Re: [Election-Methods] method design challenge + new method AMP

2008-05-09 Thread Juho

On May 9, 2008, at 10:46 , Jobst Heitzig wrote:


Dear Raphfrk

you wrote:

One issue with random processes is that they don't work well for a
legislature. A majority would just keep asking that the vote be
repeated until they win it.
Saying that a re-vote cannot occur unless the situation changes would
require that a definition of a change in the situation be decided.


Alternatively, laws could be considered social contracts which have  
a duration and certain terms of termination which would have to be  
met by any later decisions to change the law.



Also, people have a certain level of distrust for random processes.
I don't think people would accept a President who was elected even
though he only had a 1% chance of winning. I am not sure what the
threshold is before it would be acceptable (some people would object
to a 49% candidate winning instead of a 51% candidate).


This is probably true. I would not recommend such a method for  
elections of Presidents or the like but for bodies who frequently  
make individual decisions on issues.


Probabilistic methods are actually proportional methods (at least if  
they aim at giving n% probability to a candidate with n% support,  
or some other probabilities that the voters like more). I don't know  
what the other (non-proportional) methods should be called here since  
dictatorship of majority is not valid in this particular case.  
Maybe always elect the best (according to some criterion) is more  
accurate.


Juho



Yours, Jobst


__ 
_

EINE FÜR ALLE: die kostenlose WEB.DE-Plattform für Freunde und Deine
Homepage mit eigenem Namen. Jetzt starten! http://unddu.de/? 
[EMAIL PROTECTED]






___ 
The all-new Yahoo! Mail goes wherever you go - free your email address from your Internet provider. http://uk.docs.yahoo.com/nowyoucan.html



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [Election-Methods] method design challenge +new method AMP

2008-05-09 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Dear Juho,

you wrote:
 Yes, but as I see it the reasons are different. In a typical non-
 deterministic method like random ballot I think it is the intention
 to give all candidates with some support also some probability of
 becoming elected. 

Not at all! At least in those non-deterministic methods which I design 
the goal is to make it probable that the voters implement a strategic 
equilibrium in which a compromise option (instead of the favourite of a 
mere majority) will be elected with (near) certainty. But for such an 
equilibrium to exist in the first place, the method cannot be 
majoritarian, since then the majority would have no incentive at all to 
cooperate. Instead, all voters must have some power, not only those 
belonging to the majority, and therefore each voter is given control 
over an equal amount of winning probability. Still, the goal is not 
that they assign this amount to their favourite option but that they 
trade it in some controlled way, in order to elect a compromise which 
makes all the cooperating voters better off than without the trading!

Since at the same time, voting shall be secret, the trading cannot be 
expected to be performed by open negotiations between the voters, but 
it must be facilitated by some mechanism which trades winning 
probabilities automatically depending on the preference information on 
the voters' ballots.

If then in certain situations it happens that not much trading actually 
takes place, so that the winning probabilities remain with the voters' 
favourites, then this is only an indication that no sufficiently 
attractive compromise options existed in that situation. But whenever 
such an option does exist, the goal of non-deterministic methods like 
DFC, D2MAC, and AMP is that voters recognize that they are better off 
with the compromise than with the benchmark Random Ballot solution, and 
that they can bring about the election of the compromise by safely 
indicating their willingness to trade their share of the winning 
probability, without running the risk of being cheated by the other 
faction(s). 

D2MAC is quite good at this if only the compromise option is 
sufficiently attractive, but not in a situation which is as narrow as 
the one I gave at the beginning of this thread. AMP is better there, 
but it is not monotonic unfortunately.

Yours, Jobst


 In the deterministic methods electing some non- 
 popular extremist is typically an unwanted feature and a result of
 the method somehow failing to elect the best winner.

  *No* election or decision method should be applied without first
  checking the feasibility of options with respect to certain basic
  requirements. This sorting out the constitutional options cannot
  be subject to a group decision process itself since often the
  unconstitutional options have broad support (Hitler is only the
  most extreme example for this).
 
  In other words, without such a feasibility check *before* deciding,
  also majoritarian methods can produce a very bad outcome (think of
  Rwanda...).

 Ok, this looks like an intermediate method where one first has one
 method (phase 1) that selects a set of acceptable candidates and then
 uses some other method (phase 2) (maybe non-deterministic) to elect
 the winner from that set.

 There is need for pure non-deterministic methods like random ballot,
 and pure deterministic methods, and also combinations of different
 methods may be useful.

 Also in the case where the no-good candidates are first eliminated I
 see the same two different philosophies on how the remaining
 candidates are handled. Either all remaining candidates (with some
 support) are given some probability or alternatively one always tries
 to elect the best winner. The intention was thus not to say non-
 deterministic methods would not work properly but that there are two
 philosophies that are quite different and that may be used in
 different elections depending on the nature of the election.

 Due to this difference I'm interested in finding both deterministic
 and non-deterministic solutions for the challenge.

 Juho

  Yours, Jobst
  ___
 ___ _
  EINE FÜR ALLE: die kostenlose WEB.DE-Plattform für Freunde und
  Deine Homepage mit eigenem Namen. Jetzt starten! http://unddu.de/?
  [EMAIL PROTECTED]

 ___
 Inbox full of spam? Get leading spam protection and 1GB storage with
 All New Yahoo! Mail. http://uk.docs.yahoo.com/nowyoucan.html

 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list
 info


pgpUbFPDuaKZJ.pgp
Description: PGP signature

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [Election-Methods] method design challenge +new method AMP

2008-05-09 Thread Juho

On May 9, 2008, at 20:27 , Jobst Heitzig wrote:


Dear Juho,

you wrote:

Yes, but as I see it the reasons are different. In a typical non-
deterministic method like random ballot I think it is the intention
to give all candidates with some support also some probability of
becoming elected.


