Re: [EM] Record activity on the EM list?

2011-08-04 Thread Juho Laatu
Yes, there are areas where single-winner methods are more challenging. For 
example multi-winner STV works better than single-winner STV, and it is easier 
to collect sincere ratings in multi-winner methods than in single-winner 
methods. On the other hand the field of study may be wider in multi-winenr 
methods (a bit like N is more complicated than 1). In multi-winner methods we 
may have some additional aspects to study and solve like proportionality, 
geographical proportionality and the computational complexity related problems 
tend to cause problems. Individual problems may thus be more numerous in 
multi-winner methods although some individual problems may be more challenging 
in single-winner methods.

Juho



On 3.8.2011, at 19.35, James Gilmour wrote:

 Juho Laatu   Sent: Wednesday, August 03, 2011 6:04 AM
 Multi-winner methods are, if possible, even more complicated 
 than single-winner methods. 
 
 I disagree.  It is much easier to obtain a satisfactory (representative, 
 acceptable) outcome for a multi-winner election than it
 is to obtain a satisfactory (representative, acceptable) outcome for a 
 single-winner election.  Choosing a method to elect the
 candidate who best represents the voters in a single-winner election is the 
 most difficult challenge in electoral science.  As soon
 as you elect two or more candidates together, many of the problems disappear.
 
 James Gilmour
 
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Record activity on the EM list?

2011-08-04 Thread James Gilmour
There is only one real issue in elections: representation of the voters.

If in a single winner partisan election the voters vote 51% for A and 49% for 
B, we have a major problem in representation.

But if the voters vote in the same way (51% to 49%) in a two-member election, 
any sensible voting system will give one seat to A and
one seat to B.

Compared to that difference in providing representation of the voters, all 
the other differences between single-winner and
multi-winner elections are trivial.

James

 -Original Message-
 From: election-methods-boun...@lists.electorama.com 
 [mailto:election-methods-boun...@lists.electorama.com] On 
 Behalf Of Juho Laatu
 Sent: Thursday, August 04, 2011 7:07 AM
 To: EM list
 Subject: Re: [EM] Record activity on the EM list?
 
 
 Yes, there are areas where single-winner methods are more 
 challenging. For example multi-winner STV works better than 
 single-winner STV, and it is easier to collect sincere 
 ratings in multi-winner methods than in single-winner 
 methods. On the other hand the field of study may be wider in 
 multi-winenr methods (a bit like N is more complicated than 
 1). In multi-winner methods we may have some additional 
 aspects to study and solve like proportionality, geographical 
 proportionality and the computational complexity related 
 problems tend to cause problems. Individual problems may thus 
 be more numerous in multi-winner methods although some 
 individual problems may be more challenging in single-winner methods.
 
 Juho
 
 
 
 On 3.8.2011, at 19.35, James Gilmour wrote:
 
  Juho Laatu   Sent: Wednesday, August 03, 2011 6:04 AM
  Multi-winner methods are, if possible, even more complicated
  than single-winner methods. 
  
  I disagree.  It is much easier to obtain a satisfactory 
  (representative, acceptable) outcome for a multi-winner 
 election than 
  it is to obtain a satisfactory (representative, 
 acceptable) outcome 
  for a single-winner election.  Choosing a method to elect the 
  candidate who best represents the voters in a single-winner 
 election 
  is the most difficult challenge in electoral science.  As 
 soon as you 
  elect two or more candidates together, many of the problems 
 disappear.
  
  James Gilmour
  
  
  
  Election-Methods mailing list - see 
 http://electorama.com/em for list 
  info
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em 
 for list info
 


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA and the Condorcet criterion

2011-08-04 Thread Jameson Quinn
Here's the new text on the SODA
pagehttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approval#Criteria_Compliancerelating
to the Condorcet criterion:

It fails the Condorcet
criterionhttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/Condorcet_criterion,
although the majority Condorcet winner over the ranking-augmented ballots is
the unique strong, subgame-perfect equilibrium winner. That is to say that,
the method would in fact pass the *majority* Condorcet winner criterion,
assuming the following:

