Wow! Thanks for the synopsis. I don't understand how biosemiotics is Neo-Kantian, though. If you are referring to Soviet philosopher David Dubrovsky, I'd appreciate some expansion on this topic as well.

Do you know whether Whitehead had a social theory? The lack of social theory in the biosemiotcs schema is as telling as the failure to distinguish between the "semiosis" of unicellular organisms and human beings.

I saw Sebeok back in the '70s. He didn't talk about this, but he did say something suspicious. He said something about overeating as a craving for information. This is a cute metaphor, but it also reveals the idealism of interpreting the material universe as information.

This picture shows up what I'm trying to get it in the distinction between mystical and materialist emergentism. There is a "dialectical" lesson here. Note that the linchpin of all these bad biosemiotic arguments comes from the metaphysical ordering of empirical data and the manipulation of the relationships between philosophical categories. This is where dialectics is important, not in the direct intervention into empirical science.

I think I need to repeat this last paragraph a few hundred times and then explain it. For now, though, just note the categorial relationships between matter, information, meaning, mind, society ... that form the basis of this idealist discipline.

At 12:26 PM 3/12/2005 +0200, Oudeyis wrote:
Ralph,
1.    You should be distrustful of this biosemiotics business.  In essence,
it's just a new twist on the kind of Neo-Kantian Ideas, Western and Russian,
that Lenin (1908) warned us about in Materialism and Empirio-Criticism.

 2.   I don't know just how much you want to know about it so I'll just
provide a quick sketch of the origins, history and family ties of
biosemiotics and a general description and criticism of two of its more
important theoretical developments (Western: Hoffmeyer and Emmeche, Russian:
Alexei Sharov).

ORIGINS, HISTORY, AND GENEOLOGY OF BIOSEMIOTICS:
3.     Biosemiotics shares with Ethology and Biosociology a common ancestor
in Jakob v. Uexküll of umweltforschung fame.  Umwelt can be understood to
mean the world of significant experience of any specified, individual life
form.

 4.    Here's how it's put in the encyclopedia of the free dictionary.com
http://encyclopedia.thefreedictionary.com/Umwelt
Umwelt (from the German umwelt, "environment") is the "biological
foundations that lie at the very epicentre of the study of both
communication and signification in the human [and non-human] animal." The
term is usually translated as "subjective universe". Uexküll theorized that
organisms can have different Umwelten, even though they share the same
environment.
Each component of a Umwelt has a meaning which is functional for a
particular organism. Thus it can be water, food, shelter, potential threats,
or points of reference for navigation. An organism creates its own Umwelt
when it interacts with the world, and at the same time the organism reshapes
it. This is termed a 'functional circle'. The Umwelt theory states that the
mind
and the world are inseparable, because it is the mind that interprets the
world for the organism.

5.    As you can gather from this description, umwelt is a very Kantian
concept.  That is to say that umwelt describes the world of the life form as
the "product" of its subjective consciousness.  Uexküll (1864-1944) along
with Dilthey and Popper in historical studies and Levy-Bruhl and Franz Boas
in anthropology and Mach and Avenarius in the philosophy of science is among
the considerable number of European and Russian intellectuals who developed
the distinctive Neo-Kantianism that still dominates much of the so-called
advanced thinking of modern science, even today.

6.     Thomas Sebeok (1920-2001), the Hungarian-American semioticist,
combined v. Uexküll's ideas with the theories of language of de Sassure and
Jakobsen thereby inventing the discipline of biosemiotics.  Sebeok's
biosemiotics is based on the following three principles: See
http://encyclopedia.thefreedictionary.com/biosemiotics  for more on this.
1. The signification, communication and habit formation of living processes
2. Semiosis (changing sign relations) in living nature
3. The biological basis of all signs and sign interpretation
Biosemiotics is "biology interpreted as sign systems".  It certainly is a
revolutionary approach when compared with the almost exclusive focus of
orthodox biological theorizing on the mechanical properties of life systems.
Biosemiology represents a new focus on life process (rather than mechanism)
as the conveyance of signs and  and their interpretation by other living
signs in a variety of ways, including by means of molecules.  While
biosemiotics takes for granted and respects the complexity of living
processes as revealed by the existing fields of biology - from molecular
biology to brain science and behavioural studies - its object is to bring
together separate findings of the various disciplines of biology (including
evolutionary biology) into a new and more unified perspective on the central
phenomena of the living world, including the generation of function and
signification in living systems, from the ribosome to the ecosystem and from
the beginnings of life to its ultimate meanings.

