Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-29 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Nov 29, 2009, at 6:37 PM, James Gilmour wrote:


Robert Bristow-Johnson wrote (9 Nov 2009):

"Of course IRV, Condorcet, and Borda use different methods  to  
tabulate

the votes and select the winner and my opinion is that IRV ("asset
voting", I might call it "commodity voting": your vote is a
"commodity" that you transfer according to your preferences) is a
kabuki dance of transferred votes.  and there is an *arbitrary*
evaluation in the elimination of candidates in the IRV rounds: 2nd-
choice votes don't count for shit in deciding who to eliminate (who
decided that?  2nd-choice votes are as good as last-choice?  under
what meaningful and consistent philosophy was that decided?), then
when your candidate is eliminated your 2nd-choice vote counts as  
much

as your 1st-choice."


These statements suggest a misunderstanding of how STV voting works  
and what preferences (US "rankings") mean in the STV voting

system.


i know earlier someone (it might've been James, i dunno) wrote that  
"STV" (i think that's what it's called in Australia) is called "IRV"  
in the US.  i dunno to what extent that is true, but assuming it is,  
i understand exactly how IRV works as used by a few municipalities in  
the US, specifically what was used in Burlington VT which i think is  
identical to how it is in Cambridge MA, SF CA, someplace in NC, and  
Mpls/StP MN.  to how the method works in Australia, i do not know  
first hand.


also, i case you're interested, i voted for IRV for Burlington in  
2005 (it has been used in two elections since), and in the referendum  
it faces this coming spring, i'll likely vote against recalling  
(abolishing in favor of the FPTP/delayed_runoff we had before) IRV.   
the issue to me is that the single-transferrable vote (as done in our  
domestic IRV) is the wrong algorithm to tabulate the votes in a multi- 
candidate election where no candidate gets a majority of 1st-pick votes.



  In all STV elections, the preferences are contingency choices.


that is true.  i fully support a contingency choice is multi-party/ 
multi-candidate elections.



  Your vote is transferred to your second choice only in the
event that your first choice cannot secure election or does not  
need you support to secure election.


that is *one* way to use the information of the contingency choices.   
if you are working out a complex problem with multiple directions of  
interest (which an election with more than 2 sincere candidates would  
be), you don't necessarily quantify votes as a commodity with some  
fixed value, and then, as i still point out, transfer these  
commodities around according to a candidate viability metric that  
arbitrarily says that 2nd-choice is no better than the last choice.


you still haven't demonstrated why this contingent-choice information  
is the logical way to resolve a bunch of different competing  
contingency interests.  we know how, if there were only two  
candidates, to decide between the two (assuming they don't tie).  we  
know how to vote in that case (our sincere vote is the same as our  
tactical vote, easy), plurality = majority.  assuming no funny  
business, no one can dispute the popular legitimacy of the winner.


what we don't want to happen (assuming we want honest and democratic  
elections where tactical voting is not likely to work) is resolve an  
election differently between any two candidates differently than we  
would if those two were among a larger group of candidates.  we don't  
want to have to think how we would vote differently in the two  
cases.  if there is a Condorcet winner, and you are not that person,  
that Condorcet winner beat you, as far as the electorate is  
concerned.  if it was just the two of you, he beats you.  if it was  
you two along with N-2 other candidates, he still beats you (as well  
as beating everyone else).


This is most easily seen in single-winner STV elections (US = IRV),  
where the sequence of rounds is exactly analogous to the
sequence of rounds in an exhaustive ballot (eliminating one  
candidate at a time in successive ballots).


please don't patronize me.  there is nothing you're saying here that  
i don't know.  it is in how IRV does that that is the problem.  it  
doesn't accomplish the very goals we had when we adopted IRV (not  
rewarding tactical voting thus eliminating the need to consider  
tactical voting so we can vote the way we want to and not worry about  
contributing to defeating our own political interest - "voter regret").



  The only difference is that
in an STV (IRV) election you don't know what all the other voters  
did in Round 1 when you come to give your second choice.


you mean you don't have transparency on how the rounds were performed  
or is it that your STV is a delayed runoff where you come in later?   
because i can't see the difference.  in the IRV i am familiar with,  
you order your candidates before knowing how any round turns out.  no  
one is returning to a

Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-25 Thread Dave Ketchum

Trying to sort this out as to Condorcet and LNH:

Seems that cycles are involved before, after, or both.  And the voters  
change their votes, getting more affect on result than they might  
expect.  So what, assuming the counters properly read the vote?


I agree with those who expect cycles to be rare.  Still, it is the  
more important races that are more likely to result in cycles.


What I see as important is that, assuming analysis of the election is  
done both officially and by others, it should be practical to decide  
whether the official result was correct, considering the N*N vote  
count.  In other words, the official analysis should not be complex -  
especially not to gain trivial improvement in quality of official  
result.


Dave Ketchum

On Nov 25, 2009, at 3:08 PM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:

On Nov 25, 2009, at 10:05 AM, Chris Benham wrote:

Robert Bristow-Johnson wrote (9 Nov 2009):

"Of course IRV, Condorcet, and Borda use different methods to  
tabulate

the votes and select the winner and my opinion is that IRV ("asset
voting", i might call it "commodity voting": your vote is a
"commodity" that you transfer according to your preferences) is a
kabuki dance of transferred votes.  and there is an *arbitrary*
evaluation in the elimination of candidates in the IRV rounds: 2nd-
choice votes don't count for shit in deciding who to eliminate (who
decided that?  2nd-choice votes are as good as last-choice?  under
what meaningful and consistent philosophy was that decided?), then
when your candidate is eliminated your 2nd-choice vote counts as much
as your 1st-choice."

Regarding IRV's "philosophy": each voter has single vote that is  
transferable
according to a rule that meets Later-no-Harm, Later-no-Help and  
Majority

for Solid Coalitions.

I rate IRV (Alternative Vote with unlimited strict ranking from the  
top) as the

best of the single-winner methods that meet Later-no-Harm.



On Nov 25, 2009, at 2:41 PM, Warren Smith wrote:


Are there any other voting methods besides IRV, meeting the
'later no harm' criterion?



my understanding is that the later-no-harm result happens only if  
the case of a Condorcet cycle (the prevalence of which i am dubious  
about).  where there is a Condorcet winner and that person is  
elected, is there still possible later harm?


i hadn't thought of it before but i s'pose that since Condorcet  
*does* give preference to centrist candidates over solid coalition  
candidates (in comparison to IRV rules).  i knew before that  
Condorcet sorta favors centrist candidates because voters in either  
the left or right fringes (that do not pick the centrist candidate  
as their 1st-choice) likely pick the centrist as their 2nd-choice.   
that's nice for political interests of centrist voters, but that is  
no reason to pick an election method.  the reason that IRV or *any*  
non-Condorcet method is problematic for the interest of democracy is  
that any candidate elected that is not the Condorcet winner is  
elected despite the fact that the majority of voters expressed that  
they wanted someone else *specifically* on their ballots.


when IRV or Borda or whatever happens to elect the Condorcet winner,  
they seem to do pretty well.  when they fail to do that, voters have  
reason to wonder: "didn't more of us prefer that other guy?  how'd  
this guy get elected?"  isn't that what democracy is about?: if more  
of us prefer Candidate A to Candidate B, then it isn't Candidate B  
who gets elected.


other than the possible cycle, in which some kinda pathologies can  
happen, i still don't see a pimple on it.


r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-25 Thread Juho

On Nov 26, 2009, at 12:43 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

A final note is this: while the above may make it seem like I think  
criterion compliance is pointless (after all, the failure could be  
hidden in an obscure election scenario that will never happen),  
that's not quite true. If a method passes Condorcet, you at once  
know it will always pick the CW if one exists; you don't have to sit  
down and reason whether the failure is acceptable by whatever metric  
you are using. Thus, if we can pass criteria without having to pay  
too much, we should; a method passing a criterion is a guarantee for  
that method that it won't ever misbehave in the way drawn up by the  
criterion, and such absolute guarantees are nice things to have. If  
we can't have them, *then* we can start talking about whether or not  
it matters, but in the ideal world, we would have a method that pass  
the criteria that are worth passing.


I agree with this.

If some method breaks some criterion it would be good to understand  
also how often that is expected to happen and how serious the  
consequences are expected to be. (Even if some violations of this  
criterion (by other methods) would be serious the violations of this  
method might be minor. The violations might be so rare and  
consequences so mild that the problems are marginal or below the noise  
level.)