   - *Candidates are honest* in their pre-election rankings. This could be
   because they are innately unwilling to be dishonest, because they are unable
   to calculate a useful dishonest strategy, or, most likely, because they fear
   dishonesty would lose them delegated votes. That is, voters who disagreed
   with the dishonest rankings might vote approval-style instead of delegating,
   and voters who perceived the rankings as dishonest might thereby value the
   candidate less.
   - *Candidates are rationally strategic* in assigning their delegated
   vote. Since the assignments are sequential, game theory states that there is
   always a subgame-perfect Nash equilibrium, which is always unique except in
   some cases of tied preferences.
   - *Voters* are able to use the system to *express all relevant
   preferences*. That is to say, all voters fall into one of two groups:
   those who agree with their favored candidate's declared preference order and
   thus can fully express that by delegating their vote; or those who disagree
   with their favored candidate's preferences, but are aware of who the
   Condorcet winner is, and are able to use the approval-style ballot to
   express their preference between the CW and all second-place candidates.
   Second place means the Smith set if the Condorcet winner were removed from
   the election; thus, for this assumption to hold, each voter must prefer the
   CW to all members of this second-place Smith set or vice versa. That's
   obviously always true if there is a single second-place CW.

The three assumptions above would probably not strictly hold true in a
real-life election, but they usually would be close enough to ensure that
the system does elect the CW.

SODA does even better than this if there are only 3 candidates, or if the
Condorcet winner goes first in the delegation assignment order, or if there
are 4 candidates and the CW goes second. In any of those circumstances,
under the assumptions above, it passes the *Condorcet* criterion, not just
the majority Condorcet criterion. The important difference between the
Condorcet criterion (beats all others pairwise) and the majority Condorcet
criterion (beats all others pairwise by a strict majority) is that the
former is clone-proof while the latter is not. Thus, with few enough strong
candidates, SODA also passes the independence of clones
criterionhttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/index.php?title=Independence_of_clones_criterionaction=editredlink=1
.

Note that, although the circumstances where SODA passes the Condorcet
criterion are hemmed in by assumptions, when it does pass, it does so in a
perfectly strategy-proof sense. That is *not* true of any actual Condorcet
system (that is, any system which universally passes the Condorcet
criterion). Therefore, for rationally-strategic voters who believe that the
above assumptions are likely to hold, *SODA may in fact pass the Condorcet
criterion more often than a Condorcet system*.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] A DSV method inspired by SODA

2011-08-04 Thread Jameson Quinn
I suspect that SODA would be Condorcet compliant (over ballots) if the first
player was, not the DSC winner, but the DAC winner (re-ordering between each
delegated assignment).

I'll see if I can work up a proof on this.

JQ

2011/7/30 fsimm...@pcc.edu

 One of the features of SODA is a step where the candidates decide what
 their approval cutoffs will be.on
 behalf of themselves and the voters for whom they are acting as proxies.
  One of the many novel features
 is that instead of making these decisions simultaneously, the candidates
 make them sequentially with
 full knowledge of the decisions of the candidates preceding them in the
 sequence.

 I wonder if anybody has ever tried a DSV (designated strategy voting)
 method based on these ideas.

 Here's one way it could go:

 Voters submit range ballots.

 Factions are amalgamated via weighted averages, so that each candidate ends
 up with one faction that
 counts according to its total weight. For large electorates, these faction
 scores will almost surely yield
 complete rankings of the candidates.

 From this point on, only these rankings will be used.  The ratings were
 only needed for the purpose of
 amalgamating the factions.  If we had started with rankings, we could have
 converted them to ratings via
 the method of my recent post under the subject Borda Done Right.  In
 either case, once we have the
 rankings from the amalgamated factions we proceed as follows:

 Based on these rankings the DSC (descending solid coalitions) winner D is
 found.  The D faction ranking
 determines the sequential order of play.  When it is candidate X's turn in
 the order of play, X's approval
 cutoff decision is made automatically as follows:

 For each of the possible cutoffs, the winner is determined recursively (by
 running through the rest of the
 DSV tentatively).  The cutoff that yields the best (i.e. highest ranked)
 candidate according to X's faction's
 ranking, is the cutoff that is applied to X's faction.

