Re: [EM] The structuring of power and the composition of norms by communicative assent

2009-01-19 Thread Michael Allan
Juho Laatu wrote:

  If private and public opinions differ, then which is the
  manipulated one?
 
 If they deviate it is hard to imagine
 that the private opinion would not be
 the sincere one.

That's because you are thinking of individual opinion.  Consider:

  * private opinion informed by mass media, and likewise measured by
mass elections with a secret ballot

  * public opinion formed in mutual discussion, and likewise measured
by peer-to-peer voting with a public ballot

It makes a difference when people act socially (inter-subjectively)
amongst themselves, rather than alone.  When they act alone, they are
apt to be systematically manipulated as objects.  Alone they have
subjective truth (personal sincerity), but together they have
communicative reason (mutual understanding or consensus).

 I think the common practice is to force
 privacy on everyone in order to allow
 the weakest of the society to keep
 their privacy.

That's because you are thinking of an administrative context.  Force
is permitted in that context.  We can be restrained from choosing our
own voting methods, at the polling station.  We can be forced to use
the methods as provided, or to abstain from voting.

The public sphere is different.  There, people can choose their own
means of expression.  We cannot restrict them to a private voting
method, except by violating the principle of free speech.  And if that
didn't stop us, the law would.
 
 It is true that public votes help
 implementing some features, but in
 most typical (low level) elections
 privacy has been considered to be
 essential.

Privacy is essential, I agree, but it's insufficient.  The secret
ballot *does* work in state elections.  I don't mean it any
disrespect.  But it will work even better when it's complemented by a
public ballot in cross-party primaries.  (That's what I argue,
anyway.)

-- 
Michael Allan

Toronto, 647-436-4521
http://zelea.com/


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] The structuring of power and the composition of norms by communicative assent

2009-01-19 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Michael Allan wrote:

Juho Laatu wrote:


If private and public opinions differ, then which is the
manipulated one?

If they deviate it is hard to imagine
that the private opinion would not be
the sincere one.


That's because you are thinking of individual opinion.  Consider:

  * private opinion informed by mass media, and likewise measured by
mass elections with a secret ballot

  * public opinion formed in mutual discussion, and likewise measured
by peer-to-peer voting with a public ballot

It makes a difference when people act socially (inter-subjectively)
amongst themselves, rather than alone.  When they act alone, they are
apt to be systematically manipulated as objects.  Alone they have
subjective truth (personal sincerity), but together they have
communicative reason (mutual understanding or consensus).


Could not these domains work together? To my knowledge, that's what 
happens now. People discuss politics and find out what they're going to 
vote. Any sort of improvement on the availability of discussion, as well 
as of information of representatives' actions will help that domain. 
Then, when the voters actually decide to vote, they have privacy. Their 
opinions may change based on what they hear or discuss, but at the end, 
it's a private decision who they'll give their vote to.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Generalizing manipulability

2009-01-19 Thread Jonathan Lundell

On Jan 18, 2009, at 5:13 PM, Juho Laatu wrote:


--- On Mon, 19/1/09, Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com wrote:


- Why was the first set of definitions
not good enough for Approval? (I read
rank as referring to the sincere
personal opinions, not to the ballot.)


vi ranks, and vi is by definition the ballot.
That's why the second
definition introduces o.


OK. I should say that is the way I'd
like to read it.


I'd like to take another shot at that. Steve's first definition:


   Let X denote the set of alternatives being voted on.
   Let N denote the set of voters.

   Let V(X,N) denote the set of all possible collections of admissible
   votes regarding X, such that each collection contains one vote
   for each voter i in N.  For all collections v in V(X,N) and all
   voters i in N, let vi denote i's vote in v.

   Let C denote the vote-tallying function that chooses the winner
   given a collection of votes. That is, for all v in V(X,N), C(v) is
   some alternative in X.