If there are multiple criteria that can not be met simultaneously it  
is possible that the best method violates all these criteria (instead  
of trying to meet as many of them as possible). It is possible that  
compatibility with some criteria makes the method violate some other  
criterion more. And this may lead e.g. to greater vulnerability to  
tactical voting (since the weakest link of the chain is now weaker  
than what it could be when all/many of the criteria are violated but  
only lightly).


In summary, it would be good to have some standard ways and common  
practices to give also some general estimates on 1) when / how often  
some criterion is violated and 2) how serious the consequences are.


We all would like e.g. "later preferences to never cause harm" and  
"election methods to be strategy free" but we just can't. Typically we  
need to sacrifice some properties in favour of some others, or simply  
accept that the laws of nature don't allow us to have everything that  
we would like to have. Some criteria are also double-edged. You may  
have problems both if you meet them and if you don't. Nice names of  
the criteria (that point in one direction only) and that use words  
with positive or negative tone may sometimes increase confusion (=> as  
if there would be a need to meet such a criterion always).


I addition I must note (the trivial fact) that the number of criteria  
that some method meets does not mean that it would be good (although  
there is some correlation). There may be e.g. criteria that point out  
some benefits that are marginal and that are in real life run over by  
some other bigger vulnerabilities. I think the true vulnerability of  
the methods can often be described in a more reliable way e.g. by  
giving some realistic (real life / in the intended environment)  
examples on how the method may fail. Such examples are of course often  
based on the basic information about theoretical vulnerabilities and  
whether or not the method meets some criteria but the real test is if  
those vulnerabilities will/can have some impact in the actual election.


Another summary. Maybe I was just saying that in many typical  
environments Condorcet methods are indeed "quite LNH" :-).


Juho






Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-25 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

robert bristow-johnson wrote:


On Nov 25, 2009, at 3:26 PM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:


robert bristow-johnson wrote:

my understanding is that the later-no-harm result happens only if the 
case of a Condorcet cycle (the prevalence of which i am dubious 
about).  where there is a Condorcet winner and that person is 
elected, is there still possible later harm?


As far as I remember, Condorcet and LNHarm has the property that 
LNHarm isn't, by itself, violated as long as there is a CW, but the 
transition from CW to no CW (or vice versa) makes it inevitable that 
there will be a LNHarm-violating discontinuity *somewhere*.


the degree of inevitability is an issue.  if "inevitable" is measured as 
a binary value, the i s'pose it's inevitable.  if "inevitable" is 
measured as a probability of a cycle occurring per election-year, then i 
think it's a small number.  if cycles are rare, the mean percentage of 
elections that have Condercet cycles is small.  when we somehow figure 
out a merit metric for an election system, a low-likelihood of a 
pathology that has low cost (say, if a cycle happens you elect using IRV 
rules, how bad can that be?) should contribute (negatively) negligibly 
to the merit metric.


I just want to be precise here: when I talk about inevitability, I talk 
about mathematical inevitability. That is, (if I'm right,) for any 
possible completion method, there will be some ballot set that, when 
some of the ballots are modified to add later candidates to otherwise 
truncated ballots, the candidates that are ranked higher are harmed by that.


The elections don't have to be realistic - what's sufficient in the term 
of criterion compliance is whether it's possible to contrive an example.


Whether or not that has any real bearing on the issue of public 
elections using the method is another question, but that's an argument 
one may field against any criterion compliance/failure. For instance, 
some of those who favor IRV say that monotonicity failures can't be 
manipulated and so are irrelevant.


In any case, I think we agree, but I wanted to clear that up. I'll 
repeat that I don't think LNHarm compliance is that important, although 
others disagree, of course.



A final note is this: while the above may make it seem like I think 
criterion compliance is pointless (after all, the failure could be 
hidden in an obscure election scenario that will never happen), that's 
not quite true. If a method passes Condorcet, you at once know it will 
always pick the CW if one exists; you don't have to sit down and reason 
whether the failure is acceptable by whatever metric you are using. 
Thus, if we can pass criteria without having to pay too much, we should; 
a method passing a criterion is a guarantee for that method that it 
won't ever misbehave in the way drawn up by the criterion, and such 
absolute guarantees are nice things to have. If we can't have them, 
*then* we can start talking about whether or not it matters, but in the 
ideal world, we would have a method that pass the criteria that are 
worth passing.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-25 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Nov 25, 2009, at 3:26 PM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:


robert bristow-johnson wrote:

my understanding is that the later-no-harm result happens only if  
the case of a Condorcet cycle (the prevalence of which i am  
dubious about).  where there is a Condorcet winner and that person  
is elected, is there still possible later harm?


As far as I remember, Condorcet and LNHarm has the property that  
LNHarm isn't, by itself, violated as long as there is a CW, but the  
transition from CW to no CW (or vice versa) makes it inevitable  
that there will be a LNHarm-violating discontinuity *somewhere*.


the degree of inevitability is an issue.  if "inevitable" is measured  
as a binary value, the i s'pose it's inevitable.  if "inevitable" is  
measured as a probability of a cycle occurring per election-year,  
then i think it's a small number.  if cycles are rare, the mean  
percentage of elections that have Condercet cycles is small.  when we  
somehow figure out a merit metric for an election system, a low- 
likelihood of a pathology that has low cost (say, if a cycle happens  
you elect using IRV rules, how bad can that be?) should contribute  
(negatively) negligibly to the merit metric.


In other words, as long as you stay within the CW domain, there is  
no LNHarm failure, but there is no way to engineer a completion  
rule to maintain this for every CW<->no CW transition.


sure, but i'm still dubious about the product of likelihood times  
cost of occurrence of that.



I'm not entirely sure about that, though - can anyone confirm?


and i continue to wonder (really) how a possibly rare occurrence of a  
no-CW election (with its LNHarm consequence) becomes a greater  
concern than that of the likelihood and cost of electing a candidate  
against the expressed wishes of a majority of the electorate.  i  
think that cost (electing the wrong candidate) is reasonably high and  
that the likelihood of it happening is definitely non-zero because it  
has happened in the Vermont town i am a resident of.


Not that this bothers me - LNHarm seems to me to be a criterion of  
"don't take the full picture into account". Consider a negotiation  
situation: if everybody keeps their cards close to their chests  
(i.e. vote bullet style), there can be no compromise; but if  
they're willing to reach further, one might find an option that,  
while not the favorite of any, is good enough for all.


i would call that the essential measure of a popular election.  it's  
utilitarian: we maximize satisfaction for the franchised about the  
governance of whatever organization by pleasing more people with a  
decision than we displease.  that's the reason we have elections, we  
could adopt rules to give it to the minority candidate if that  
candidate reaches a certain threshold, but we don't do that for  
binary decisions, we consistently give it to the majority.


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

"Imagination is more important than knowledge."





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-25 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

robert bristow-johnson wrote:

my understanding is that the later-no-harm result happens only if the 
case of a Condorcet cycle (the prevalence of which i am dubious about).  
where there is a Condorcet winner and that person is elected, is there 
still possible later harm?


As far as I remember, Condorcet and LNHarm has the property that LNHarm 
isn't, by itself, violated as long as there is a CW, but the transition 
from CW to no CW (or vice versa) makes it inevitable that there will be 
a LNHarm-violating discontinuity *somewhere*.


In other words, as long as you stay within the CW domain, there is no 
LNHarm failure, but there is no way to engineer a completion rule to 
maintain this for every CW<->no CW transition.


I'm not entirely sure about that, though - can anyone confirm?


Not that this bothers me - LNHarm seems to me to be a criterion of 
"don't take the full picture into account". Consider a negotiation 
situation: if everybody keeps their cards close to their chests (i.e. 
vote bullet style), there can be no compromise; but if they're willing 
to reach further, one might find an option that, while not the favorite 
of any, is good enough for all. An LNHarm-respecting method has to act 
as if people are voting cautiously before it can consider any additional 
information, and thus it misses such opportunities for compromise.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-25 Thread robert bristow-johnson





On Nov 25, 2009, at 10:05 AM, Chris Benham wrote:


Robert Bristow-Johnson wrote (9 Nov 2009):

"Of course IRV, Condorcet, and Borda use different methods to tabulate
the votes and select the winner and my opinion is that IRV ("asset
voting", i might call it "commodity voting": your vote is a
"commodity" that you transfer according to your preferences) is a
kabuki dance of transferred votes.  and there is an *arbitrary*
evaluation in the elimination of candidates in the IRV rounds: 2nd-
choice votes don't count for shit in deciding who to eliminate (who
decided that?  2nd-choice votes are as good as last-choice?  under
what meaningful and consistent philosophy was that decided?), then
when your candidate is eliminated your 2nd-choice vote counts as much
as your 1st-choice."