 After all of the cutoffs have been applied, the approval winner (based on
 those cutoffs) is elected.

 It would be too good to be true if this method turned out to be monotone.
  For that to be true moving up
 one position in the sequence of play could not hurt the winner.  Although I
 think that this is probably
 usually true, I don't think that it is always true.  Anybody know any
 different?
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] A DSV method inspired by SODA

2011-08-04 Thread fsimmons
Of course DSC and DAC are the same when rankings are complete.  I was only 
going to use it to determine the first player, and with amalgamated factions 
(almost surely) the rankings would be complete.

Of course there are many variations of this DSV idea [e.g. we could use 
chiastic approval to pick the first player], but the main contribution of SODA 
is the idea of sequential determination of the approval cutoffs.  That 
eliminates the need for mixed (i.e. probabilistic) strategies.  In other words, 
it makes the DSV method deterministic instead of stochastic.  I think a 
deterministic DSV method is easier to sell than a stochastic one, even though 
personally I would be happy with strategy A applied to the ballots one by one 
in some random order.  In other words, the approval cutoff on the current 
ballot is next to the current approval winner on the side of the approval 
runnerup.  If there is no CW, then the winner depends on the random order of 
the ballot processing.  The public might have a hard time with that fact.

- Original Message -
From: Jameson Quinn 
Date: Thursday, August 4, 2011 7:41 am
Subject: Re: [EM] A DSV method inspired by SODA
To: fsimm...@pcc.edu
Cc: election-methods@lists.electorama.com

 I suspect that SODA would be Condorcet compliant (over ballots) 
 if the first
 player was, not the DSC winner, but the DAC winner (re-ordering 
 between each
 delegated assignment).
 
 I'll see if I can work up a proof on this.
 
 JQ
 
 2011/7/30 
 
  One of the features of SODA is a step where the candidates 
 decide what
  their approval cutoffs will be.on
  behalf of themselves and the voters for whom they are acting 
 as proxies.
  One of the many novel features
  is that instead of making these decisions simultaneously, the 
 candidates make them sequentially with
  full knowledge of the decisions of the candidates preceding 
 them in the
  sequence.
 
  I wonder if anybody has ever tried a DSV (designated strategy 
 voting) method based on these ideas.
 
  Here's one way it could go:
 
  Voters submit range ballots.
 
  Factions are amalgamated via weighted averages, so that each 
 candidate ends
  up with one faction that
  counts according to its total weight. For large electorates, 
 these faction
  scores will almost surely yield
  complete rankings of the candidates.
 
  From this point on, only these rankings will be used. The 
 ratings were
  only needed for the purpose of
  amalgamating the factions. If we had started with rankings, 
 we could have
  converted them to ratings via
  the method of my recent post under the subject Borda Done 
 Right. In
  either case, once we have the
  rankings from the amalgamated factions we proceed as follows:
 
  Based on these rankings the DSC (descending solid coalitions) 
 winner D is
  found. The D faction ranking
  determines the sequential order of play. When it is candidate 
 X's turn in
  the order of play, X's approval
  cutoff decision is made automatically as follows:
 
  For each of the possible cutoffs, the winner is determined 
 recursively (by
  running through the rest of the
  DSV tentatively). The cutoff that yields the best (i.e. 
 highest ranked)
  candidate according to X's faction's
  ranking, is the cutoff that is applied to X's faction.
 
  After all of the cutoffs have been applied, the approval 
 winner (based on
  those cutoffs) is elected.
 
  It would be too good to be true if this method turned out to 
 be monotone.
  For that to be true moving up
  one position in the sequence of play could not hurt the 
 winner. Although I
  think that this is probably
  usually true, I don't think that it is always true. Anybody 
 know any
  different?
  
  Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em 
 for list info
 
 

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] A DSV method inspired by SODA

2011-08-04 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/8/4 fsimm...@pcc.edu

 Of course DSC and DAC are the same when rankings are complete.  I was only
 going to use it to determine the first player, and with amalgamated factions
 (almost surely) the rankings would be complete.


Yes, understood. I on the other hand was speaking of using this within SODA
itself, not within your SODA-inspired method. In SODA, tied candidate
preferences are legal.