   Call C manipulable by voter strategy if there exist two  
collections

   of votes v,v' in V(X,N) and some voter i in N such that both of
   the following conditions hold:
1.  v'j = vj for all voters j in N-i.
2.  vi ranks C(v') over C(v).

The idea in condition 2 is that voter i prefers the winner given the  
strategic vote v'i over the winner given the sincere vote vi.


This definition is stronger than *requiring* that vi be any particular  
ordering--in particular i's sincere preferences. That's very neat.


Notice also that we get away with it because the ballot in this case  
is expressive enough to represent i's sincere preference ranking.  
That's not true for an approval ballot, which is why the second  
definition needs to introduce a separate preference order o.


Finally, the definition says nothing about how voter i might go about  
*finding* v'i, or even how to discover for any particular ballot  
profile whether v'i exists. 


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Condorcet - let's move ahead

2009-01-19 Thread Markus Schulze
Dear Kristofer Munsterhjelm,

you wrote (19 Jan 2009):

 So voters prefer MAM winners to Beatpath winners
 more often than vice versa. What method is the
 best in that respect?

Copeland methods are the best methods in this
respect.

The fact, that the ranked pairs winner usually
pairwise beats the Schulze winner in random
simulations, is a direct consequence of the facts,
that the Schulze winner is usually identical
to the MinMax winner and that the MinMax winner
usually has a very low Copeland score (compared
to the winners of other Condorcet methods).

Markus Schulze



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV and Brown vs. Smallwood

2009-01-19 Thread Terry Bouricius
FYI,

FairVote Minnesota does not and never has had any legal connection to 
the national organization known as FairVote (though they obviously 
communicate and are collegial). The views of Tony Solgard are his, and not 
FairVote's. FairVote does not argue that Condorcet methods would violate 
the federal constitution, and would likely defend their constitutionality. 
I don't believe Tony Solgard has argued there is any problem with 
Condorcet methods with regards to the federal constitution either.

Terry Bouricius

- Original Message - 
From: Markus Schulze markus.schu...@alumni.tu-berlin.de
To: election-meth...@electorama.com
Sent: Sunday, January 18, 2009 11:52 PM
Subject: Re: [EM] IRV and Brown vs. Smallwood


Dear Terry Bouricius,

you wrote (18 Jan 2009):

 FairVote is not responsible for reports by
 the League of Women Voters or lawyers writing
 scholarly articles.

Tony Solgard was president of FairVote Minnesota
when he wrote the quoted article in which he claims
that Condorcet was unconstitutional in Minnesota.

Also the report by the League of Women Voters of
Minnesota refers to him as Tony Solgard, President
of Board of FairVote Minnesota.

Markus Schulze



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] The structuring of power and the composition of norms by communicative assent

2009-01-19 Thread Michael Allan
Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

 Could not these domains work together? To my knowledge, that's what happens 
 now. People discuss politics and find out what they're going to vote. Any 
 sort of improvement on the availability of discussion, as well as of 
 information of representatives' actions will help that domain. Then, when 
 the voters actually decide to vote, they have privacy. Their opinions may 
 change based on what they hear or discuss, but at the end, it's a private 
 decision who they'll give their vote to.

I was thinking along the same lines, replying to your previous post!
Here it is:

Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote (previously):

 You may put it that way, but I think that goes the other direction as well: 
 if it is true that distortions (by carrot or by stick, e.g vote-buying or 
 coercion) degrade the public sphere so that one have to use a secret ballot 
 in ordinary elections, then the distortions will remain when using a method 
 that relies on public sphere information (that is, what you call 
 communicative assent), yet the means of masking that distortion no longer 
 applies, because it's no longer a private matter of voting, but a public 
 one of discussion.

 Or to phrase it in another way: the distortions of action can be called 
 corruption, since this is really what happens when you're letting the 
 distortions govern how you act when you're supposed to be acting either in 
 accordance to your own opinion, or as an agent of someone else. For obvious 
 reasons, we don't want corruption, and we would seek to minimize it, but 
 it's still a problem.