Regarding IRV's "philosophy": each voter has single vote that is  
transferable
according to a rule that meets Later-no-Harm, Later-no-Help and  
Majority

for Solid Coalitions.

I rate IRV (Alternative Vote with unlimited strict ranking from the  
top) as the

best of the single-winner methods that meet Later-no-Harm.



On Nov 25, 2009, at 2:41 PM, Warren Smith wrote:


Are there any other voting methods besides IRV, meeting the
'later no harm' criterion?



my understanding is that the later-no-harm result happens only if the  
case of a Condorcet cycle (the prevalence of which i am dubious  
about).  where there is a Condorcet winner and that person is  
elected, is there still possible later harm?


i hadn't thought of it before but i s'pose that since Condorcet  
*does* give preference to centrist candidates over solid coalition  
candidates (in comparison to IRV rules).  i knew before that  
Condorcet sorta favors centrist candidates because voters in either  
the left or right fringes (that do not pick the centrist candidate as  
their 1st-choice) likely pick the centrist as their 2nd-choice.   
that's nice for political interests of centrist voters, but that is  
no reason to pick an election method.  the reason that IRV or *any*  
non-Condorcet method is problematic for the interest of democracy is  
that any candidate elected that is not the Condorcet winner is  
elected despite the fact that the majority of voters expressed that  
they wanted someone else *specifically* on their ballots.


when IRV or Borda or whatever happens to elect the Condorcet winner,  
they seem to do pretty well.  when they fail to do that, voters have  
reason to wonder: "didn't more of us prefer that other guy?  how'd  
this guy get elected?"  isn't that what democracy is about?: if more  
of us prefer Candidate A to Candidate B, then it isn't Candidate B  
who gets elected.


other than the possible cycle, in which some kinda pathologies can  
happen, i still don't see a pimple on it.


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

"Imagination is more important than knowledge."





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-25 Thread Chris Benham
Robert Bristow-Johnson wrote (9 Nov 2009):

"Of course IRV, Condorcet, and Borda use different methods to tabulate  
the votes and select the winner and my opinion is that IRV ("asset  
voting", i might call it "commodity voting": your vote is a  
"commodity" that you transfer according to your preferences) is a  
kabuki dance of transferred votes.  and there is an *arbitrary*  
evaluation in the elimination of candidates in the IRV rounds: 2nd- 
choice votes don't count for shit in deciding who to eliminate (who  
decided that?  2nd-choice votes are as good as last-choice?  under  
what meaningful and consistent philosophy was that decided?), then  
when your candidate is eliminated your 2nd-choice vote counts as much  
as your 1st-choice."

Regarding IRV's "philosophy": each voter has single vote that is transferable
according to a rule that meets Later-no-Harm, Later-no-Help and Majority
for Solid Coalitions.

I rate IRV (Alternative Vote with unlimited strict ranking from the top) as the
best of the single-winner methods that meet Later-no-Harm.

Chris Benham


  
__
Win 1 of 4 Sony home entertainment packs thanks to Yahoo!7.
Enter now: http://au.docs.yahoo.com/homepageset/

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting? (long)

2009-11-11 Thread Juho
In large elections with evenly spread voters and candidates and no  
strategies the distribution of Approval votes may indeed be such that  
the best candidate regularly wins. The situation may however be also  
different. I  gave one simple example where the left wing had two  
candidates and the right wing had only one. The distribution of votes  
may not bring fair results in this type of set-up.


The assumption was that the right wing voters would predominantly  
approve only their own candidate while many left wing voters would be  
tempted to indicate which one of the left wing candidates they prefer  
over the other (despite of clearly preferring both left wing  
candidates over the right wing candidate). The end result could  
therefore be biased. The right wing candidate might easily win even if  
right wing would have considerably smaller than 50% support.


With small number of candidates and with a candidate set-up that is  
not symmetric or well balanced Approval may well produce biased  
results. Methods that are capable of providing richer information  
(ranked methods) are likely to provide more balanced input data (and  
results).


Juho


On Nov 12, 2009, at 2:28 AM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:


On Nov 10, 2009, at 7:40 AM, Matthew Welland wrote:



It is the aggregate of
thousands or millions of votes that will make or break A vs. B. How  
many

feel so strongly against A that they cannot vote for him or her?

The binary nature of approval is washed out by large numbers just  
as a class
D amplifier can directly produce smooth analog waveforms out of a  
pure 1 or 0

signal.


the mathematical function that does that is the low-pass filter on  
the output.  it's sorta the same idea that these 1-bit A/D (a.k.a.  
"sigma-delta") converters use.  if we were voting with a range  
ballot, and our continuous range value gets a zero-mean uniform  
p.d.f. random "dither" signal added to it (or, to use your PWM  
example, a zero-mean number drawn sequentially, in chronological  
order of the vote submission) and that gets quantized to a yes/no  
Approval vote (i s'pose if the threshold is set to 50%), then you  
would have a comparable situation.


i just dunno if i like the idea of a zero-mean (and even symmetrical  
p.d.f.) random variable actually going into a governmental  
election.  how well i approve or disapprove of a particular  
candidate that i am not actively supporting is a function of how i'm  
feeling on Election Day.  but it's less likely how i rank that  
candidate w.r.t. the other candidates would change.  like grading  
papers, sometimes to come up with a numerical score, we get out our  
dartboard and see how good our toss is.  but students might like a  
more deterministic method.


for governmental elections, i only support a system that is fully  
deterministic (and repeatable) except, i s'pose, if there is a dead  
heat, then i s'pose, some kind of drawing of lots would be  
necessary.  it should require enough information from voters that  
the system knows how any voter would choose between any subset of  
candidates (the ranked ballot does that, but the approval ballot  
does not).  and it shouldn't force voters to bring their dartboard  
(or dice or spinner, etc) to the polls to come up with a numerical  
approval rating for each candidate, because of GIGO.


the other principle that is important is that of anonymity of vote.   
it shouldn't matter if you really, really, really like your  
candidate and i only tepidly support his/her opponent.  my vote for  
the opponent should count just as much as your more enthusiastic  
vote for your candidate.  there should be nothing that tips the  
scale in favor of your candidate based on how enthusiastically she  
is supported, only by the numbers of voters that supports her.  our  
votes should have equal weight.


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

"Imagination is more important than knowledge."





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for  
list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting? (long)

2009-11-11 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Nov 10, 2009, at 7:40 AM, Matthew Welland wrote:


Also, again, your single vote is irrelevant.


except in a close election.


It is the aggregate of
thousands or millions of votes that will make or break A vs. B. How  
many

feel so strongly against A that they cannot vote for him or her?

The binary nature of approval is washed out by large numbers just  
as a class
D amplifier can directly produce smooth analog waveforms out of a  
pure 1 or 0

signal.


the mathematical function that does that is the low-pass filter on  
the output.  it's sorta the same idea that these 1-bit A/D (a.k.a.  
"sigma-delta") converters use.  if we were voting with a range  
ballot, and our continuous range value gets a zero-mean uniform  
p.d.f. random "dither" signal added to it (or, to use your PWM  
example, a zero-mean number drawn sequentially, in chronological  
order of the vote submission) and that gets quantized to a yes/no  
Approval vote (i s'pose if the threshold is set to 50%), then you  
would have a comparable situation.


i just dunno if i like the idea of a zero-mean (and even symmetrical  
p.d.f.) random variable actually going into a governmental election.   
how well i approve or disapprove of a particular candidate that i am  
not actively supporting is a function of how i'm feeling on Election  
Day.  but it's less likely how i rank that candidate w.r.t. the other  
candidates would change.  like grading papers, sometimes to come up  
with a numerical score, we get out our dartboard and see how good our  
toss is.  but students might like a more deterministic method.


for governmental elections, i only support a system that is fully  
deterministic (and repeatable) except, i s'pose, if there is a dead  
heat, then i s'pose, some kind of drawing of lots would be  
necessary.  it should require enough information from voters that the  
system knows how any voter would choose between any subset of  
candidates (the ranked ballot does that, but the approval ballot does  
not).  and it shouldn't force voters to bring their dartboard (or  
dice or spinner, etc) to the polls to come up with a numerical  
approval rating for each candidate, because of GIGO.


the other principle that is important is that of anonymity of vote.   
it shouldn't matter if you really, really, really like your candidate  
and i only tepidly support his/her opponent.  my vote for the  
opponent should count just as much as your more enthusiastic vote for  
your candidate.  there should be nothing that tips the scale in favor  
of your candidate based on how enthusiastically she is supported,  
only by the numbers of voters that supports her.  our votes should  
have equal weight.