I'd call the resulting method SODA-DAC. Plain SODA still uses the order
based on current approval total, for simplicity. The results are equivalent
for up to 3 candidates, and generally speaking as long as the CW makes a
strong initial showing (goes first, or goes second of 4, or )



 Of course there are many variations of this DSV idea [e.g. we could use
 chiastic approval to pick the first player], but the main contribution of
 SODA is the idea of sequential determination of the approval cutoffs.  That
 eliminates the need for mixed (i.e. probabilistic) strategies.  In other
 words, it makes the DSV method deterministic instead of stochastic.


Again, understood.


   I think a deterministic DSV method is easier to sell than a stochastic
 one, even though personally I would be happy with strategy A applied to
 the ballots one by one in some random order.  In other words, the approval
 cutoff on the current ballot is next to the current approval winner on the
 side of the approval runnerup.  If there is no CW, then the winner depends
 on the random order of the ballot processing.  The public might have a hard
 time with that fact.


I agree. In particular, even I might have a hard time, if there weren't at
least a deterministic pseudorandom number generator with a pre-declared
seed. Even then, this process would be much more difficult to audit /
recount than a deterministic one. So I agree that the player-order idea for
making things deterministic is helpful.

JQ

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Amalgamation details, hijacking, and free-riding

2011-08-04 Thread fsimmons


- Original Message -
From: Jameson Quinn 
Date: Wednesday, August 3, 2011 4:10 pm
Subject: Re: Amalgamation details, hijacking, and free-riding
To: fsimm...@pcc.edu
Cc: election-methods@lists.electorama.com

 2011/8/3 
 
  So if the true preferences are
 
  20 AB
  45 C?
  35 (something else),
 
  the C supporters could spare 21 voters to vote AC so that the 
 amalgamated factions would become
 
  41 AC
  24 C?
  35 (something else) .
 
  I can see where it is possible for such a move to payoff, but 
 it seems
  fairly innocuos compared to other
  strategy problems like burial, compromising, chicken, etc.
 
 
 Not to me. I would be livid to find out my vote had been 
 hijacked. All the
 other strategies you mention at least use a voter's own vote.
 

Highjacking sounds bad, but it is just one form of over-riding votes.  At 
least it doesn't over-ride your 
first place preference like the compromising incentive twists your arm to do.  
Every method eventually 
over-rides various preferences at some point in the process.  Compromising is a 
form of extortion that 
blackmails you into expressing a false preference. That's the most egregious 
form.
 
In other words, compromising forces you to either lie or lose.  If somebody 
else highjacks, they lie to 
take advantage of you, but with much more risk than the liar who buries to take 
advantage of the CW 
supporters.
 
For this kind of highjacking to work, the highjacking faction would have to 
have more than three times the 
support of  the highjacked faction, as can be seen from the above example 
(which lacking that much 
support in the hijacking faction gives an obvious first place advantage to A).  
That kind of superiority is 
more than enough to over-ride pairwise wins in ranked pairs, river, beatpath, 
etc.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Amalgamation details, hijacking, and free-riding

2011-08-04 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/8/4 fsimm...@pcc.edu



 - Original Message -
 From: Jameson Quinn
 Date: Wednesday, August 3, 2011 4:10 pm
 Subject: Re: Amalgamation details, hijacking, and free-riding
 To: fsimm...@pcc.edu
 Cc: election-methods@lists.electorama.com

  2011/8/3
 
   So if the true preferences are
  
   20 AB
   45 C?
   35 (something else),
  
   the C supporters could spare 21 voters to vote AC so that the
  amalgamated factions would become
  
   41 AC
   24 C?
   35 (something else) .
  
   I can see where it is possible for such a move to payoff, but
  it seems
   fairly innocuos compared to other
   strategy problems like burial, compromising, chicken, etc.
  
 
  Not to me. I would be livid to find out my vote had been
  hijacked. All the
  other strategies you mention at least use a voter's own vote.
 

