study of social
reality. It can be one that understands that the arrow of time offers the
possibility of creation. It can be one that understands that the
multiplicity of human patterns of behavior is precisely the field of our
research, and that we may approach an understanding of what is possible only
when we shed our assumptions about what is universal.

Finally, we are all offered the possibility of reintegrating the knowledge
of what is true and what is good. The probabilities of our futures are
constructed by us within the framework of the structures that limit us. The
good is the same as the true in the long run, for the true is the choice of
the optimally rational, substantively rational, alternatives that present
themselves to us. The idea that there are "two cultures," a fortiori that
these two cultures are in contradiction to each other, is a gigantic
mystification. The tripartite division of organized knowledge is an obstacle
to our fuller understanding of the world. The task before us is to
reconstruct our institutions in such a way that we maximize our chances of
furthering collective knowledge.

This is an enormous task, given the inherent conservatism of institutional
authorities and the danger such a reconstruction poses to those who benefit
from the inegalitarian distribution of resources and power in the world. But
the fact that it is an enormous task does not mean that it is not doable. We
have entered a bifurcation in the structures of knowledge, which appears in
many ways to be chaotic. But of course we shall emerge from it with a new
order. This order is not determined, but it is determinable. But we can only
have fortuna if we seize it.

----------------------------------------------------------------------------
----
(Go to top of paper)
(Go to top of list of papers)
(Go to Fernand Braudel Center Home Page)


Reply via email to