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

"Imagination is more important than knowledge."





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Raph Frank
On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 10:52 PM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm
 wrote:
> In the context of SEC, it would be:
>
> Voter submits two ballots - one is ranked and the other is a Plurality
> ballot. Call the first the fallback ballot, and the second the consensus
> ballot.
>
> If everybody (or some very high percentage, e.g. 99%) votes for the same
> consensus ballot, it wins. Otherwise, construct a Condorcet matrix based on
> the fallback ballots. Pick two candidates at random and the one that
> pairwise beats the other, wins.

How do you pick the random candidates?

For that to be clone independent, there would actually need to be 3 ballots:

- consensus ballot

If more than X% of the ballots pick the same candidate, then that
candidate wins.

- nomination ballot
- fallback ranking

2 nomination ballots are picked to decide the candidate and the
pairwise winner according to the rankings wins.

However, as I said in my last post, the nomination ballot isn't strategy free.

> To my knowledge, Random Pair is strategy-free. It might also be
> proportional, but I'm not sure about that (partly because I'm not sure how
> you'd define "proportional" for ranked ballots).

The problem is picking the 2 candidates.  If 2 are picked at random,
then the method isn't clone independent.

Also, it favours the condorcet winner, so may suffer from tyranny of
the majority.

However, if you had a divided society, then both ethnic groups would
still have some say.

For example, if the split was 55% (A) and 45 (B), and each ethnic
group only voted for their own candidate, then the results would be

2 A's: 30% => ethnic group A wins
A+B:  50% => ethnic group A wins (as they are the majority)
2 B's: 20% => ethnic group B wins

Thus group B gets some power, but not proportional power.

However, once the society starts working better, it would seamlessly
transition to a near condorcet method.

Also, in a divided society condorcet voting might reduce the issue directly.

In both cases, there would be an incentive for politicians from ethnic
group A to try to get support from voters in ethnic group B.

OTOH, a random election method may not be the best plan in a society
where corruption is a problem.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Raph Frank wrote:

On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 8:11 PM, Jobst Heitzig  wrote:

Hello Kristofer,

Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information
from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with
respect to Random Ballot?

This sounds interesting, but what exactly do you mean by Random Pair?
Pick a randomly chosen pair of candidates and elect the pairwise winner
of them? I will think about this...


Presumably, it means that the voter submits 2 ballots, a ranking and a
nomination for the 2nd round?


In the context of SEC, it would be:

Voter submits two ballots - one is ranked and the other is a Plurality 
ballot. Call the first the fallback ballot, and the second the consensus 
ballot.


If everybody (or some very high percentage, e.g. 99%) votes for the same 
consensus ballot, it wins. Otherwise, construct a Condorcet matrix based 
on the fallback ballots. Pick two candidates at random and the one that 
pairwise beats the other, wins.


To my knowledge, Random Pair is strategy-free. It might also be 
proportional, but I'm not sure about that (partly because I'm not sure 
how you'd define "proportional" for ranked ballots).


You seem to be suggesting a more Condorcet way of doing the consensus 
balloting. A possible option would be to look at how e.g. Debian handles 
supermajority issues. On the other hand, grafting Condorcet onto the 
consensus option would make the actual consensus more opaque, and one 
may in any case argue: "if you have a consensus, there's an agreement 
and so you don't need a complex method to determine what the consensus 
actually is".


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Raph Frank
On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 8:11 PM, Jobst Heitzig  wrote:
> Hello Kristofer,
>> Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information
>> from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with
>> respect to Random Ballot?
>
> This sounds interesting, but what exactly do you mean by Random Pair?
> Pick a randomly chosen pair of candidates and elect the pairwise winner
> of them? I will think about this...

Presumably, it means that the voter submits 2 ballots, a ranking and a
nomination for the 2nd round?

Clearly, your rankings should be honest, as it is only looked at once
the 2 candidates have been decided.

However, your nomination would have to be made tactically.

It would require that the voter decide the probability of the
candidate they nominate winning.

If you nominate the condorcet winner, then the odds of your candidate
winning the second round is 100%, as no other candidate can possibly
beat him..

However, if you nominate an extremist, then your nomination is almost
certain to fail, as he will lose to virtually any other candidate.

If the voter distribution is symmetric (and voter utility is
symmetric) around a central point, then the nominated candidate who is
closest to the centre will win.

If each voter nominates their favourite, then you best strategy is to
nominate the the candidate which maximises

f(distance)*utility

f(distance) is the fraction of the nominations that nominate
candidates further away than that distance from the centre.

f(0) is automatically 1 and f(most extremist candidate's distance) is
automatically 0.  Also, f(d) is a monotonic decreasing function.

Thus, when considering 2 candidates of near equal utility, you should
nominate the candidate nearest the centre.

However, if all voters do that, then most of the nominations will
start to be clustered near the centre.  This means that the voters
should nominate candidates even closer to the centre.

I.e. if f(d) = 0.1, then you would have to prefer that candidate at
least 10 times better than the condorcet winner in order to nominate
him.

I think the effect could very easily end up being that the condorcet
winner normally wins.

It could also be implemented in 2 formal rounds.  In the first round,
each voter votes for 1 candidate.  2 candidates are picked at random,
using random ballot.

Those 2 candidates then proceed to the run off.  This might even make
people accept random ballot.  The problem that a candidate with 1%
support could get to be President is eliminated.  (Unless it happens
twice in 1 election.)

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Jobst Heitzig wrote:

Hello Kristofer,

you wrote:



You could probably devise a whole class of SEC-type methods. They would
go: if there is a consensus (defined in some fashion), then it wins -
otherwise, a nondeterministic strategy-free method is used to pick the
winner. The advantage of yours is that it uses only Plurality ballots.


The hard point is, I think, to define what actually a potential
consensus option is. And here the idea was to say everything unanimously
preferred to some benchmark outcome qualifies as potential consensus.
The benchmark then cannot be any feasible option but must be a lottery
of some options, otherwise the supporters of the single option would
block the consensus. But which lottery you take as a benchmark could be
discussed. I chose the Random Ballot lottery since it seems the most
fair one and has all nice properties (strategy-freeness, proportional
allocation of power).


I suppose the nondeterministic method would have to be "bad enough" to
provide incentive to pick the right consensus, yet it shouldn't be so
bad as to undermine the process itself if the voters really can't reach
a consensus.


Although I can hardly imagine real-world situations in which no
consensus option can be found (maybe be combining different decisions
into one, or using some kind of compensation scheme if necessary).


That might be true for a consensus in general, but I was referring to 
the SEC method, where all it takes is for a single voter to submit a 
different consensus ballot than the rest.



Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information
from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with
respect to Random Ballot? 


This sounds interesting, but what exactly do you mean by Random Pair?
Pick a randomly chosen pair of candidates and elect the pairwise winner
of them? I will think about this...


Yes. The CW now has a greater chance to win - but note that it's not 
given that the CW will win, because if he's not picked as one of the 
pair candidates, he doesn't come into play at all.



It would lead to a better outcome if the
consensus fails, but so also make it more likely that the consensus does
fail. Or would it? The reasoning from a given participant's point of
view is rather: do I get something *I* would like by refusing to take
part in consensus -- not, does *society* get something acceptable.


I'm not sure I know what you mean here.


Well, I was thinking that the SEC method provides an incentive for 
people to reach a common consensus because the alternative, which is the 
random ballot, isn't very good. Any (random or deterministic) method 
that favors some group would lead to that group having less of an 
incentive to participate in the consensus process because they know 
they'll get something they'll like.