 Highjacking sounds bad, but it is just one form of over-riding votes.
  At least it doesn't over-ride your
 first place preference like the compromising incentive twists your arm to
 do.  Every method eventually
 over-rides various preferences at some point in the process.  Compromising
 is a form of extortion that
 blackmails you into expressing a false preference. That's the most
 egregious form.

 In other words, compromising forces you to either lie or lose.  If somebody
 else highjacks, they lie to
 take advantage of you, but with much more risk than the liar who buries to
 take advantage of the CW
 supporters.

 For this kind of highjacking to work, the highjacking faction would have to
 have more than three times the
 support of  the highjacked faction, as can be seen from the above example
 (which lacking that much
 support in the hijacking faction gives an obvious first place advantage to
 A).  That kind of superiority is
 more than enough to over-ride pairwise wins in ranked pairs, river,
 beatpath, etc.


This is only true if you define the hijacking faction in terms of the
ultimate beneficiary, the winner. But a minor faction could hijack another
minor faction to shift the frontrunner.

I agree, it's unlikely. But the very possibility, to me, rankles more than
the average strategy. In fact, I suspect it would open the process to legal
challenges.

Anyway, I don't see why it's necessary. All it gains you is summability;
which is nice, but in the age of fast data pipelines it is not a necessity.

JQ

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA and the Condorcet criterion

2011-08-04 Thread fsimmons
I want to thank Jameson for taking the ball and running with it on SODA.  I 
really appreciate his talented 
and energetic work on elaborating, explaining, and selling the method.

It's exciting to me to see the possibilities.

Here's more evidence of monotonicity:

With a three candidate cycle

x ABC
y BCA
z CAB

if xyz, then A plays first, but B wins the election.

If the B faction increases at the expense of the x faction so that  yxz, then 
B goes first, and still wins! 
(because ACB is opposite the cyclic order of the beat cycle)

The other nice thing about SODA and strong first play order is that it makes 
the game of chicken go 
away.



 Date: Thu, 4 Aug 2011 08:01:30 -0500
 From: Jameson Quinn 
 To: EM 
 Subject: [EM] SODA and the Condorcet criterion
 Message-ID:
 
 Content-Type: text/plain; charset=iso-8859-1
 
 Here's the new text on the SODA
 page Delegated_Approval#Criteria_Compliancerelatingto the Condorcet 
 criterion:
 It fails the Condorcet
 criterion,
 although the majority Condorcet winner over the ranking-
 augmented ballots is
 the unique strong, subgame-perfect equilibrium winner. That is 
 to say that,
 the method would in fact pass the *majority* Condorcet winner 
 criterion,assuming the following:
 
 - *Candidates are honest* in their pre-election rankings. 
 This could be
 because they are innately unwilling to be dishonest, because 
 they are unable
 to calculate a useful dishonest strategy, or, most likely, 
 because they fear
 dishonesty would lose them delegated votes. That is, voters 
 who disagreed
 with the dishonest rankings might vote approval-style instead 
 of delegating,
 and voters who perceived the rankings as dishonest might 
 thereby value the
 candidate less.
 - *Candidates are rationally strategic* in assigning their 
 delegated vote. Since the assignments are sequential, game 
 theory states that there is
 always a subgame-perfect Nash equilibrium, which is always 
 unique except in
 some cases of tied preferences.
 - *Voters* are able to use the system to *express all relevant
 preferences*. That is to say, all voters fall into one of two 
 groups: those who agree with their favored candidate's 
 declared preference order and
 thus can fully express that by delegating their vote; or 
 those who disagree
 with their favored candidate's preferences, but are aware of 
 who the
 Condorcet winner is, and are able to use the approval-style 
 ballot to
 express their preference between the CW and all second-place 
 candidates. Second place means the Smith set if the 
 Condorcet winner were removed from
 the election; thus, for this assumption to hold, each voter 
 must prefer the
 CW to all members of this second-place Smith set or vice 
 versa. That's
 obviously always true if there is a single second-place CW.
 
 The three assumptions above would probably not strictly hold 
 true in a
 real-life election, but they usually would be close enough to 
 ensure that
 the system does elect the CW.
 
