Andy Blunden September 2005

Foucault’s Discursive Subject (continued)


1. Knowledge
The epistemological problem of whether knowledge is entirely enclosed
by the paradigm or discourse within which it exists is one that has
received ample attention over the past century, and there is no need
to recapitulate that debate here. A recent example is the question as
to whether poverty exists and can be measured objectively or is on the
contrary simply a construct of the setting of the ‘poverty line’ in
welfare discourses. Foucault seemed on strong ground when he pointed
out that the very concept of ‘sex’ is constructed from a multiplicity
of pleasures, discourses, needs, and so on, and poverty researchers
would do well to learn from this: both poverty and the concept of
poverty are social constructs, differing in nature from one epoch or
culture to the next, so if they are to be objective and socially
relevant, measures of poverty must be constructed critically. It turns
out in fact that poverty is subject to objective measurement (life
expectancy, rates of psychiatric admissions, child abuse,
imprisonment, etc.), even though such measures only present themselves
as a result of a critique of the naïve/intuitive conception of poverty
based exclusively on income and monetary wealth. And the line which
asserts that on the contrary, the concept of poverty is simply a
linguistic construct leads to profoundly reactionary conclusions.

Natural science first took up this question on its own territory with
Charles Sanders Peirce’s conception of Pragmatism (1878) and Percy
Bridgman’s Operationalism (1927), culminating in Thomas Kuhn’s concept
of “paradigm” (1962). Ultimately however, the validity of a theory is
tested on the ground of ethics, that is to say, on the domain of a
whole form of life. This insight, which can be traced back to Hegel,
was first formulated within the discourse of natural science by
Jacques Monod, the 1965 Nobel Laureate for Biology. Critique of
knowledge can find a firm ground only in ethics, and this is something
that Foucault fails to provide.

How is knowledge constituted then? Knowledge is the knowledge of a
subject. The Cartesian conception of the subject as a thinking ego
came under attack centuries before M. Foucault came on the scene. An
individual with working nervous system and sense organs, can know
nothing; in addition to the nervous and sensori-motor systems with
which every human individual is endowed, knowledge presupposes that
the individual is participating in some collaborative activity,
engaging both systems, with other people, by means of which their
needs a met. Collaborative activity connects people with the entire
history of humanity through languages, symbols and images, artefacts,
not to mention the human bodies and sense organs shaped by many
generations of such activity. The knowledge a person has makes sense
to them only to the extent that it is connected with their active use
of their body in meeting human needs; but closer examination shows
that the specific content of that knowledge is formed not by the
individual themself but by the efforts of the individual to
collaborate with others using and modifying the ideal entities which
mediate their collaboration. The knowing subject therefore includes
not only the (socially constructed) nervous and sensori-motor systems
of the individual person, but also the concept and the material
products (including words and images) embodying that concept, used to
recognise and make sense of sense perceptions, and the system of human
relations and institutions, through which the concept is brought into
relation to the person.

Let me be clear here: it is not my contention that an individual
“uses” artefacts and other people in order to acquire knowledge. I am
saying that the knowing subject is a specific dynamic combination of
individuals, ideals and social collaboration. A “thought” unrelated to
any social action or meaningful artefact (word, symbol, etc.) would be
as absurd as a reflection without its object, the meaning of a
nonsense word, or a nation with no citizens.

Foucault directs his fire against the naïve/intuitive Cartesian
conception of knowledge, in support of an idea of knowledge
constituted by discourse; discourse is understood as the unity of an
ideal conceptual structure and a real set of power relations between
people. However, Foucault is seen not as describing a more concrete
conception of the subject, but rather as “deconstructing” the subject,
leaving us the absurdity of knowledge without a subject.

On the contrary, knowledge is knowledge of some subject, some needy
social agent.

2. Human Needs
As Marx said at length in the 1844 Manuscripts, “the forming of the
five senses is a labour of the entire history of the world down to the
present.”

“The eye has become a human eye, just as its object has become a
social, human object – an object made by man for man. The senses have
therefore become directly in their practice theoreticians.” [Private
Property and Communism, Marx 1844]

Both human capacities and human needs have been shaped by the
historical development of the social cooperation and the division of
labour. A person’s needs are not found in some inner personal world,
but on the contrary in the social world in which both their needs and
the means of their satisfaction are produced; and not just needs, but
a person’s entire identity is produced through their activity with
other people. The insight that the sense organs are the product of
social development, and can sense only what is socially meaningful
certainly undermines the idea of a sovereign individual subject, but
it does not undermine the concept of subjectivity as such. Discourse
shapes the sense organs, but equally, social relations acquire their
sense organs in human individuals. Human eyes and ears are the sense
organs of subjects, not of individual subjects, but of social
subjects, structured around a division of labour and the social
production of human life.

So Foucault is right when he argues that there is no such thing as a
pre-social ‘sex’ in the human organism, only a range of pleasures and
stimuli, arbitrarily bunched together under a concept of sexuality
which is a cultural-historical product; but it is equally evident that
there can be no sexuality without those pleasures and stimuli which
exist only in human bodies. It turns out that human needs are
immensely malleable, more malleable than seems imaginable at first,
but they remain, nevertheless, human needs.

“all the organs of his individual being [are] the appropriation of
human reality. Their orientation to the object is the manifestation of
the human reality, ... it is human activity and human suffering”
[Private Property and Communism, Marx 1844]

3. Agency
If it be granted that human knowledge and human needs are the labour
of social subjects actualised by individuals, and that knowledge and
needs are irreducibly the functions of real, individual, suffering
human beings, it may still be doubted that it is in any way sensible
to talk about individual agency.