Therefore, I at first thought that even though Random Pair would provide 
a result more people would be happy with, it would make the voters less 
interested in actually finding a consensus because the alternative isn't 
so bad anymore. However, then I realized that any given voter, if he's 
at the point where he doesn't care about the consensus option, will not 
be deterred from such a line of thinking because the alternative is 
suboptimal for society, only if it is suboptimal in his point of view. 
That means that you could replace Random Ballot with Random Pair as long 
as the fairness (what you call proportional allocation of power) remains 
intact, because if the improvement in result lifts all the groups 
equally, there's no more incentive for some group to "cheat" with 
respect to any other.


There's also another way of looking at it, which I just saw now: my 
first idea was that you can't move to a lottery that gives consistently 
good results because that will diminish people's interest in determining 
a consensus. But if the lottery is both fair and provides good results, 
then who cares? The consensus option will only come into play if the 
people can explicitly agree on a choice that's better than the expected 
value of the lottery. If figuring out a consensus is worth it (much 
better than the lottery, relatively speaking), then people will care, 
otherwise they won't. Thus improving the lottery part of the method will 
improve the method in general - it'll make up the amount it no longer 
encourages people to determine the consensus, by just giving better results.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Hello Kristofer,

you wrote:
> However, my point was that Range goes further: a minority that acts
> in a certain way can get what it wants, too; all that's required is that
> the majority does not vote Approval style (either max or min) and that
> the minority does, and that the minority is not too small.
> 
> It is in that respect I mean that Range is more radical, because it
> permits a minority to overrule a majority that otherwise agrees about
> which candidates it prefers. For those who mean that elections have to
> be, at least, majoritarian, Range may contain a surprise.

That's true. Methods in which a group can suppress the rest are
certainly bad, even more so when the group can be small...

> You could probably devise a whole class of SEC-type methods. They would
> go: if there is a consensus (defined in some fashion), then it wins -
> otherwise, a nondeterministic strategy-free method is used to pick the
> winner. The advantage of yours is that it uses only Plurality ballots.

The hard point is, I think, to define what actually a potential
consensus option is. And here the idea was to say everything unanimously
preferred to some benchmark outcome qualifies as potential consensus.
The benchmark then cannot be any feasible option but must be a lottery
of some options, otherwise the supporters of the single option would
block the consensus. But which lottery you take as a benchmark could be
discussed. I chose the Random Ballot lottery since it seems the most
fair one and has all nice properties (strategy-freeness, proportional
allocation of power).

> I suppose the nondeterministic method would have to be "bad enough" to
> provide incentive to pick the right consensus, yet it shouldn't be so
> bad as to undermine the process itself if the voters really can't reach
> a consensus.

Although I can hardly imagine real-world situations in which no
consensus option can be found (maybe be combining different decisions
into one, or using some kind of compensation scheme if necessary).

> Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information
> from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with
> respect to Random Ballot? 

This sounds interesting, but what exactly do you mean by Random Pair?
Pick a randomly chosen pair of candidates and elect the pairwise winner
of them? I will think about this...

> It would lead to a better outcome if the
> consensus fails, but so also make it more likely that the consensus does
> fail. Or would it? The reasoning from a given participant's point of
> view is rather: do I get something *I* would like by refusing to take
> part in consensus -- not, does *society* get something acceptable.

I'm not sure I know what you mean here.

Yours, Jobst

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Jobst Heitzig wrote:

Dear Kristofer,

both Approval Voting and Range Voting *are* majoritarian: A majority
can always get their will and suppress the minority by simply bullet-voting.

So, a more interesting version of your question could be: Which
*democratic* method (that does not allow any sub-group to suppress the
rest) has (usually or on average or in the worst case) the least
Bayesian Regret.


Yes. A majority that acts in a certain way can get what it wants. That's 
true for Range and Approval, and it's true for Condorcet, Plurality, 
etc. However, my point was that Range goes further: a minority that acts 
in a certain way can get what it wants, too; all that's required is that 
the majority does not vote Approval style (either max or min) and that 
the minority does, and that the minority is not too small.


It is in that respect I mean that Range is more radical, because it 
permits a minority to overrule a majority that otherwise agrees about 
which candidates it prefers. For those who mean that elections have to 
be, at least, majoritarian, Range may contain a surprise.



I conjecture that at least when the nomination of additional options
is allowed, the method SEC described recently is a hot candidate for
this award, since it seems that SEC will lead to the election of the
option at the *mean* (instead of the median) voter position, and I guess
that in most spacial utility models the mean position is in many senses
"better" and will in particular have less Bayesian Regret than the
median position. (Recall that in a one-dimensional spacial model where
additional options can be nominated, all majoritarian methods likely
lead to median positions being realized and are thus basically all
equivalent.)


You could probably devise a whole class of SEC-type methods. They would 
go: if there is a consensus (defined in some fashion), then it wins - 
otherwise, a nondeterministic strategy-free method is used to pick the 
winner. The advantage of yours is that it uses only Plurality ballots.


I suppose the nondeterministic method would have to be "bad enough" to 
provide incentive to pick the right consensus, yet it shouldn't be so 
bad as to undermine the process itself if the voters really can't reach 
a consensus.


Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information 
from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with 
respect to Random Ballot? It would lead to a better outcome if the 
consensus fails, but so also make it more likely that the consensus does 
fail. Or would it? The reasoning from a given participant's point of 
view is rather: do I get something *I* would like by refusing to take 
part in consensus -- not, does *society* get something acceptable.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Matthew Welland
On Tuesday 10 November 2009 03:37:56 am Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
> Matthew Welland wrote:
> > So, to re-frame my question. What is the fatal flaw with approval? I'm
> > not interested in subtle flaws that result in imperfect results. I'm
> > interested in flaws that result in big problems such as those we see
> > with plurality and IRV.
>
> IMHO, it is that you need concurrent polling in order to consistently
> elect a good winner. If you don't have polling and thus don't know where
> to put the cutoff (between approve and not-approve), you'll face the
> Burr dilemma: If you prefer A > B > C, if you "approve" both A and B,
> you might get B instead of A, but if you "approve" only A, you might get
> C!

This seems to me to be a minor, not major, flaw.  Having to vote A & B to 
hedge your bets is not ideal but you might even be able to argue some 
benefits to it. A will see B as a serious threat and vice versa. They may 
make adjustments to their stands on issues to accommodate voters like you. 
Approval voting is enough to bring competition for votes back into the arena 
and I think it makes negative campaigning a very risky strategy. 

Also, again, your single vote is irrelevant. It is the aggregate of 
thousands or millions of votes that will make or break A vs. B. How many 
feel so strongly against A that they cannot vote for him or her?

The binary nature of approval is washed out by large numbers just as a class 
D amplifier can directly produce smooth analog waveforms out of a pure 1 or 0 
signal.

> Thus the kind of Approval that homes in on a good winner employs
> feedback. The method is no longer Approval alone, but Approval plus
> polling. That /can/ work (people approve {Nader, Gore} if Nader has
> fewer votes than Gore, so that Bush doesn't win from the split, but only
> approve either Nader or Gore if both are large), but why should we need
> to be burdened with the feedback?

Sure, in any real election there will be many dynamics at work. Feedback 
polls, debates etc. will all improve an election. Approval might benefit from 
feedback but I don't see why it becomes fatally flawed without it, only 
mildly flawed.

> Some, like Abd, argue that we always reason based on others' positions
> to know how much we can demand, and so that this is a feature rather
> than a bug. That doesn't quite sound right to me. In any event, if you
> want Approval + bargaining (which the feedback resolves to), make that
> claim. Approval alone, without feedback, will be subject to the flaws
> mentioned earlier, however.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Raph Frank
On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 10:37 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm
 wrote:
> IMHO, it is that you need concurrent polling in order to consistently elect
> a good winner. If you don't have polling and thus don't know where to put
> the cutoff (between approve and not-approve), you'll face the Burr dilemma:
> If you prefer A > B > C, if you "approve" both A and B, you might get B
> instead of A, but if you "approve" only A, you might get C!

However, the same logic can be applied to plurality voting.  If people
had to vote blind, then the results would be even worse.

History with plurality has shown that it is reasonable to expect
people to know who the top-2 candidates are.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Matthew Welland wrote:

So, to re-frame my question. What is the fatal flaw with approval? I'm 
not interested in subtle flaws that result in imperfect results. I'm 
interested in flaws that result in big problems such as those we see 
with plurality and IRV.


IMHO, it is that you need concurrent polling in order to consistently 
elect a good winner. If you don't have polling and thus don't know where 
to put the cutoff (between approve and not-approve), you'll face the 
Burr dilemma: If you prefer A > B > C, if you "approve" both A and B, 
you might get B instead of A, but if you "approve" only A, you might get C!