 SODA does even better than this if there are only 3 candidates, 
 or if the
 Condorcet winner goes first in the delegation assignment order, 
 or if there
 are 4 candidates and the CW goes second. In any of those 
 circumstances,under the assumptions above, it passes the 
 *Condorcet* criterion, not just
 the majority Condorcet criterion. The important difference 
 between the
 Condorcet criterion (beats all others pairwise) and the majority 
 Condorcetcriterion (beats all others pairwise by a strict 
 majority) is that the
 former is clone-proof while the latter is not. Thus, with few 
 enough strong
 candidates, SODA also passes the independence of clones
 criterion
 .
 
 Note that, although the circumstances where SODA passes the Condorcet
 criterion are hemmed in by assumptions, when it does pass, it 
 does so in a
 perfectly strategy-proof sense. That is *not* true of any actual 
 Condorcetsystem (that is, any system which universally passes 
 the Condorcet
 criterion). Therefore, for rationally-strategic voters who 
 believe that the
 above assumptions are likely to hold, *SODA may in fact pass the 
 Condorcetcriterion more often than a Condorcet system*.
 -- next part --
 An HTML attachment was scrubbed...
 URL:  electorama.com/attachments/20110804/d8f85fc2/attachment-0001.htm
 

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] SODA and the Condorcet criterion

2011-08-04 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/8/4 fsimm...@pcc.edu

 I want to thank Jameson for taking the ball and running with it on SODA.  I
 really appreciate his talented
 and energetic work on elaborating, explaining, and selling the method.


Thank you.

More stuff I've added to the SODA page recently:

-I tried to unify the terminology. Voters can delegate their votes;
Candidates receive delegated votes (not ballots), which they then use (I
had been using assign, exercise, or share) by approving other
candidates, who in turn receive these shared votes.

I'd be open to suggestions to improve any of those terms, though I think
consistency is more important than perfection.

-I revamped the section on Advantages, and added a section on Electoral
College compatibility. The latter contains proposed rules for using with the
EC, for which I'm open to refinements or suggestions.

Here are the sections as they stand:

Advantages

SODA has advantages for many groups. In fact, most of the advantages would
fit in more than one of the categories below, so the division is somewhat
arbitrary. Also, on the talk page (click discussion above) there are also
two hard sell SODA pitches for two different audiences, which restate
these advantages in more-opinionated terms.
 
[edithttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/index.php?title=Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approvalaction=editsection=10
]For voters

   1. SODA is extremely easy for the voters; in fact, *no voting system is
   simpler to vote*. (Plurality, by restricting you to only one vote, also
   makes it possible to mistakenly overvote, spoiling your ballot. There is
   no such way to accidentally invalidate your ballot under SODA. Also, both
   Plurality and Approval require a conscientious voter to consider strategy
   and polling status; SODA allows a simple bullet vote to still be
   strategically as strong as possible, regardless of the candidate standings.)
   2. Under SODA, there is *no need for dishonesty* from individual voters.
   A voter can safely vote for any candidate that they honestly agree with,
   without fear of that vote being wasted; or safely vote an honest
   approval-style ballot, if they do not agree with any candidate's preference
   order. This is drastically different from plurality, where voters must
   dishonestly spurn spoiler candidates as a matter of course.
   3. SODA *does not require you to trust any politician*. Any vote
   delegation is both safe (you can see where your delegated vote will go) and
   entirely optional. Any voter who dislikes the idea of their vote being
   delegated in a smoke-filled room, need not allow that to happen.

[edithttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/index.php?title=Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approvalaction=editsection=11
]For society (results)

   1. SODA is far *more likely to arrive at a majority result* than
   Plurality (or even IRV). Winners will thus have a clearer mandate.
   2. SODA may be *more likely to elect the Condorcet winner* (aka pairwise
   champion, the candidate who could beat all others one-on-one) than *any
   other system* (except SODA-DAC http://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/DAC).
   See the technical discussion in the prior section for the assumptions that
   would make this true.
   3. However, unexpected, relatively unknown or *unqualified winners will
   be as rare or rarer under SODA* than under Approval or a Condorcet
   system. In a polarized society, Condorcet can have such a strong tendency to
   elect centrists that even unqualified, largely-unknown centrists have an
   advantage over better-known candidates; SODA will not have such a tendency
   unless the stronger candidates consciously choose this as a compromise.