7.     For the biosemioticist signification, is understood to be real
material activities: They are governed by regularities (habits, if not laws)
that can be discovered and explained. They are intrinsic in living nature,
but we can access them, not directly, but indirectly through other sign
processes (measurements for instance) - even though the human representation
and understanding of these processes (in the construction of explanations)
builds up as a separate scientific sign system distinct from the organisms'
own sign processes.

8.     The tremendous expansion of research into the mechanics of
inheritance is accompanied by a growing realization that the complexity of
life activity cannot be easily unified by mechanical theory (see Hoffmeyer
"Biosemiotics: Towards a New Synthesis in Biology" European Journal for
Semiotic Studies Vol. 9 No. 2, 1997 pp. 355-376).  The difficulties of
developing a unified
mechanical theory even for evolutionary processes (we've come a long way
since Dawkins wrote) has made Uexküll and Sebeok's work much more attractive
to bioscience than ever before.  Hoffmeyer and Emmeche are the leading
figures in this development in Europe and the US while Alexei Sharov has
been the most prominent thinker in this area in Russia.

HOFFMEYER, EMMECHE AND SHAROV:
9.     Hoffmeyer and Emmeche:  Hoffmeyer and Emmeche, share with Kant the
objective of determining the universals that govern activity.  They go one
better than Kant, and search for the universals that govern all life
activity, from the DNA molecule in the Zygote to the writing of important
articles in the European Journal for Semiotic Studies.  Hoffmeyer even goes
so far as to suggest that consciousness is not a truly important part of
creatively selective activity.

10.     The problem of the origin of semiosis for Hoffmeyer and Emmeche is
the acquisition by pre-biotic systems of the capacity to impart significance
(essence) to the differences in their environment. They posit that the
necessary and sufficient conditions for a system to make distinctions in
this sense is that it has developed self-reference based on code-duality,
i.e. the continued chain of digital-analogue (i.e. DNA cell)
re-interpretations guiding the genealogical descent (Hoffmeyer 1997). The
basic idea of code duality and self-representation is the existence of a
digital codifier (like DNA, RNA, or what have you) and an interpretant
(zygote, cell, or organism) that is able to read the digital info as
structure and process and reproduce an analogue of the object (the
Phenotype) recorded digitally (the Genotype) by the codifier (Hoffmeyer and
Emmeche 1991 in M. Anderson and Floyd Merrell eds On Semiotic Modelling pp.
117-166).

11.     Evolution, Natural Selection, an external mechanism, explains the
development of semiosis over time (after all the theory itself, like all
Kantian and Neo-Kantian theory contains no internal dynamic to explain
change).  Naturally, the focus of the Hoffmeyer - Emmeche model on semiosis
leads them to propose that the natural selective process discriminates
between semiotic systems rather than on genetic or on anatomic-economic
activity.  This is a revolutionary proposal in the context of the Standard
Model of Natural Selection since what is selected are intra- and
interspecies interactional systems rather than species themselves.
Hoffmeyer (1997) further postulates that evolution maximizes sophistication
of semiotic interactions, i.e. semiotic freedom, as well as enhanced
information content.  He writes in the same article:
"And to the extent evolution favours the establishment of refined semiotic
interaction patterns between species, it will also tend to open the way for
a multitude of physical interactions between species.  In this perspective
symbiotic relations are not to considered just funny accidents, rather they
constitute a systematically occurring phenomenon in the semiosphere {cf.
Salthe 1993 Development and Evolution: chap. 6]".

12.     Play, (Hoffmeyer uses Bateson's (1979 Mind and Nature) description
of play as experimental interaction as opposed to ritual) to explain the
input of new semiotic systems into the Natural Selection meat grinder.
Interestingly, he recognizes that as play pushes semiotic freedom upwards it
becomes virtually impossible (as games become more complex they tend to
produce no-win results) to measure the stakes of individual players
(individuals, demes, or species) in the game, and suggests that Natural
Selection does not discriminate between individual semiotic systems, but
rather between different kinds of play activity.

13.       Despite his insinuation that species selection may not be as
central to Natural Selection as represented in the Standard Model, Hoffmeyer
returns speciation back into the selective process by suggesting that
species selection operates in favour of increased sophistication of mate
recognition or, better, of recognition all the cues in the environment that
influence reproductive activities in the direction of demic isolation. Thus,
semiotics might hold the essential clue to the origin of species.