Thus the kind of Approval that homes in on a good winner employs 
feedback. The method is no longer Approval alone, but Approval plus 
polling. That /can/ work (people approve {Nader, Gore} if Nader has 
fewer votes than Gore, so that Bush doesn't win from the split, but only 
approve either Nader or Gore if both are large), but why should we need 
to be burdened with the feedback?


Some, like Abd, argue that we always reason based on others' positions 
to know how much we can demand, and so that this is a feature rather 
than a bug. That doesn't quite sound right to me. In any event, if you 
want Approval + bargaining (which the feedback resolves to), make that 
claim. Approval alone, without feedback, will be subject to the flaws 
mentioned earlier, however.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting

2009-11-08 Thread Warren Smith
OK, this is an attempt to reply to Robert Bristow-Johnson.

>WDS: For Condorcet systems with ranking-equalities
> allowed,
> they might behave better with strategic voters, though.  I've posted
> on that topic before.
>RBJ: ... so [range is] *not* always "better than every rank-order system for 
>...
>strategic voters".

--1. I meant Condorcet with equalities permitted might behave better
for strat voters than Condorcet without equalities permitted.
Everybody seems to think that but no full understanding is available.
2. By "rank order system" I meant, equalities not permitted.  A>B>C>D
is a rank ordering. A>B=C>D is not.
3. For a partial understanding of Condorcet with equalities permitted
and strategic voting, see puzzle #113 here:
http://rangevoting.org/PuzzlePage.html

>RBJ:
now the relationship that citizens of a community or nation have with
each other is not the same kind of trusting and sometimes blind
relationships we have with members of our families and other partners
(like business partners) that we end up trusting by default,
essentially in our own enlightened self-interest.  in general, we
have contracts and laws essentially intended in the best
circumstances to "keep honest people honest".  we have locked doors,...

--Range voting in no way "assumes" that everybody is trustworthy and
nonstrategic.
It is designed to behave comparatively well with strategists present.

>RBJ:
so Warren, you're gonna sell your system on the hope that in this
place of absolute privacy, we'll all be sincere. [Tons of other blather too.]

--huh?

>RBJ:
i want a system that offers nothing for the voter's political
interest for voting insincerely.

--It is known that no deterministic voting system using rank-order ballots, or
rank-order-with-equalities-permitted,
can satisfy this desire.  See http://rangevoting.org/GibbSat.html

Range and approval voting, however, are not of the above types.
They partially-evade this impossibility theorem.
I have a theorem (discussed at that web page) extending this
impossibility theorem
to wider class of voting systems.   In short you here are asking for
the impossible.

>RBJ:
but, save for the case of a
Condorcet cycle, i don't see how voting insincerely in a Condorcet-
decided race ever serves the political interest of the voter.

--That is merely because your vision is poor.  E.g. see
http://www.rangevoting.org/CondStratProb.html

> WDS: 3. The main perceived flaw in range voting is for strategic+honest
> voter MIXTURES
> and under the worrying assumption that who decides to be strategic, is
> CORRELATED with the politics of that voter.  Thus for example,
> strategic Bush voters could beat unstrategic Gore voters.  Problem
> isn't really much of a problem if the Bush strategy-fraction is the
> same as the Gore strategy fraction (a claim backed up by computer
> sims).
> RBJ: just like the issue of drawing random ballots in multi-winner PR STV
and counting on that as "representative", i wonder why counting on
computer simulation to support this balance of tactical voters would
be as trustworthy.

--you are confused.  The simulation did not "support this balance of
tactical voters."
It simply asked: if there is some fixed fraction F of strategic
voters, rest honest, then
how well does range perform (measured by Bayesian regret) and how well do other
systems perform?   It turns out range outperforms every rank-order system,
with 3-10 candidates, for example, for EVERY value of F.


> RBJ:
in other words, if in some election, one side has more politically
savvy strategists, advocates, and voters?  isn't that often how one
side wins and the other side loses?  one side has a Karl Rove and the
other side has John Kerry and one of his 3 serial campaign managers.
don't count on it not differing.

--You are correct in principle.   If one side has more-strategic
voters than another, it could win even though with equal strategy it
would lose. This can happen with range voting.  It also can happen
with lots of other systems.  Including Condorcet.
Including Condorcet in an election which (with honest voters) has no cycles.

However, we have to ask what happens in reality.  Is it actually true that
Karl Rove, by advising voters, will somehow come upon some amazing
insight that will cause Bush to win, while the other side's voters
will fail to reach that insight?
Is this realistic?In range voting, unlike Condorcet and IRV,
strategy is pretty simple.
Even you (RBJ) ought to be able to comprehend the basics of it.  Even
without any aid from Karl Rove.   And if Rove and Party Talking Heads
are busily telling everybody how to vote (which they will be) then
even if you did not have that level of intelligence, you'd
probably still get the idea.   Of course, somebody with IQ<50 might
still be unable to get it.  But I guess we have to ask: is it really
really important that people with IQ<50
must have equal voting influence?

Anyhow, unlike RBJ, I have actually enquired into the state of
reality, by 

Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-08 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Dear Kristofer,

both Approval Voting and Range Voting *are* majoritarian: A majority can always 
get their will and suppress the minority by simply bullet-voting.

So, a more interesting version of your question could be: Which *democratic* 
method (that does not allow any sub-group to suppress the rest) has (usually or 
on average or in the worst case) the least Bayesian Regret. 

I conjecture that at least when the nomination of additional options is 
allowed, the method SEC described recently is a hot candidate for this award, 
since it seems that SEC will lead to the election of the option at the *mean* 
(instead of the median) voter position, and I guess that in most spacial 
utility models the mean position is in many senses "better" and will in 
particular have less Bayesian Regret than the median position. (Recall that in 
a one-dimensional spacial model where additional options can be nominated, all 
majoritarian methods likely lead to median positions being realized and are 
thus basically all equivalent.)

Yours, Jobst

 
> -Ursprüngliche Nachricht-
> Von: "Kristofer Munsterhjelm" 
> Gesendet: 08.11.09 10:23:11
> An: Warren Smith 
> CC: election-methods 
> Betreff: Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and 
> range voting?


> Warren Smith wrote:
> >> It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the
> > strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal
> > improvement of other methods is fairly small. Can anyone point me to
> > analysis, preferably at a layman level, that contradicts or supports this
> > assertion?
> >> Or, in succinct terms, what are the strategic flaws in approval or range
> > voting?
> >> Thanks, Matthew Welland
> > 
> > --well... there is the whole rangevoting.org website...
> > my more-recent papers at
> > math.temple.edu/~wds/homepage/works.html
> > discuss range voting including some ways it is provably better than every
> > rank-order voting system for either honest or strategic voters...
> > 
> > --but those are not exactly "succinct"...
> > 
> > OK Let me try:
> > 1. Range for 100% honest voters behaves better than IRV, Borda,
> > Condorcet and it is pretty intuitively clear why -- strength of
> > preference info used, not discarded.
> 
> There is, of course, the flipside of that property. If one wants a 
> voting method where the majority wins, then Range won't work, simply 
> because a minority of strong opinions can outweigh a majority of weak 
> ones. You might argue that that is no bug at all (strong opinions 
> *should* outweigh weak ones), but for those for which Majority 
> compliance is a must-have, it should be mentioned - particularly since 
> that is supposed to be one aspect of the fairness of traditional democracy.
> 
> In that sense, moving to Range (and perhaps Approval - depends on how 
> you interpret it) is a more radical proposal than, for instance, moving 
> to Condorcet (which passes Majority).
> 
> (And now I wonder which election method that passes Majority has the 
> least Bayesian regret.)
> 
> Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
> 



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-08 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Warren Smith wrote:

It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the

strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal
improvement of other methods is fairly small. Can anyone point me to
analysis, preferably at a layman level, that contradicts or supports this
assertion?

Or, in succinct terms, what are the strategic flaws in approval or range

voting?

Thanks, Matthew Welland


--well... there is the whole rangevoting.org website...
my more-recent papers at
math.temple.edu/~wds/homepage/works.html
discuss range voting including some ways it is provably better than every
rank-order voting system for either honest or strategic voters...

--but those are not exactly "succinct"...

OK Let me try:
1. Range for 100% honest voters behaves better than IRV, Borda,
Condorcet and it is pretty intuitively clear why -- strength of
preference info used, not discarded.


