Dialectics of Nature. Frederick Engels (1883)

1. INTRODUCTION

MODERN natural science, which alone has achieved an all-round systematic and
scientific development, as contrasted with the brilliant
natural-philosophical intuitions of antiquity and the extremely important
but sporadic discoveries of the Arabs, which for the most part vanished
without results - this modern natural science dates, like all more recent
history, from that mighty epoch which we Germans term the Reformation, from
the national misfortune that overtook us at that time, and which the French
term the Renaissance and the Italians the Cinquecento, although it is not
fully expressed by any of these names. It is the epoch which had its rise in
the last half of the fifteenth century. Royalty, with the support of the
burghers of the towns, broke the power of the feudal nobility and
established the great monarchies, based essentially on nationality, within
which the modern European nations and modern bourgeois society came to
development. And while the burghers and nobles were still fighting one
another, the peasant war in Germany pointed prophetically to future class
struggles, not only by bringing on to the stage the peasants in revolt -
that was no longer anything new - but behind them the beginnings of the
modern proletariat, with the red flag in their hands and the demand for
common ownership of goods on their lips. In the manuscripts saved from the
fall of Byzantium, in the antique statues dug out of the ruins of Rome, a
new world was revealed to the astonished West, that of ancient Greece: the
ghosts of the Middle Ages vanished before its shining forms; Italy rose to
an undreamt-of flowering of art, which seemed like a reflection of classical
antiquity and was never attained again. In Italy, France, and Germany a new
literature arose, the first, modern literature; shortly afterwards came the
classical epochs of English and Spanish literature. The bounds of the old
orbis terrarum were pierced. Only now for the first time was the world
really discovered and the basis laid for subsequent world trade and the
transition from handicraft to manufacture, which in its turn formed the
starting-point for modern large scale industry. The dictatorship of the
Church over men's minds was shattered; it was directly cast off by the
majority of the Germanic peoples, who adopted Protestantism, while among the
Latins a cheerful spirit of free thought, taken over from the Arabs and
nourished by the newly-discovered Greek philosophy, took root more and more
and prepared the way for the materialism of the eighteenth century.

It was the greatest progressive revolution that mankind has so far
experienced, a time which called for giants and produced giants - giants in
power of thought, passion, and character, in universality and learning. The
men who founded the modern rule of the bourgeoisie had anything but
bourgeois limitations. On the contrary, the adventurous character of the
time inspired them to a greater or less degree. There was hardly any man of
importance then living who had not travelled extensively, who did not
command four or five languages, who did not shine in a number of fields.
Leonardo da Vinci was not only a great painter but also a great
mathematician, mechanician, and engineer, to whom the most diverse branches
of physics are indebted for important discoveries. Albrecht Durer was
painter, engraver, sculptor, and architect, and in addition invented a
system of fortification embodying many of the ideas that much later were
again taken up by Montalembert and the modern German science of
fortification. Machiavelli was statesman, historian, poet, and at the same
time the first notable military author of modern times. Luther not only
cleaned the Augean stable of the Church but also that of the German
language; he created modern German prose and composed the text and melody of
that triumphal hymn which became the Marseillaise of the sixteenth century.
The heroes of that time had not yet come under the servitude of the division
of labour, the restricting effects of which, with its production of
onesidedness, we so often notice in their successors. But what is especially
characteristic of them is that they almost all pursue their lives and
activities in the midst of the contemporary movements, in the practical
struggle; they take sides and join in the fight, one by speaking and
writing, another with the sword, many with both. Hence the fullness and
force of character that makes them r.omplete men. Men of the study are the
exception - either persons of second or third rank or cautious philistines
who do not want to burn their fingers.

At that time natural science also developed in the midst of the general
revolution and was itself thoroughly revolutionary; it had to win in
struggle its right of existence. Side by side with the great Italians from
whom modern philosophy dates, it provided its martyrs for the stake and the
prisons of the Inquisition. And it is characteristic that Protestants outdid
Catholics in persecuting the free investigation of nature. Calvin had
Servetus burnt at the stake when the latter was on the point of discovering
the circulation of the blood, and indeed he kept him roasting alive during
two hours; for the Inquisition at least it sufficed to have Giordano Bruno
simply burnt alive.

The revolutionary act by which natural science declared its independence
and, as it were, repeated Luther's burning of the Papal Bull was the
publication of the immortal work by which Copernicus, though timidly and, so
to speak, only from his deathbed, threw down the gauntlet to ecclesiastical
authority in the affairs of nature. The emancipation of natural science from
theology dates from this act, although the fighting out of the particular
antagonistic claims has dragged out up to our day and in many minds is still
far from completion. Thenceforward, however, the development of the sciences
proceeded with giant strides, and, it might be said, gained in force in
proportion to the square of the distance (in time) from its point of
departure. It was as if the world were to be shown that henceforth the
reciprocal law of motion would be as valid for the highest product of
organic matter, the human mind, as for inorganic substance.