14.     Tommi Vehkavaara (1998 Some Conceptual Extensions in Biosemiotics
and the Extended Concept of Knowledge) describes the Hoffmeyer - Emmeche
model as extension of the concept of subjectivity into what is inherently
unconscious activity.  They are not the first to have done this, Franklin
Pierce, the American pragmatist and semiologist-logician.  Pierce theorized
that essence can be arrived at without consciousness if the subjective
meaning, the interpretant should be defined simply as the appropriate
reaction of an interpreter when the sign starts to represent the object for
the interpreter.

15.    Hoffmeyer and Emmeche's model is clear as regards the identity of the
interpreter of the digital information system as analogue, i.e. the cell or
zygote or for that matter the human individual.  On the other hand, the
interpretation and identity of the interpreter of the object as digital
information is ambiguous to say the least.  The interpretation of the object
as digital occurs at a different level from the former process and the
interpreter is identified as the population or lineage of an evolving group.
This group is generally not reducible to individual cells, so the link
between object to digital and digital to analogue must be realized by some
sort of (non-conscious) interaction between individuals and groups.
Hoffmeyer identifies this link in the Swarm (Hoffmeyer 1997 The Swarming
Body); Swarms being self-organized groups of minor subjects capable of
coherent collective functioning.  This is only a partial solution since both
Hoffmeyer and Emmeche are insistent that the object represented by the
digital presentation is a whole organism and not just a co-operating
collectivity.

16.    The Russian biosemiologist, Alexei Sharov, more or less resolves the
question by clearer distinguishing between the interpreter and the
interpretant, i.e. the interpretant is the product of the interpreter (the
descendent is the product of the interpretation of the interpreter, cell,
zygote, organism).  He also argues (and here we begin to see where Sharov
"is coming from") that the object must exist before the digital
representation and that representation is further manifested by the
formation of the interpretant (Vehkavaara 1998).  The problem with Sharov's
argument is that his interpretant (the gene frequency in the descendent
population) is not a true interpreter of the object.  Though Sharov's
interpretant, the descendants (the gene frequency of the descendent
population) the fact of differential reproduction in the descendent
population does indeed effect the relation of interpreter with the
environment such that certain objects are selected for digitalisation as
contrasted with others that are ignored or discarded.

17.     Sharov's general reasoning concerning biosemiotics differs somewhat
from that of Hoffmeyer and Emmeche.  He also proposes a dual system, but he
represents this dual system as consisting of a the macro-features of
structure or of material and its representation by the micro-features of
information bearing media or ideality.  Remind you of anyone you know?
Well, here's another hint. The material world is independent because its
dynamics can be predicted along all stable trajectories, while the ideal
world can interfere in this process only at unstable bifurcation (choice)
points.  I'll quote the rest of the paragraph (Sharov 1992 Biosemiotics:
Functional-Evolutionary Approach to the Analysis of the Sense of Information
from Sebeok and Umiker-Sebeok (ed.) Biosemiotics, The Semiotic Web):
"That's why such [bifurcation points] points are essential for the function
of actual information.  The more is the number of unstable points the more
matter is 'spiritualised'.  It becomes clear why physics predicts the
movement of a stone perfectly but cannot predict the movement of a man."
(And that should confirm without a doubt where Sharov is coming from)!

18.    Sharov recognizes that while the interpretation of matter into
informational code describes the material world in an "ideal" form, it does
not truly indicated essence or significance.  To produce essence he
introduces the concept of value as the third element of the system (or the
second element of the signifying process).  In general, value is interpreted
as purpose or utility, a conscious activity, which is not a useful concept
for describing the non-conscious activities of primitive life.  Sharov
suggests that since purpose perishes after being combined with the system
(if the purpose is attained there is no more purpose), value must be
separable from purpose.  As he sees it, value is immanent to its bearer.  It
can be thought of as a purpose as it is combined with a system, as
'entellehia' (his term, not mine) or 'containing purpose'.  Thus, Sharov
represents value as objectively measurable by the coefficient of
reproduction.  Value, in this sense, exists as a function of processes of
self-maintenance and self-reproduction, or, in other words, as equivalent to
the system's ability to support survival and reproduction of the information
that embodies the system.  In this fashion, Sharov avoids the extended
subjectivity suggested by the Hoffmeyer-Emmeche model, but at the cost of
producing a pseudo-biosemiotic system (see Vehkavaara critique above)

19. Sharov's material description of essence-value enables him to adopt a
view of Natural Selection, less radical than that of Hoffmeyer and Emmeche.
Sharov regards the development of self-replicating systems as the
development of sense expansion in time and space through discrimination in
favour of value by Natural Selection.  Sharov concurs with Teilhard de
Chardin's idea of non-living nature as pre-life, containing ideality in its
rudimental form.  The origin of life is in the assignment of value through
Natural Selection of this rudimentary ideality, thereby imparting to it
essence and transforming it into information.  The introduction of essence
into the natural world produces matter that can extend itself in time and
space by reproducing offspring and actively interact with its environment.
By interacting with its surroundings, the self-reproducing matter
incorporates elements of the latter into its internal system or, in other
words, its internal space.

