http://home.mira.net/~andy/works/reading-capital.htm

Political economy is the system of thought forms within which people
live by producing and exchanging commodities, and Capital demonstrated
this – the whole universe of sweat-shops, insurance companies,
industrial corporations, multimillionaires, famines and wars flows
from commodity production. Within such a world, in the main, the
concepts of political economy are valid to the extent that they are
connected with practice rather than apologetic “Just So” myths. The
struggle against capitalism is therefore the struggle against that
world of a particular kind of inverted consciousness, one in which
social relations between people take the form of relations between
things.

But in a letter to Kugelmann on 28 December 1862, Marx says of the
soon-to-be-published book: “It is a sequel to Part I, but will appear
on its own under the title, Capital, with A Contribution to the
Critique of Political Economy as merely the subtitle.” Marx worked
hard to get the book noticed and criticised by the professional
economists of his day, and clearly wanted to engage them in debate.

In the letter to Kugelmann of 11 July 1868, he says:

“... it shows the depth of degradation reached by these priests of the
bourgeoisie: while workers and even manufacturers and merchants have
understood my book and made sense of it, these ‘learned scribes’ (!)
complain that I make excessive demands on their comprehension.”

And while he was most interested in getting it to workers, criticising
Lassalle for not working harder to encourage workers to read it, he
certainly aimed at taking his fight into the recognised scientific
circles. He believed (and with good reason) that his work engaged in a
meaningful way with mainstream economic theory; it did not live in a
parallel universe. Marx complained that he was being met with a
conspiracy of silence, but history shows that Capital did get the
recognition it deserved, and Capital haunts bourgeois economics to
this day, like the ghost of its dead father.

The point is that prices, profits, rents and so on are, in Marx’s
scheme of things, merely surface appearances, like the froth and
bubbles on the surface of the ocean, the forms of which tell us little
about the main business of tidal shifts and melting ice-packs. Marx
begins with the concept of bourgeois society and moves to more and
more concrete concepts, that is to say, he reconstructs the concrete,
the appearances, in scientific terms. In such an approach the effect
of a drought in Australia on mortgage rates in the US, and so on,
belong somewhere in Volume XX. They are not excluded, but it is the
dynamics of class relations which are fundamental and central.

So in summary, Capital remains an unfinished work and it seems
unlikely that the job of finishing it to the point where it could
provide a superior tool for management of government or corporate
economic affairs will ever be completed, were it to remain the work of
an isolated individual. Basically it is a practical task. With the
partial exception of Boltanski, the theoretical work of critiquing
political economy seems to have died with Marx. So far as I know, none
of the “Marxist Economists” have critiqued the theory of marginal
utility beyond denouncing it as an ideological apology aimed at
discrediting Marx and demobilizing the workers’ movement (all of which
may well be true, by the way). There have been a plethora of new
economic forms of activity since 1883. Marx never knew Taylorism,
which completely transformed work practices, the social division of
labour and the composition of the working class. He never knew
Fordism, which completely transformed the form of exploitation, the
concept of a living wage, and the nature of working-class communities;
he never knew the welfare state with its system of universal
state-provided benefits, or Toyota-ism and its appropriation of worker
cooperation for the benefit of capital, or the practices of
franchising, out-sourcing, the practice of part-time working, and the
export of manufacture to non-union industrial zones in far-off
countries, or the inflow of economic migrants to the former colonial
centres. All these represent transformations in political economy, not
anticipated in Capital.

Just one example: in Marx’s day, workers were basically locked in a
large building to work under their own supervision for as long as the
capitalist could force them to using the weapon of keeping wages at
near-starvation level. This way of thinking is directly reflected in
the categories of Capital because that’s how capital worked. But this
is no longer the case in the countries where capital predominates.

So those who read Capital to learn Marx’s “method” have a point. Even
some very fundamental features of Capital may no longer be relevant.
And what is more, it is fair to suppose that later development in the
activity of capital must, in some sense at least, come closer to the
essence, the truth of bourgeois society. The critic does not create
thought out of thought; theory can only reveal what is already present
in social practice. In the Grundrisse, Marx said:

“... Hegel fell into the illusion of conceiving the real as the
product of thought concentrating itself, probing its own depths, and
unfolding itself out of itself, by itself, ... in the theoretical
method, too, the subject, society, must always be kept in mind as the
presupposition.”

So the job of Marx’s continuers begins with the latest developments in
bourgeois society most especially insofar as the concrete sheds light
on the categories of current economic theory and vice versa. It seems
likely that such a continuing critique would continue to use the
concept of value at its foundation, if we are to be true to Marx.

In the letter to Kugelmann quoted above, in responding to a bourgeois
critic of Capital, he observes:

“The chatter about the need to prove the concept of value arises only
from complete ignorance both of the subject under discussion and of
the method of science. Every child knows that any nation that stopped
working, not for a year, but let us say, just for a few weeks, would
perish. And every child knows, too, that the amounts of products
corresponding to the differing amounts of needs demand differing and
quantitatively determined amounts of society’s aggregate labour. It is
self-evident that this necessity of the distribution of social labour
in specific proportions is certainly not abolished by the specific
form of social production; it can only change its form of
manifestation. Natural laws cannot be abolished at all. The only thing
that can change, under historically differing conditions, is the form
in which those laws assert themselves. And the form in which this
proportional distribution of labour asserts itself in a state of
society in which the interconnection of social labour expresses itself
as the private exchange of the individual products of labour, is
precisely the exchange value of these products. ...

“On the other hand, as you correctly believe, the history of the
theory of course demonstrates that the understanding of the value
relation has always been the same, clearer or less clear, hedged with
illusions or scientifically more precise. Since the reasoning process
itself arises from the existing conditions and is itself a natural
process, really comprehending thinking can always only be the same,
and can vary only gradually, in accordance with the maturity of
development, hence also the maturity of the organ that does the
thinking. Anything else is drivel.”

So what is involved is the transhistorical necessity of every society
making some arrangement or other for the distribution of the social
labour and its products. This is what is contained in the concept of
value. Implicit in the concept of value is the notion of the intrinsic
equality of human beings. In an emphatically world economy in which
capital based, for example, in the US, is manufacturing in India and
drastically underpaying labour, we have an instance of price being
less than value for long periods of time. But once ‘the great mass of
the produce of labour takes the form of commodities [and]
consequently, the dominant relation between man and man, is that of
owners of commodities’, there is a necessary tendency towards the
equalisation of wages, which nonetheless may take centuries of war and
revolution to exert itself.

There are dozens of such problems that arise as a result of changes in
the political economy of modern life, the solution of which are
presupposed in a continuation of Marx’s work.




--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

_______________________________________________
Marxism-Thaxis mailing list
Marxism-Thaxis@lists.econ.utah.edu
To change your options or unsubscribe go to:
http://lists.econ.utah.edu/mailman/listinfo/marxism-thaxis

Reply via email to