“Freedom is the understanding of necessity” said Hegel; an individual
is free only to the extent that they can make an intelligent choice
between real possibilities, rather than being governed by ‘blind
necessity’. Hegel reserved real freedom for ‘world historic heroes’,
like Napoleon, who directly express the World Spirit in their lives.
Many who have rejected Hegel’s metaphysical conception of history
would still grant that the idea of self-determination, or sovereignty,
as applied to an individual is an absurdity. At the same time, most
frequently when people use the word ‘subject’ they mean precisely that
individual agent who is deemed, on the contrary to lack agency in any
real sense of the word. So it is here surely that Foucault’s critique
would seem to have the most purchase.

It is worthwhile to pause and clarify what is meant by
“self-determination.” Compare the definition given by Kant in his
original definition of the subject of moral philosophy and the
definition of sovereignty in the law of nations:

A person is a subject whose actions can be imputed to him. ... a
person is subject to no other laws than those he gives to himself,
either alone or at least along with others. (Kant, The Metaphysics of
Morals)

and

“sovereignty, the principle that each nation answers only to its own
domestic order and is not accountable to a larger international
community, save only to the extent that it has consented to do so.”
(Bederman, International Law Frameworks, p. 50)

The same parallelism is found in the “recognition” paradigm of sovereignty:

“the relations of free beings to one another is a relation of
reciprocal interaction throughintelligence and freedom. One cannot
recognise the other if both do not mutually recognise each other.”
(Fichte, Foundations of Natural Right, p. 42)

and

“an unspoken assumption in the criterion for statehood ... that other
nations are prepared to treat a particular entity as a member of the
family of nations.” (Bederman, International Law Frameworks, p. 54)

Thus we see that the concepts of sovereignty developed by the founders
of modern moral philosophy (Kant and Fichte) align with the concepts
of sovereignty still used in international law to this day. The
meaning of the concept in the context of the law of nations is
somewhat clearer than in the context of moral philosophy where the
writers we have quoted, pioneers of bourgeois ideology, proposed the
individual person as a sovereign subject. Clearly such a conception is
idealistic; the individual as a sovereign subject is something that
can only be imagined for a faraway future society: “... an association
in which the free development of each is the condition for the free
development of all.” [The Communist Manifesto, 1848] Nevertheless,
this conception of self-determination can serve as a norm against
which the meaning of ‘subject’ as a ‘free being’ (to use Fichte’s
terminology) can be measured.

An individual sees themself in the action of others, where that action
fulfils a person’s own aspirations and is the completion of the
person’s own actions; people make a ‘psychic investment’ (to use James
Coleman’s terminology) in other people. Thus we can see that
individuals even today can exercise self-determination, that is to say
‘agency’, in and through their relationships with others.
‘Self-determination’ does not and never did imply infinite negative
freedom, that is to say, to be able to determine one’s actions purely
and simply without regard to the freedom of others. Rather,
‘self-determination’ implies being subject only to laws which the
subject may be deemed to have set for themself, either alone or along
with others like oneself. Implicit in this concept are norms of
procedural fairness appropriate to subjects which recognise each other
as moral equals.

Thus an individual can enjoy self-determination to the extent that
they can freely invest themselves in the actions of social subjects
which enjoy self-determination in these terms.

A number of issues bear on the question as to whether it is possible
for individuals to enjoy self-determination through participation in
social subjectivity. These include (i) the presence of ‘discursive
heterogeneity’, that is, the presence of competing discourses which
give individuals the opportunity to take a critical stance in relation
to any given discourse before making a ‘psychic investment’ in it;
(ii) if we allow that companies, that is, subjects whose
self-determination is directly subject to the ‘laws of economics’ can
allow only qualified access to self-determination, then (iii) the
existence of relations of trust and solidarity between mutually
independent subjects, which offer opportunities for individuals to
participate in determining the conditions of their own lives, and (iv)
people in general have some measure of real control over the products
of their own labour.

As it happens, the past couple of decades have seen the growth of
social conditions in which the great mass of people are experiencing a
‘loss of agency’, as power becomes more and more concentrated in a
relatively small number of great corporations, subject to the “laws of
the market,” while all other forms of social collaboration are being
destroyed and society atomised. This is where our attention needs to
be focused. To theorise this as if subjectivity was only ever an
illusion, or even, as some do, paint ‘the subject’ as an essentially
oppressive entity anyway, only makes the situation worse.

What Foucault can help us with though is this: in the modern world it
is no longer plausible to conceptualise agency in terms of ‘social
subjects’, understood as mutually independent institutions,
organisations, social movements and so on. The notions of discourse
and interpellation into subject positions within a multiplicity of
narratives, actually give us a better approach to the conception of
subjectivity and self-determination. The kind of mechanical field
presupposed in both the above quotes defining the notion of
sovereignty, needs to be replaced with a field of interlocking
discourses in which each effects a kind of ‘matrix transformation’ on
relationships in the others. This is a complex task, but offers a way
forward.


--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

All quotes from Foucault refer to The History of Sexuality. An
Introduction. Volume I. Michel Foucault, translated by Robert Hurley,
Vintage Books 1990.

_______________________________________________
Marxism-Thaxis mailing list
Marxism-Thaxis@lists.econ.utah.edu
To change your options or unsubscribe go to:
http://lists.econ.utah.edu/mailman/listinfo/marxism-thaxis

Reply via email to