[edithttp://wiki.electorama.com/wiki/index.php?title=Simple_Optionally-Delegated_Approvalaction=editsection=12
]For society (process)

   1. Leaders of *minority factions would have an appropriate voice for
   their concerns*, although power would ultimately reside with any majority
   coalition which exists. In fact, you could say that SODA combines the best
   of both worlds - the negotiated, everyone-gets-a-voice coalitions of
   parliamentary government, with the decisive, buck-stops-here clear winner of
   a US-style system.
   2. SODA would *reduce negative campaigns*. A negative attack against
   opponent A would often just shift votes to another opponent B who would end
   up sharing them back with A in the delegation round. Meanwhile, the
   candidate carrying out the attacks could also suffer with voters.
   3. Like many other voting reforms, SODA would *reduce the influence of
   money* in political campaigns. Plurality, with its overriding need to be
   a frontrunner, exaggerates the importance of money. SODA in particular, by
   encouraging meaningful campaigns and get-out-the-vote operations by minor
   candidates, while still ensuring that the extra turnout those generated
   would have an effective impact in deciding between the major candidates,
   would help substitute grassroots 

Re: [EM] [RangeVoting] Re: Range Voting As an Issue

2011-08-04 Thread Dave Ketchum
Here I talk of moving up from FPP to Range or Condorcet.  I do not get  
into other single-winner elections or into multi-winner elections -  
while such deserve considering, they distract from my primary goal,  
which is to promote moving upward without getting buried in details.


Voters should see advantages in moving up to a better method.

To vote for one, as in FPP:
. In Range, assign your choice a maximum rating.
. In Condorcet, simply rank your choice.

Voting for two is using more power than FPP offers.  Often there is a  
major pair of candidates for which you prefer one, and one other that  
you also want to vote for:  For your second choice you could give the  
same rank or rating, or lower:
. In Range you assign first choice maximum rating.  Unrated share  
minimum.  The farther you rate second below max, the stronger your  
vote for max over second.  BUT, the nearer you rate second to unrated,  
the weaker you rate second over unrated.

. In Condorcet, rank your first choice higher than your second.

Voting for more is doable:
. In Range your difference in rating between any two is how much  
you prefer the higher over the lower, and the sum of these differences  
decides which wins their race.

. In Condorcet they count how many rank AB vs how many rank BA.

Politicians may hesitate in moving up to more powerful methods.  Range  
or Condorcet can cost more, but getting a truer reading as to voter  
choices can be worth the pain.


Dave Ketchum

On Aug 4, 2011, at 3:20 AM, bob wrote:


--- In rangevot...@yahoogroups.com, thenewthirdparty  
thenewthirdparty@... wrote:


Guys and Gals,
I now see Range Voting as a very important component to getting  
third parties elected.  But I don't see how the Range Voting group  
will ever change the minds of the public in order for it to be a  
reality.  Does someone have thoughts on how to get your Range  
Voting plan voted into action?  I would like to hear how Range  
Voting moves beyond more than just a good idea.




I think we need to start a PAC or even maybe a party that has the  
sole objective of getting rid of plurality voting.  We need to be  
able to communicate that competitive elections in which there is no  
vote splitting is the most important thing we can do to hold  
politicians accountable.  We also need to be willing to vote for  
candidates who support getting rid of plurality regardless of what  
other positions that candidate holds. We need to communicate that  
once we get over this hump, we will no longer have to worry about  
having to vote for the lesser of two evils ever again.