The main work in the first period of natural science that now opened lay in
mastering the material immediately at hand. In most fields a start had to be
made from the very beginning. Antiquity had bequeathed Euclid and the
Ptolemaic solar system; the Arabs had left behind the decimal notation, the
beginnings of algebra, the modern numerals, and alchemy; the Christian
Middle Ages nothing at all. Of necessity, in this situation the most
fundamental natural science, the mechanics of terrestrial and heavenly
bodies, occupied first place, and alongside of it, as handmaiden to it, the
discovery and perfecting of mathematical methods. Great work was achieved
here. At the end of the period characterised by Newton and Linnaus we find
these branches of science brought to a certain perfection. The basic
features of the most essential mathematical methods were established;
analytical geometry by Descartes especially, logarithms by Napier, and the
differential and integral calculus by Leibniz and perhaps Newton. The same
holds good of the mechanics of rigid bodies, the main laws of which were
made clear once for all. Finally in the astronomy of the solar system Kepler
discovered the laws of planetary movement and Newton formulated them from
the point of view of the general laws of motion of matter. The other
branches of natural science were far removed even from this preliminary
perfection. Only towards the end of the period did the mechanics of fluid
and gaseous bodies receive further treatment. Physics proper had still not
gone beyond its first beginnings, with the exception of optics, the
exceptional progress of which was due to the practical needs of astronomy.
By the phlogistic theory, chemistry for the first time emancipated itself
from alchemy. Geology had not yet gone beyond the embryonic stage of
mineralogy; hence paleontology could not yet exist at all. Finally, in the
field of biology the essential preoccupation was still with the collection
and first sifting of the immense material, not only botanical and zoological
but also anatomical and even physiological. There could as yet be hardly any
talk of the comparison of the various forms of life, of the investigation of
their geographical distribution and their climatic, etc., living conditions.
Here only botany and zoology arrived at an approximate completion owing to
Linnĉus.

But what especially characterises this period is the elaboration of a
peculiar general outlook, in which the central point is the view of the
absolute immutability of nature. In whatever way nature itself might have
come into being, once present it remained as it was as long as it continued
to exist. The planets and their satellites, once set in motion by the
mysterious "first impulse", circled on and on in their predestined ellipses
for all eternity, or at any rate until the end of all things. The stars
remained for ever fixed and immovable in their places, keeping one another
therein by "universal gravitation". The earth had persisted without
alteration from all eternity, or, alternatively, from the first day of its
creation. The "five continents" of the present day had always existed, and
they had always had the same mountains, valleys, and rivers, the same
climate, and the same flora and fauna, except in so far as change or
cultivation had taken place at the hand of man. The species of plants and
animals had been established once for all when they came into existence;
like continually produced like, and it was already a good deal for Linnaus
to have conceded that possibly here and there new species could have arisen
by crossing. In contrast to the history of mankind, which develops in time,
there was ascribed to the history of nature only an unfolding in space. All
change, all development in nature, was denied. Natural science, so
revolutionary at the outset, suddenly found itself confronted by an
out-and-out conservative nature in which even to-day everything was as it
had been at the beginning and in which - to the end of the world or for all
eternity - everything would remain as it had been since the beginning.

High as the natural science of the first half of the eighteenth century
stood above Greek antiquity in knowledge and even in the sifting of its
material, it stood just as deeply below Greek antiquity in the theoretical
mastery of this material, in the general outlook on nature. For the Greek
philosophers the world was essentially something that had emerged from
chaos, something that had developed, that had come into being. For the
natural scientists of the period that we are dealing with it was something
ossified, something immutable, and for most of them something that had been
created at one stroke. Science was still deeply enmeshed in theology.
Everywhere it sought and found its ultimate resort in an impulse from
outside that was not to be explained from nature itself. Even if attraction,
by Newton pompously baptised as "universal gravitation", was conceived as an
essential property of matter, whence comes the unexplained tangential force
which first gives rise to the orbits of the planets? How did the innumerable
varieties of animals and plants arise? And how, above all, did man arise,
since after all it was certain that he was not present from all eternity? To
such questions natural science only too frequently answered by making the
creator of all things responsible. Copernicus, at the beginning of the
period, writes a letter renouncing theology; Newton closes the period with
the postulate of a divine first impulse. The highest general idea to which
this natural science attained was that of the purposiveness of the
arrangements of nature, the shallow teleology of Wolff, according to which
cats were created to eat mice, mice to he eaten by cats, and the whole of
nature to testify to the wisdom of the creator. It is to the highest credit
of the philosophy of the time that it did not let itself be led astray by
the restricted state of contemporary natural knowledge, and that - from
Spinoza right to the great French materialists - it insisted on explaining
the world from the world itself and left the justification in detail to the
natural science of the future.