There is, of course, the flipside of that property. If one wants a 
voting method where the majority wins, then Range won't work, simply 
because a minority of strong opinions can outweigh a majority of weak 
ones. You might argue that that is no bug at all (strong opinions 
*should* outweigh weak ones), but for those for which Majority 
compliance is a must-have, it should be mentioned - particularly since 
that is supposed to be one aspect of the fairness of traditional democracy.


In that sense, moving to Range (and perhaps Approval - depends on how 
you interpret it) is a more radical proposal than, for instance, moving 
to Condorcet (which passes Majority).


(And now I wonder which election method that passes Majority has the 
least Bayesian regret.)


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-07 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Nov 7, 2009, at 8:14 PM, Warren Smith wrote:



--well... there is the whole rangevoting.org website...
my more-recent papers at
math.temple.edu/~wds/homepage/works.html
discuss range voting including some ways it is provably better than  
every

rank-order voting system for either honest or strategic voters...


okay...


--but those are not exactly "succinct"...

OK Let me try:
1. Range for 100% honest voters behaves better than IRV, Borda,
Condorcet and it is pretty intuitively clear why -- strength of
preference info used, not discarded.

2. For 100% strategic voters Borda is a total disaster as is also
pretty obvious... far worse than approval voting...  but range voting
just degenerates basically to approval voting, which still works
pretty well since, e.g. it obeys the "favorite betrayal criterion."
If the strategic voters use "I'll exaggerate on the top two" naive
strategy (which in fact, in the real world, they pretty much do) then
Condorcet and IRV both degenerate
to strategic plurality voting, which is pretty obviously worse than
approval voting,
so range beats them.  For Condorcet systems with ranking-equalities  
allowed,

they might behave better with strategic voters, though.  I've posted
on that topic before.


... so *not* always "better than every rank-order system for ...  
strategic voters".


now the relationship that citizens of a community or nation have with  
each other is not the same kind of trusting and sometimes blind  
relationships we have with members of our families and other partners  
(like business partners) that we end up trusting by default,  
essentially in our own enlightened self-interest.  in general, we  
have contracts and laws essentially intended in the best  
circumstances to "keep honest people honest".  we have locked doors,  
secret credit card numbers and passwords that we don't share with  
even people we normally trust (they have no legitimate need for  
them).  essentially we rely on a system that does *not* rely on  
individual honesty in completely opaque, private, or confidential  
situations.  what if, instead of passing the offering plate around in  
full view, everybody gets to go into a private booth with the open  
plate (and not a secure drop box with a slot) and "add" their offering?


the guarantee that you and i have (at least in the US) is to vote in  
complete secrecy and security.  one *big* difference between any US  
election and what i have read for the UK is that there are no serial  
numbers on our ballots just in case there may be a legal ruling that  
someone was mistakenly allowed to vote in an election they weren't  
eligible to vote in that turned out to be critically close and  
contested.  i believe that i read, in the UK they can actually run  
the ballots through the scanning machine and yank an errant ballot  
and uncount it.  in Saddam's Iraq, there was an election in the 1990s  
where Saddam Hussein was re-elected with 99% of the vote, but the  
ballots there were also serialized and associated with the voter when  
issued and i'm surprized that even 1% felt it safe to vote against him.


but you can't do that in the US, and there *was* a case that went to  
the US Supreme Court that even Scalia voted the correct way on (and  
interestingly, his lapdog Thomas did not vote likewise).  in this  
case someone was discovered to live on the other side of the district  
or town line in some election.  when this was discovered, the person  
(and his wife, i think) was brought to court, everyone understood and  
acknowledged that these persons weren't supposed to vote in that  
election and the judge asked the guy what his vote was so they could  
uncount it and decide the election.  to the guy's credit of  
integrity, instead of lying and telling the judge exactly opposite  
(guaranteeing that his choice is elected), he tells the judge that he  
voted by secret ballot and refuses to say how, even though he was  
ordered to by the judge.  (i dunno what his wife did.)  anyway, the  
SCOTUS upheld that right.


every place i have lived and voted in the US (ND, IL, ME, NJ, NH, VT)  
had ballots with no serial number nor distinguishing marks on it when  
it ultimately went into the ballot box.  in IL i worked as a poll  
watcher, and watched the precinct officials open absentee envelopes,  
decide on their inclusion, and if included tossed an interior  
unmarked envelope onto a pile with others.  at that point, the  
inclusion or the ballot was committed because of its anonymity.  we  
have totally confidentiality with the content of our vote, but not  
with fact of whether we voted or not.


so Warren, you're gonna sell your system on the hope that in this  
place of absolute privacy, we'll all be sincere.  that i can count on  
the sincerity of voters who are political opponents just as they can  
count on my sincerity.


i want a system that offers nothing for the voter's political  
interest for voting insincerely.  i s'pose

[EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-07 Thread Warren Smith
>It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the
strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal
improvement of other methods is fairly small. Can anyone point me to
analysis, preferably at a layman level, that contradicts or supports this
assertion?
>Or, in succinct terms, what are the strategic flaws in approval or range
voting?
>Thanks, Matthew Welland

--well... there is the whole rangevoting.org website...
my more-recent papers at
math.temple.edu/~wds/homepage/works.html
discuss range voting including some ways it is provably better than every
rank-order voting system for either honest or strategic voters...

--but those are not exactly "succinct"...

OK Let me try:
1. Range for 100% honest voters behaves better than IRV, Borda,
Condorcet and it is pretty intuitively clear why -- strength of
preference info used, not discarded.

2. For 100% strategic voters Borda is a total disaster as is also
pretty obvious... far worse than approval voting...  but range voting
just degenerates basically to approval voting, which still works
pretty well since, e.g. it obeys the "favorite betrayal criterion."
If the strategic voters use "I'll exaggerate on the top two" naive
strategy (which in fact, in the real world, they pretty much do) then
Condorcet and IRV both degenerate
to strategic plurality voting, which is pretty obviously worse than
approval voting,
so range beats them.  For Condorcet systems with ranking-equalities allowed,
they might behave better with strategic voters, though.  I've posted
on that topic before.

3. The main perceived flaw in range voting is for strategic+honest
voter MIXTURES
and under the worrying assumption that who decides to be strategic, is
CORRELATED with the politics of that voter.  Thus for example,
strategic Bush voters could beat unstrategic Gore voters.  Problem
isn't really much of a problem if the Bush strategy-fraction is the
same as the Gore strategy fraction (a claim backed up by computer
sims). It is only if they differ.

4. I'm unaware of any evidence from the real world that Bushy and
Gorey voters really are any different strategically with range voting.
   However, there is evidence that
Nader voters are less strategic and more honest.  (Not surprisingly
since voting Nader
in the USA *was* unstrategic.)   However, the evidence from the real
world is that all political types of range voters are substantially
honest, i.e.only a small fraction vote approval-style, and this causes
Nader, despite this relative disadvantage, to do a lot better with
range voting than he does with approval voting.


-- 
Warren D. Smith
http://RangeVoting.org  <-- add your endorsement (by clicking
"endorse" as 1st step)
and
math.temple.edu/~wds/homepage/works.html

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-07 Thread Raph Frank
On Sat, Nov 7, 2009 at 10:57 PM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm
 wrote:
>> The recommended strategy in approval is to approve one of the top 2
>> and also any other candidates who are above your approval threshold.
>
> That's strategy T. Some times (see Rob LeGrand's dissertation defense
> slides) a "strategy A" is better: approve all that you like better than
> whoever's getting the most Plurality votes, and approve of him as well if
> you prefer him to the one in second place on the Plurality count.

Strategy A, as you defined it, is almost equivalent to just setting
the threshold to the utility of the expected winner.

> (I think it's a Plurality count. Late here, so "vote-getter" may refer to
> Approval votes - I'm not sure.)

I don't think that actually matters much.  They should be roughly the same.

The main point is that the top-2 candidates are the 2 candidates who
are most likely to tie, so you should approve one of them and not the
other.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-07 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Raph Frank wrote:

On Sat, Nov 7, 2009 at 8:12 PM, Matthew Welland  wrote:

It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the
strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal
improvement of other methods is fairly small.


The recommended strategy in approval is to approve one of the top 2
and also any other candidates who are above your approval threshold.