GENERAL CRITIQUE OF BIOSEMIOTICS:
20. I will limit the criticism of Biosemiotics to 3 main points:
1. Its absolute (or nearly absolute) obliviousness to the role of social
life; conscious and unconscious in the development of semiotic systems.
2. It's fundamentally ahistorical conception of development.
3. It's failure to account for the development of learning in virtually all
multi-celled organisms and of consciousness in all vertebrates and possibly
in some of the invertebrates.

21.  In general, the biosemoticists ignore the role of social life in the
development of semiotic systems.  Hoffmeyer and Emmeche's approach is
unabashedly a subjectivist one in which the whole semiotic process is
regarded as an immanent feature of organism without almost any need to
postulate a learning process much less the formation of normative
representations (ideas) to account for knowledge and thought.  I write here,
"almost", because of Hoffmeyer's only partially successful effort to
identify the interpreter of the object with the swarm, which is, indeed, a
primitive and non-conscious sort of sociality.  The effort is only partially
successful since Hoffmeyer, in the final analysis, cannot actually account
for the actual physical link between the swarm and the single cell member
(the digital interpreter).  Sharov's adoption of Dubrovsky's avowedly
non-social materialism is implicit in his definition of ideality as a purely
subjective, or, in this case, individual property.  Though Sharov does
present a tolerable theory for conditioned learning, ideality and value,
i.e. information does not exist outside the bounds of the individual and he
encounters considerable difficulty in determining an objective medium
whereby information acquired through conditioning is transferred from
individual to individual.  The best he can do is propose that similarity of
macro- (material) and micro- (ideal) fields of related organisms enables
them to communicate through the use of shared signs, which is about as
precise a representation as any of Kant's ideas of common understanding (see
Ilyenkov, 1974 Dialectical Logic chap. 3 and 5) .

 22.  The object of Hoffmeyer, Emmeche and Sharov's work is to produce a
single theory that encompasses the semiotic activities of all life forms
from the retrovirus to man.  In truth, all three recognize that human
semiotic activity is quite different from that of primitive life (Hoffmeyer
identifying the nearly total independence of human consciousness from
natural restraints and Sharov in recognizing that human semiotic activity is
associated with man's virtually absolute control over the properties of his
environment), but none of them can account for these strange developments
within the context of their theoretical formulations.  It appears to me that
the failure of Hoffmeyer's argument that the swarm is the interpreter of the
object arises out of his attempt to unite the swarm and cell in a simple
synthesis.  In fact, the swarm represents a dialectical negation of the cell
and that it is out of this dialectical negation that one might generate the
fully organized multicellular life form. By regarding the relation between
cell, swarm, and multicellular organism as a dialectical process, Hoffmeyer
might have been able to postulate a parallel history of semiosis involving
distinct processes for each stage of organizational development, each stage
of semiosis negating and sublating the prior stages in a truly historical
schema for semiotic development.

23.  Without a consideration of the impact of social life on the development
of semiotic systems and committed to an abstract, ahistorical representation
of semiotic activity, the proponents of biosemiotics cannot account for the
development of the very consciousness that enables them to reflect on
natural phenomenon and to construct ideas about it.  It's hard to believe
that the same processes whereby the ambient bacterium senses a good meal
just a little to his starboard bow is the same as that produced the papers
on biosemiotics.

Links on Biosemiotics:
 The international biosemiotics page
Overview of Gatherings in Biosemiotics
The S.E.E.D. Journal (Semiotics, Evolution, Energy, and Development)
Jakob von Uexküll Centre
Zoosemiotics Home Page
Biosemiotics Home Page


_______________________________________________
Marxism-Thaxis mailing list
Marxism-Thaxis@lists.econ.utah.edu
To change your options or unsubscribe go to:
http://lists.econ.utah.edu/mailman/listinfo/marxism-thaxis

Reply via email to