I include the materialists of the eighteenth century in this period because
no natural scientific material was available to them other than that above
described. Kant's epoch- making work remained a secret to them, and Laplace
came long after them. We should not forget that this obsolete outlook on
nature, although riddled through and through by the progress of science,
dominated the entire first half of the nineteenth century, and in substance
is even now still taught in all schools. 1
<http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1883/don/ch01.htm#p1> 

The first breach in this petrified outlook on nature was made not by a
natural scientist but by a philosopher. In 1755 appeared Kant's Allgemeine
Naturgesehichte und Theorie des Himmels [General Natural History and Theory
of the Heavens]. The question of the first impulse was abolished; the earth
and the whole solar system appeared as something that had come into being in
the course of time. If the great majority of the natural scientists had had
a little less of the repugnance to thinking that Newton expressed in the
warning: "Physics, beware of metaphysics!", they would have been compelled
from this single brilliant discovery of Kant's to draw conclusions that
would have spared them endless deviations and immeasurable amounts of time
and labour wasted in false directions. For Kant's discovery contained the
point of departure for all further progress. If the earth were something
that had come into being, then its present geological, geographical, and
climatic state, and its plants and animals likewise, must be something that
had come into being; it must have had a history not only of co-existence in
space but also of succession in time. If st once further investigations had
been resolutely pursued in this direction, natural science would now be
considerably further advanced than it is. Rut what good could come of
philosophy? Kant's work remained without immediate results, until many years
later Laplace and Herschel expounded its contents and gave them a deeper
foundation, thereby gradually bringing the "nebular hypothesis" into favour.
Further discoveries finally brought it victory; the most important of these
were: the proper motion of the fixed stars, the demonstration of a resistant
medium in universal space, the proof furnished by spectral analysis of the
chemical identity of the matter of the universe and the existence of such
glowing nebular masses as Kant had postulated.

It is, however, permissible to doubt whether the majority of natural
scientists would so soon have become conscious of the contradiction of a
changing earth that bore immutable organisms, had not the dawning conception
that nature does not just exist, but comes into being and passes away,
derived support from another quarter. Geology arose and pointed out, not
only the terrestrial strata formed one after another and deposited one upon
another, but also the shells and skeletons of extinct animals and the
trunks, leaves, and fruits of no longer existing plants contained in these
strata. It had finally to be acknowledged that not only the earth as a whole
but also its present surface and the plants and animals living on it
possessed a history in time. At first the acknowledgement occurred
reluctantly enough. Cuvier's theory of the revolutions of the earth was
revolutionary in phrase and reactionary in substance. In place of a single
divine creation, he put a whole series of repeated acts of creation, making
the miracle an essential natural agent. Lyell first brought sense into
geology by substituting for the sudden revolutions due to the moods of the
creator the gradual effects of a slow transformation of the earth. 2
<http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1883/don/ch01.htm#p2> 

Lyell's theory was even more incompatible than any of its predecessors with
the assumption of constant organic species. Gradual transformation of the
earth's surface and of all conditions of life led directly to gradual
transformation of the organisms and their adaptation to the changing
environment, to the mutability of species. But tradition is a power not only
in the Catholic Church but also in natural science. For years, Lyell himself
did not see the contradiction, and his pupils still less. This is only to be
explained by the division of labour that had meanwhile become dominant in
natural science, which more or less restricted each person to his special
sphere, there being only a few whom it did not rob of a comprehensive view.
Meanwhile physics had made mighty advances, the results of which were summed
up almost simultaneously by three different persons in the year 1842, an
epoch-making year for this branch of natural investigation. Mayer in
Heilbronn and Joule in Manchester demonstrated the transformation of heat
into mechanical energy and of mechanical energy into heat. The determination
of the mechanical equivalent of heat put this result beyond question.
Simultaneously, by simply working up the separate physical results already
arrived at, Grove - not a natural scientist by profession, but an English
lawyer - proved that all so-called physical energy, mechanical energy, heat,
light, electricity magnetism, indeed even so-called chemical energy, become
transformed into one another under definite conditions without any loss of
energy occurring, and so proved post factum along physical lines Descartes'
principle that the quantity of motion present in the world is constant. With
that the special physical energies, the as it were immutable "species" of
physics, were resolved into variously differentiated forms of the motion of
matter, convertible into one another according to definite laws. The
fortuitousness of the existence of a number of physical energies was
abolished from science by the proof of their interconnections and
transitions. Physics, like astronomy before it, had arrived at a result that
necessarily pointed to the eternal cycle of matter in motion as the ultimate
reality.

The wonderfully rapid development of chemistry, since Lavoisier, and
especially since Dalton, attacked the old ideas of nature from another
aspect. The preparation by inorganic means of compounds that hitherto had
been produced only in the living organism proved that the laws of chemistry
have the same validity for organic as for inorganic bodies, and to a large
extent bridged the gulf between inorganic and organic nature, a gulf that
even Kant regarded as for ever impassable.



_______________________________________________
Marxism-Thaxis mailing list
Marxism-Thaxis@lists.econ.utah.edu
To change your options or unsubscribe go to:
http://lists.econ.utah.edu/mailman/listinfo/marxism-thaxis

Reply via email to