Consider all three types of voting system, the two existing, and the
third proposed:

  TABLE 1.  SYSTEMATIC CORRUPTION OF VOTERS
  --
  Voting System   IndividualCollective
  --    

  State   --manipulation by mass
  Electoral propaganda, financed by
campaign contributions,
or by influence peddling

  State   Party discipline, --
  Legislative the whipping system

  Vote buying, influence
  peddling

  Public Primary  Social pressure from  --
  (Electoral and  employer, school,
   Legislative)   church, union, etc. *

  Vote buying, influence
  peddling

  -
   * family pressure is more nature-like than systematic, so
 consider it separately

 The secret ballot came into use to protect voters from the distortion. 
 Presumably the distortion was real and sufficiently severe to need such 
 measures. If we remove the protection, the distortion will again be 
 uncovered. It may be a problem with society, or with the method, but it'll 
 be there, whatever the cause.

That protection will not be removed.  No changes to the existing
voting systems are proposed.  On the other hand, we cannot extend the
same protection to the public system, not even partially.  To enforce
a secret ballot would violate the guarantees of free speech in the
public sphere.  Ad hoc, people can make public voting a fact.

We can take any of the corruptions (Table 1), and investigate it in
detail.  That's one approach.  Another (as suggested in your other
post) is to consider how the two categories of system (state and
public) will interact.  There could be a positive synergy between
them, with the corruptions of the state being weakened by the public
system, while those of the public system are filtered out by the
state's secret ballot.  I would argue this is generally true, for all
of the corruptions listed in the table.

 The vote-buying effort would, of course, be a this-for-that endeavor. I 
 provide money, you provide the vote - I buy your vote. After you've 
 voted, I got what I bought, and I may buy another vote later.

 Alternately, it can be continual: for as long as you, as a proxy, mirror 
 me, I'll pay you. Stop doing it and I stop paying.

 In both cases, the vote is the commodity.

Only the latter case would apply, as the commodity is continuous.
There is a single vote on the table, and the voter can shift it around
or withdraw it, at any time.  So the payments must be meted out
continually in nickles and dimes (as you suggest), or deferred.  These
types of payment will be less attractive to typical vote sellers.
They won't be banking their returns, but spending them immediately.

In addition to this, and the other factors (i to iv) that weigh
against vote buying, I would add:

  v) Vote sellers may be identified by pattern analysis, and simple
 record keeping.  Once identified and marked with a probability
 label, their collective behaviour may be tracked.  The tracks
 will lead to the vote buyers.

Re: [EM] IRV and Brown vs. Smallwood

2009-01-19 Thread Kathy Dopp
 From: Markus Schulze markus.schu...@alumni.tu-berlin.de
 Subject: Re: [EM] IRV and Brown vs. Smallwood

 Tony Solgard was president of FairVote Minnesota
 when he wrote the quoted article in which he claims
 that Condorcet was unconstitutional in Minnesota.

 Also the report by the League of Women Voters of
 Minnesota refers to him as Tony Solgard, President
 of Board of FairVote Minnesota.

Markus,

I decided to read the LWV, MN report and it is rife with mistatements
of fact and almost seems like it was written by Tony Solgard himself.
Apparently the LWV, MN did not try out any different examples
themselves that would have tested the false statements that were being
fed to them by Fair Vote, MN and so merely repeated the lies and
included the limited examples that backed up the lies about IRV/STV.

Sad that the LWV, MN did not think to try out diverse examples so that
they can see that in examples that correspond more closely to
real-life elections, that IRV/STV does *not* find majority winners or
solve the spoiler problem and causes a host of new problems.   Fair
Vote is truly one the most-skilled organizations at misleading the
public that exists today.