Another thing we can do is email and tweet news hosts like Rachael  
Maddow and ask them to do a segment on different voting systems.  If  
we organize to tweet pundits at the same time, maybe they'll get the  
message.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] [RangeVoting] Re: Range Voting As an Issue

2011-08-04 Thread robert bristow-johnson



On Aug 4, 2011, at 3:20 AM, bob wrote:


--- In rangevot...@yahoogroups.com, thenewthirdparty 
thenewthirdparty@... wrote:


Guys and Gals,
I now see Range Voting as a very important component to getting 
third parties elected.  But I don't see how the Range Voting group 
will ever change the minds of the public in order for it to be a 
reality.


and they haven't changed my mind about it, even though i'm not opposed 
to election policy reform nor of moving past FPP.  i fully recognize why 
the simple vote-for-one ballot (either FPP or delayed-top-two-runoff) 
disadvantages third-party and independent candidates.


this was a point i brought up during in Burlington IRV debate:  one of 
the vocal opponents to IRV was, 3 years previously, a minor candidate 
for mayor in Burlington Vermont.  i would almost say a non-serious 
candidate, but he got on the ballot (his name is Loyal Ploof).  now he 
lost to the Prog candidate who was elected in 2006 and he was a sorta 
anti-establishment rabble rouser (if he could get a rabble).


now (i told them this), suppose i'm standing in the rabble and Loyal 
says something that we all sorta know but the contending candidates 
aren't gonna bring up and i hear it and i say yeah, right!  Loyal's 
right!  maybe even he's a largely single-issue candidate, maybe not.  
but i want to send a message to city hall by voting for Loyal but the 
election between the real contenders might be close and my two-party 
contingency candidate may need my vote.  so Loyal doesn't get it, 
because even if i agree with him and *want* to vote for him, i dare not.


it's the typical Spoiler problem, that discourages voting for 
third-party or independent candidates.  if they can never sufficient 
vote (because the race between credible candidates may be close) third 
parties cannot get off the ground and become contenders.  but i was 
surprized that this guy who would directly benefit from a ranked ballot 
would be opposed to it.  (he didn't like the Prog mayor and essentially 
jumped in the boat with the other Prog-haters that believed, falsely, 
that IRV specifically favored the Progs in Burlington.)


that said, and to repeat that i also understand IRV to have *failed* in 
Burlington in 2009, i am not at all impressed with Range or Score voting 
for governmental elections (for certain Olympic sports, sure, but not 
for governmental elections).  one of the complaints we have against both 
FPP and IRV (as we found out in Burlington in 2009) is placing obvious 
burdens of tactical voting on the electorate.  we don't *like* having to 
forsake our favorite candidate in order to accomplish some other 
political imperative.  FPP discourages the Nader voters from voting for 
their favorite candidate in 2000 by punishing them when it became clear 
that their vote cause Bush to be elected.  and IRV discourages the GOP 
Prog-haters in Burlington from voting for their favorite candidate in 
2009 when they discover that marking their favorite as #1 on the ballot 
actually caused the Prog to win.


now, it's not the ranked ballot that failed these voters, it was the 
Hare-STV method of tabulating the vote. Condorcet would have taken the 
same ballot data and elected the candidate that was preferred by the 
electorate over any other specific candidate.  The GOP who lost the most 
in the election would neither have gotten punished for their sincere 
1st-choice vote (if IRV had survived, in 2012 these guys would be saying 
to themselves in the polls: I gotta choose between Liberal and 
More-Liberal, because if I vote for the guy I really like, More-Liberal 
gets elected), they would have been more satisfied with the Condorcet 
winner than with the IRV winner, who was their least favorite.  And the 
Progs would have been more satisfied with the Condorcet winner than with 
the apparent FPP winner (the GOP), but they would be unhappy with the 
result due to rivalry the Progs and Dems have for the common liberal 
voter in this town.


Ranked-choice voting requires less strategizing by the voter than Range 
because it requires less information.  with a ranked ballot, all the 
voter needs to decide is who, in every contingency that matters to the 
voter, who he or she would vote for.  they don't need to decide how much 
*more* they like Mother Teresa over Ghandi.  If they really want to bury 
a third candidate, Stalin, they have to sacrifice their preference 
between the two virtuous and the election might be decided between 
them.  Or maybe the election will turn out to be a battle between Stalin 
and Satan and they might rather live under Stalin than Satan, so they 
want to bump him up a little (leave Satan with a score of 0).  but what 
if Satan wins because not enough voters scored Stalin up enough?  or 
what if either Teresa or Ghandi lose to Stalin because too many voters 
scored Stalin too high (for fear of electing Satan)?


what to do?  what to do?

but a ranked ballot is easy:

  Teresa  Ghandi