That's strategy T. Some times (see Rob LeGrand's dissertation defense 
slides) a "strategy A" is better: approve all that you like better than 
whoever's getting the most Plurality votes, and approve of him as well 
if you prefer him to the one in second place on the Plurality count.


(I think it's a Plurality count. Late here, so "vote-getter" may refer 
to Approval votes - I'm not sure.)


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-07 Thread Raph Frank
On Sat, Nov 7, 2009 at 8:12 PM, Matthew Welland  wrote:
> It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the
> strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal
> improvement of other methods is fairly small.

The recommended strategy in approval is to approve one of the top 2
and also any other candidates who are above your approval threshold.

The threshold is not so important, as it is likely that one of the top
2 will win, so that approval is the only one that matters.

You should approve all you prefer to the best of the top 2 and should
never approve someone you like less than the worst of the top-2.

Some possible thresholds

- approve all you prefer to the expected winner
- approve all you prefer to the expected utility of the election
- approve all you prefer to the best of the top 2
- approve all you prefer to the worst of the top 2

I prefer to the first first one as it will results in the condorcet
winner winning the election if there are accurate polls.

As long as voters know who are the contenders, then approval strategy
is pretty easy.

Where there are 3 contenders, there is still some issue with regard to
handling the middle candidate.  The voter would need to make a call
about which tie was more likely and also the differences in utility.

Also, strategy isn't necessarily a bad thing.

The problem with plurality is that it converges on the 2 party system.

It is a Nash equilibrium.

If you could go through each voter after an election and ask them if
they want to change their vote, most of them wouldn't.

It would normally just reduce the margin or victory for their
favourite of the top-2.

However, with approval, you can have a sequence that goes like:

A and B are the top 2, but C is the condorcet winning candidate.

Voters follow the policy that they will approve one of the top 2 and
any candidate they prefer to the expected winner.

Since every voter will only vote for one of A and B (since they are
the top-2), one of them must end up with less than 50% of the vote.

C is the condorcet winner, so he is preferred to whoever is the
expected winner by at least half of the voters.

Thus the first poll will show something like

A: 45
B: 55
C: 51

Thus C will suddenly be one of the top-2.

This might take a few polls, but as C gets more press reports, his
percentage will increase.

Once he is one of the top-2, he cannot be displaced.  No matter who is
the other one, he will be preferred to that candidate by more than
50%.

Also, once he is one of the top 2, any voters who prefer him to all
other candidates will suddenly stop approving either of A or B.  Thus
one of them will drop in popularity.


The point is that it isn't strategy that is the problem.  It is that
strategy results in the voters ending up with the the better of 2
evils.

With approval, the result is that a condorcet winner should normally
win, so any strategy results in a fair result.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-07 Thread Jonathan Lundell

On Nov 7, 2009, at 12:12 PM, Matthew Welland wrote:


It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the
strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal
improvement of other methods is fairly small. Can anyone point me to
analysis, preferably at a layman level, that contradicts or supports  
this

assertion?

Or, in succinct terms, what are the strategic flaws in approval or  
range

voting?


Voting in either one is fundamentally strategic.

Take the simple case of casting an approval ballot with three  
candidates where your ordinal preference is A>B>C. Obviously you vote  
for A and not for C. The strategic question is whether you vote for B.  
Voting for B might cause B to beat A, but on the other hand it could  
cause B to beat C (depending of course on the other voters).


Presumably your decision to vote for B or not will be driven by your  
best guess as to which of those is more likely, and might also be  
influenced by whether your preference is more like A>>B>C or A>B>>C.  
The closer you are to A=B>C or A>B=C (and the better your information  
about other voters, say from pre-election polling), the easier that  
decision might be, but it's a strategic decision.


I suppose that I end up more or less in the same came as RB-J, except  
that I (mildly) prefer STV to Condorcet methods. In either of those,  
it's easy to cast a sincere ballot, and it's usually a good, or at  
least acceptable, strategy to do that. With approval or range, you  
don't really have that option: every ballot is inherently a strategic  
one.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-07 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Nov 7, 2009, at 3:12 PM, Matthew Welland wrote:


It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the
strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal
improvement of other methods is fairly small. Can anyone point me to
analysis, preferably at a layman level, that contradicts or  
supports this

assertion?

Or, in succinct terms, what are the strategic flaws in approval or  
range

voting?


this is no published analysis, but it should qualify as layman  
level.  this is why i don't like either approval or range voting in a  
governmental election.


in a sentence: Approval Voting does not collect enough information  
from voters and Range Voting requires too much.


since any of these methods we discuss here really exist for the  
purpose of dealing with more than two candidates (if there are  
exactly two candidates no one really disagrees about what to do)  
let's see if we have to do with multiple candidates.  in fact we can  
use the 2009 mayoral election in Burlington VT as an object lesson.


we have Candidate A (we'll call "Andy"), Candidate B (we'll call  
"Bob"), Candidate C (we'll call "Curtis", but in Burlington his name  
was Kurt), and candidate D (we'll call Dan).


Approval Voting: so i approve of Andy and Bob, maybe Dan (not likely)  
and definitely not Kurt (err "Curtis", candidate C).  but, if the  
election comes down to Andy vs. Bob, i want to register my preference  
for Andy.  how do i do that?  so then i'm thinking (tactically) that  
the Bob supporters aren't gonna be reciprocating with an approval  
vote for Andy, so what do i do if i really support Andy, am willing  
to settle for Bob, but really want Andy.  i will agonize over the  
decision and likely just vote approval for Andy, just like i would in  
a traditional FPTP election.  but then there is no information coming  
from me that i prefer Bob a helluva lot more than i approve of  
Curtis.  so Approval Voting has not relieved me, as a voter, from the  
need to consider tactics, if i want my vote to be effective.


Range Voting:  so i have 100 points that i can distribute among the 4  
candidates.  well definitely Candidate C ("Curtis", really Kurt) gets  
zero of my points.  i might toss Dan 5 points, but i would likely not  
waste them.  so how do i divide my points between Andy and Bob?  i  
like them both, but prefer Andy over Bob, so what do i do?  i have to  
think tactically again.  are the Bob supporters gonna be tossing any  
points to Andy?  i can't trust that they will, they will probably  
just put all of their support for the candidate that they are  
behind.  if i want my vote to compete effectively with theirs, i will  
end up putting all 100 points behind my candidate Andy.  so, if we  
have any political identification at all, my vote under Range will  
convey no more information than it would with FPTP.


IRV, Condorcet, and Borda, use the simple ranked-order ballot where  
we say who we support first (candidate A for me), who is our second  
choice (candidate B), who is our third choice (candidate D for me)  
and who is our last choice (candidate C for me).  so if the election  
was just between A and B, we know that this voter (me) would vote for  
A.  if the election was just between B and D, we know this voter  
would vote for B.  if the election was between C and D, we know this  
voter would choose D.  of course, for a single voter (not necessarily  
for the aggregation of votes) there is no circular preference, we  
know that if the election was between A and D, this voter would vote  
for A.  we know that this voter would vote for B if the election was  
between B and C.  and we know that this voter would vote for A if it  
were between A and C.  from that simple ranked-order ballot, we know  
how the voter would vote between any selected pair of candidates in  
the hypothetical two-candidate election between those two.


of course IRV, Condorcet, and Borda use different methods to tabulate  
the votes and select the winner and my opinion is that IRV ("asset  
voting", i might call it "commodity voting": your vote is a  
"commodity" that you transfer according to your preferences) is a  
kabuki dance of transferred votes.  and there is an *arbitrary*  
evaluation in the elimination of candidates in the IRV rounds: 2nd- 
choice votes don't count for shit in deciding who to eliminate (who  
decided that?  2nd-choice votes are as good as last-choice?  under  
what meaningful and consistent philosophy was that decided?), then  
when your candidate is eliminated your 2nd-choice vote counts as much  
as your 1st-choice.


i don't like Borda because it has another arbitrary valuation.  the  
difference in score between your 1st and 2nd choice is the same as  
the difference in score between your 2nd and 3rd choice.  but what  
eternal value is that based on?  what if i like my 1st and 2nd choice  
almost equally, but think my 3rd choice is a piece of crap?  (this is  

[EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-07 Thread Matthew Welland
It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the 
strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal 
improvement of other methods is fairly small. Can anyone point me to 
analysis, preferably at a layman level, that contradicts or supports this 
assertion?

Or, in succinct terms, what are the strategic flaws in approval or range 
voting? 

Thanks,

Matt
-=-

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info