IRV/STV is essentially a sequence of plurality elections where ballots
are treated arbitrarily unequally where voters are involuntarily
excluded from participating in subsequent rounds even if they fully
fill out the ballot whenever the number of candidates exceeds the
number of ballot positions plus the number of positions to be filled.
The unequal treatment of ballots in IRV/STV causes non-monotonicity,
and a host of other undesirable, unfair outcomes.  And if all that is
not bad enough, IRV/STV eviscerates the public oversight and
transparency of elections due to its being not precinct-summable and
of exponential difficulty to hand count or to audit.

That anyone would suggest that anyone should use such an inane voting
method as IRV/STV is beyond my understanding - except if they are
trying to help voting machine vendors profit by selling an all-new
round of high-tech voting machines or if they are trying to implement
a voting method that makes it much more difficult to detect vote fraud
when it occurs.

Cheers,

Kathy

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] The structuring of power and the composition of norms by communicative assent

2009-01-19 Thread Juho Laatu
--- On Mon, 19/1/09, Michael Allan m...@zelea.com wrote:

 Juho Laatu wrote:
 
   If private and public opinions differ, then which
 is the
   manipulated one?
  
  If they deviate it is hard to imagine
  that the private opinion would not be
  the sincere one.
 
 That's because you are thinking of individual opinion. 
 Consider:
 
   * private opinion informed by mass media, and likewise
 measured by
 mass elections with a secret ballot
 
   * public opinion formed in mutual discussion, and
 likewise measured
 by peer-to-peer voting with a public ballot
 
 It makes a difference when people act socially
 (inter-subjectively)
 amongst themselves, rather than alone.  When they act
 alone, they are
 apt to be systematically manipulated as objects.  Alone
 they have
 subjective truth (personal sincerity), but together they
 have
 communicative reason (mutual understanding or consensus).

I see two valid ways to form opinions.
- opinion formation based on mass media
- opinion formation based on mutual discussion

Individuals may use one or both
approaches when forming their private
opinion, and also when forming their
public opinion (public ballot or
other public expression of their
opinion).

 
  I think the common practice is to force
  privacy on everyone in order to allow
  the weakest of the society to keep
  their privacy.
 
 That's because you are thinking of an administrative
 context.  Force
 is permitted in that context.  We can be restrained from
 choosing our
 own voting methods, at the polling station.  We can be
 forced to use
 the methods as provided, or to abstain from voting.
 
 The public sphere is different.  There, people can choose
 their own
 means of expression.  We cannot restrict them to a private
 voting
 method, except by violating the principle of free speech. 
 And if that
 didn't stop us, the law would.

I don't see any big conflict. They are
free to speak even if the society does
not provide them with tools to prove
to others how they voted. (And they
can still tell others how they voted.)

Juho


  
  It is true that public votes help
  implementing some features, but in
  most typical (low level) elections
  privacy has been considered to be
  essential.
 
 Privacy is essential, I agree, but it's insufficient. 
 The secret
 ballot *does* work in state elections.  I don't mean it
 any
 disrespect.  But it will work even better when it's
 complemented by a
 public ballot in cross-party primaries.  (That's what I
 argue,
 anyway.)
 
 -- 
 Michael Allan
 
 Toronto, 647-436-4521
 http://zelea.com/
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see
 http://electorama.com/em for list info


  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Generalizing manipulability

2009-01-19 Thread Juho Laatu
--- On Mon, 19/1/09, Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com wrote:

 On Jan 18, 2009, at 5:13 PM, Juho Laatu wrote:
 
  --- On Mon, 19/1/09, Jonathan Lundell
 jlund...@pobox.com wrote:
  
  - Why was the first set of definitions
  not good enough for Approval? (I read
  rank as referring to the sincere
  personal opinions, not to the ballot.)
  
  vi ranks, and vi is by definition the
 ballot.
  That's why the second
  definition introduces o.
  
  OK. I should say that is the way I'd
  like to read it.
 
