Haven't had time to follow up on all the places the discussion went
to; this is more a supplement of what JF posted about positivism. I
found it a good review from a 'philosophy of sociology' perspective.

Link and excerpt follows.

CJ

-------

http://www.bangladeshsociology.org/CV%20of%20Nazrul%20-%20Pub%20-%20Positivism.htm

                    Early Sociological and Marxist Positivism·



excerpt:

>>Perhaps it amounts to heresy to call Karl Marx a positivist. By the
same token, with the exception of a few like Comte or Mach, no one
ever claimed to be a Positivist, though Mill, Spencer, Durkheim Trade,
Wundt or Lundberg were all as positivists. This paper also does not
make Marx into a positivist; it only attempts to point to the
similarities between the Marxist methodology and those of the early
sociologists, like Comte and Spencer, who were positivists.

No attempt is made here to denounce the dialectical basis of Marx's
methodology. Nor is positivism posed against dialectics as is done by
a number of German sociologists (see Adorno et. al. 1976 and Gellner
1985). This essay is not even directed at exploring the merits or
demirits of positivism vis a vis dialectics, nor even to salvage
positivism by anchoring it in the works of Marx. It is, however,
expected here that a demonstration of parallelism between Marxist
methodology and early sociology will go a long way to bridge the ever
widening gap between Marxist science of society and modern sociology
and can be immensely beneficial to the latter.

Over the period of one and a half centuries positivism has acquired
various meanings and seen numerous shifts in the emphasis of its
contents. Though its origin is intertwined with that of sociology and
had the social sciences as its focus, much of the later development of
positivism is attributed to the natural scientists and philosophers of
science in general. The derogatory connotation associated with
positivism may be imputed to the easy passage it provides towards
empiricism or "scienticism," which have always remained only a step
beyond. Left within its bounds, positivism provides a strong
foundation on which the social sciences, and sociology in particular,
or at least the main stream of it, continue to build themselves.

Because of its chequered history, a unitary definition or even a
simple explanation of positivism is difficult to attempt. According to
Keat and Urry (1978) the main arguments of positivism are as follows.
For the positivist, they say, science is an attempt to gain predictive
and explanatory knowledge of the external world (1978: 4). Toward this
end the positivist constructs theories, or highly generalized
statements (laws) expressing the regular relationships that are found
in the external world discovered through systematic observation and
experimentations. To explain or to predict something is to show that
it is an instance of these regularities. Statements expressing these
regularities cannot be known by a priori means, nor are their truth a
matter of logical necessity, it is only contingently so. All such
statements must therefore be objectively tested through observation
and experiments, which are the only source of sure and certain
empirical knowledge. Science does not go 'behind' or 'beyond' the
phenomena revealed to us through sensory experience to attain
knowledge of the unobservable, essence or mechanisms that somehow
necessitate these phenomena. For the positivist there is no necessary
connections in nature, there are only regularities, meaning succession
of phenomena, which are systematically presented in terms of universal
laws of scientific theory. The region beyond this is the realm of
metaphysics. (Keat and Urry 1978: 4-5).

The positivist, thus, looks for regularities in the external world,
presented in the form of sensory data. These are built into universal
laws verified through observation and experimentations. No
metaphysical speculation or search for the "essence" of phenomena is
entertained. Such philosophical orientations and methodological
requirements obviously relate to the domain of the natural sciences.
But sociology, or part of it, has sought to emulate these standards
since its inception. Thus the natural sciences became the model for
sociology. Giddens (1978) identifies this "positivistic attitude" in
sociology as comprising of the position (a) that the methodological
procedures of natural science may be directly applied to sociology;
(b) that the outcome or the end result of sociological investigations
can be formulated in terms parallel to those of natural science – that
is to formulate laws or law like generalizations; and (c) that the
findings of sociological research do not carry any logically given
implications for practical policy or for the pursuit of values.
(Giddens 1978: 3-4). Giddens (1978) notes that acceptance of any one
of these three suppositions do not necessarily entail the adoption of
the other two. And as will be shown later, for the early sociologists
like Comte in particular, attainment of sociological knowledge, as
opposed to point (c) above, was directed to influence policy matters,
to change society in a desired direction.

Similarly, von Wright (1976) also suggests three 'basic tenets' of
positivism: (a) Methodological monism, or the idea of the unity of
scientific method against the diversity of subject matter. (b) The
exact natural sciences, in particular mathematical physics, as setting
a methodological ideal for all other sciences. And (c) causal
scientific explanation that consists in sub-sumption of individual
cases under hypothetically assumed general laws of nature.>>end of
excerpt
_______________________________________________
Marxism-Thaxis mailing list
Marxism-Thaxis@lists.econ.utah.edu
To change your options or unsubscribe go to:
http://lists.econ.utah.edu/mailman/listinfo/marxism-thaxis

Reply via email to