 I'd like to take another shot at that. Steve's
 first definition:
 
 Let X denote the set of alternatives being voted
 on.
 Let N denote the set of voters.
  
 Let V(X,N) denote the set of all possible
 collections of admissible
 votes regarding X, such that each collection
 contains one vote
 for each voter i in N.  For all collections v in
 V(X,N) and all
 voters i in N, let vi denote i's vote in v.
  
 Let C denote the vote-tallying function that
 chooses the winner
 given a collection of votes. That is, for all v in
 V(X,N), C(v) is
 some alternative in X.
  
 Call C manipulable by voter strategy if
 there exist two collections
 of votes v,v' in V(X,N) and some voter i in N
 such that both of
 the following conditions hold:
  1.  v'j = vj for all voters j in N-i.
  2.  vi ranks C(v') over C(v).
  
  The idea in condition 2 is that voter i prefers the
 winner given the strategic vote v'i over the winner
 given the sincere vote vi.
 
 This definition is stronger than *requiring* that vi be any
 particular ordering--in particular i's sincere
 preferences. That's very neat.
 
 Notice also that we get away with it because the ballot in
 this case is expressive enough to represent i's sincere
 preference ranking. That's not true for an approval
 ballot, which is why the second definition needs to
 introduce a separate preference order o.
 
 Finally, the definition says nothing about how voter i
 might go about *finding* v'i, or even how to discover
 for any particular ballot profile whether v'i exists.

Yes, this is neat in the sense that
there is no need to explain what the
sincere opinion of the voter is and
how the strategic vote will be found.

A definition that would cover also
Approval and other methods with
simple ballots at one go would be
nice too.

Although it is sometimes difficult
to say what a sincere vote in
Approval is (could be e.g. to mark
all candidates that one approves) I
think it is quite natural to assume
that each voter has some preferences
(order), and that strategies mean
deviation from simply voting as one
feels and not considering the
technical details of the method, the
impact of how others are expected to
vote and how one could get better
results out (by e.g. voting or
nominating candidates in some
particular way).

Juho





  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Generalizing manipulability

2009-01-19 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 01:38 AM 1/18/2009, Juho Laatu wrote:

I don't quite see why ranking based
methods (Range, Approval) would not
follow the same principles/definitions
as rating based methods. The sincere
message of the voter was above that she
only slightly prefers B over A but the
strategic vote indicated that she finds
B to be maximally better than A (or
that in order to make B win she better
vote this way).


That is an *interpretation* of a Range vote. In fact, they are just 
votes, and the voter casts them according to the voter's 
understanding of what's best. This has been part of my point: Range 
votes don't indicate preference strength, as such. Consider 
Approval, which is a Range method. If the voter votes A=BC=D, what 
does this tell us? We can infer some preferences from it, to be sure, 
and those preferences are probably accurate, because Approval never 
rewards a truly insincere vote. But does this vote indicate that 
the voter has no preference between A and B, nor between C and D? Of 
course not!


Now, a Range vote. But the voter votes Approval style. What does this 
tell us about the voter preferences? *Nothing more and nothing less.* 
The voter chose to vote that way for what reason? We don't know!!!


They are votes, not sentiments. Voters may choose to express relative 
preference, in Range, with some fineness of expression, but they may 
also choose not to make refined expressions, and all these votes are 
sincere, i.e., they imply no preferences that we cannot reasonably 
infer from them with a general understanding that the voter had no 
incentive to show preferences opposite to the actual.


(Now, there is a kind of insincere voting that voters may engage in, 
but it isn't really rewarded, and voters will only do it when they 
expect it to be moot. And they may do this kind of insincere voting 
with any method whatever.)



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Generalizing manipulability

2009-01-19 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 03:57 PM 1/18/2009, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

Wouldn't it be stricter than this? Consider Range, for instance. One 
would guess that the best zero info strategy is to vote Approval 
style with the cutoff at some point (mean? not sure).


Actually, that's a lousy strategy. The reason it's lousy is that the 
voter is a sample of the electorate. Depending on the voter's own 
understanding of the electorate, and the voter's own relationship 
with the electorate, the best strategy might be a bullet vote. Saari 
showed why mean cutoff is terrible Approval strategy. What if every 
voter agrees with you but one? The one good thing Saari shows is that 
this yields a mediocre outcome when /1 voters prefer a 
candidate, but also approve another above the mean.


Essentially, the voter doesn't need to know anything specific about 
the electorate in a particular election, but only about how isolated 
the voter's position *generally* is.


For most voters, zero-knowledge indicates a bullet vote unless there 
are additional candidates with only weak preference under the 
most-preferred one, such that the voter truly doesn't mind voting for 
one or more of them in addition.


 However, it would also be reasonable that a sincere ratings ballot 
would have the property that if the sincere ranked ballot of the 
person in question is A  B, then the score of B is lower than that 
of A; that is, unless the rounding effect makes it impossible to 
give B a lower score than A, or makes it impossible to give B a 
sufficiently slightly lower score than A as the voter considers 
sincere (by whatever metric).


Yes. Indeed, I've suggested that doing pairwise analysis on Range 
ballots, with a runoff when the Range winner is beaten by a candidate 
pairwise, would encourage maintenance of this preference order.


Think of Range as a Borda ballot with equal ranking allowed and 
therefore with empty ranks. (Not the ridiculous suggestions that 
truncated ballots should be given less weight). If a voter really has 
weak preference between two candidates, the obvious and simple vote 
is to equal rank them. But then where does one put the empty rank?


There are two approaches, and both of them are sincere, though one 
approach more accurately reflects relative preference strength. There 
are ways to encourage that expression.


But here is the real problem: trying to think that a zero-knowledge 
ballot is somehow ideal is discounting the function of compromise in 
elections. That is, what we do in elections is *not only* to find 
some sort of supposed best candidate, but also to find compromises. 
That's what we do in deliberative process where repeated Yes/No 
voting is used to identify compromises, until a quorum is reached 
(usually a majority, but it can be supermajority). Deliberative 
process incorporates increasing knowledge by the electorate of 
itself. It extracts this with a series of elections in which 
sincerity is not only expected, it's generally good strategy. In that 
context, approval really is approval! If a majority agrees with 
your approval, the process is over.


I consider election methods as shortcuts, attempts to discover 
quickly what the electorate would likely settle on in a deliberative 
environment. As such, it is actually essential that whatever 
knowledge the electorate has of itself be incorporated into how the 
voters vote.


And that's what happens if, in a Range election, voters vote von 
Nuemann-Morganstern utilities. They have one full vote to bet. They 
put their vote where they think it will do the most good. They can 
put it all on one candidate, i.e., bullet vote. They can put it on a 
candidate set, thus voting a full vote for every member of the set 
over every nonmembe, i.e., they vote Approval style. They can split 
up their vote in more complex ways. What they can't do in this setup 
is to bet more than one vote. I.e., for example, one full vote for A 
over B, and one full vote for B over C. If we arrange their votes in 
sequence, from least preferred to most, the sum of votes in each 
sequential pairwise election must total to no more than one vote.


Calling them VNM utilities sounds complex, but it's actually 
instinctive. If we understand Range, we aren't going to waste 
significant voting power expressing moot preferences. Suppose someone 
asks you what you want. But you understand that you might not get 
what you want. You prefer ABCD, lets say with equal preference 
steps. You think it likely that A or B might be acceptable to your 
questioner, but not C or D. You have so much time to convince your 
questioner to give you what you argue for. How much time are you 
going to spend trying to convince the person to give you C instead of D?


You might mention it, but you wouldn't put the weight there unless 
you thought that the real possibilities were C or D.


Voter knowledge of the electorate is how elections reach compromise, 
and it's very important. Of course, there is