Not at all! At least in those non-deterministic methods which I design
the goal is to make it probable that the voters implement a strategic
equilibrium in which a compromise option (instead of the favourite  
of a

mere majority) will be elected with (near) certainty.


Ok, there are also such methods (more complex than basic random  
ballot). I interpreted the stronger than majoritarianism search of  
a compromise candidate to be an additional requirement that  
determines one subclass of (deterministic and nondeterministic)  
election methods.


Juho



But for such an
equilibrium to exist in the first place, the method cannot be
majoritarian, since then the majority would have no incentive at  
all to

cooperate. Instead, all voters must have some power, not only those
belonging to the majority, and therefore each voter is given control
over an equal amount of winning probability. Still, the goal is not
that they assign this amount to their favourite option but that they
trade it in some controlled way, in order to elect a compromise  
which

makes all the cooperating voters better off than without the trading!

Since at the same time, voting shall be secret, the trading cannot be
expected to be performed by open negotiations between the voters, but
it must be facilitated by some mechanism which trades winning
probabilities automatically depending on the preference information on
the voters' ballots.

If then in certain situations it happens that not much trading  
actually

takes place, so that the winning probabilities remain with the voters'
favourites, then this is only an indication that no sufficiently
attractive compromise options existed in that situation. But whenever
such an option does exist, the goal of non-deterministic methods like
DFC, D2MAC, and AMP is that voters recognize that they are better off
with the compromise than with the benchmark Random Ballot solution,  
and

that they can bring about the election of the compromise by safely
indicating their willingness to trade their share of the winning
probability, without running the risk of being cheated by the other
faction(s).

D2MAC is quite good at this if only the compromise option is
sufficiently attractive, but not in a situation which is as narrow as
the one I gave at the beginning of this thread. AMP is better there,
but it is not monotonic unfortunately.

Yours, Jobst



In the deterministic methods electing some non-
popular extremist is typically an unwanted feature and a result of
the method somehow failing to elect the best winner.


*No* election or decision method should be applied without first
checking the feasibility of options with respect to certain basic
requirements. This sorting out the constitutional options cannot
be subject to a group decision process itself since often the
unconstitutional options have broad support (Hitler is only the
most extreme example for this).

In other words, without such a feasibility check *before* deciding,
also majoritarian methods can produce a very bad outcome (think of
Rwanda...).


Ok, this looks like an intermediate method where one first has one
method (phase 1) that selects a set of acceptable candidates and then
uses some other method (phase 2) (maybe non-deterministic) to elect
the winner from that set.

There is need for pure non-deterministic methods like random ballot,
and pure deterministic methods, and also combinations of different
methods may be useful.

Also in the case where the no-good candidates are first eliminated I
see the same two different philosophies on how the remaining
candidates are handled. Either all remaining candidates (with some
support) are given some probability or alternatively one always tries
to elect the best winner. The intention was thus not to say non-
deterministic methods would not work properly but that there are two
philosophies that are quite different and that may be used in
different elections depending on the nature of the election.

Due to this difference I'm interested in finding both deterministic
and non-deterministic solutions for the challenge.

Juho


Yours, Jobst
___
___ _
EINE FÜR ALLE: die kostenlose WEB.DE-Plattform für Freunde und
Deine Homepage mit eigenem Namen. Jetzt starten! http://unddu.de/?
[EMAIL PROTECTED]


___
Inbox full of spam? Get leading spam protection and 1GB storage with
All New Yahoo! Mail. http://uk.docs.yahoo.com/nowyoucan.html


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list
info







Re: [Election-Methods] method design challenge + new method AMP

2008-05-08 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Dear Juho,

you wrote:
 One observation on clone independence and electing a centrist
 candidate using rankings only and when one of the extremists has
 majority.
...
 It is thus impossible for the algorithm in this case and
 with this information (rankings only) to satisfy both requirements
 and to be fully clone independent.

D'accord. This is a good reason to consider rankings insufficient, since 
from rankings only one cannot determine whether to apparent clones are 
truly clones in the sense that they are (nearly) equivalent in all 
relevant aspects.

From ratings information, however, one can see this. Therefore I would 
not at all consider A1,A2 clones in your ratings example:
 A=100 C=55 B=0 = A1=100 A2=56 C=54 B=0
 B=100 C=55 A=0 = B=100 C=56 A1=54 A2=0

For A1,A2 to be considered clones, the ratings would have to be 
something like
51: A1 100  A2 99  C 55  B 0
49: B 100  C 55  A1 1  A2 0

You also seem to think so, since you wrote:
 One approach to try to avoid this problem would be to use a more
 limited clone concept: candidates that are ranked/rated equal with
 each others.

But that would never really occur in practice. I think one should define 
the notion clone like this: A1,A2 are clones if and only if on each 
ballot, the difference in ratings between any pair of options is 
smallest for the pair A1,A2. 

(Analogously, a set S of options should be called a clone set if and 
only if on each ballot, all rating differences between two options in S 
are smaller than all rating differences between other pairs of options. 
Even more generally, a system Y of disjoint sets S1,...,Sk of options 
could be called a clone partition if and only if on each ballot, all 
rating differences between two options which are contained in the same 
member of Y are smaller than all rating differences between other pairs 
of options.)

With this definition, the problem you described cannot really occur: 
Assume the rankings are
 51: X1X2X3X4
 49: X4X3X2X1
If X1,X2 are clones, X2 cannot be considered a good compromise since 49 
voters don't like her. Similarly, if X3,X4 are clones, X3 cannot be 
considered a good compromise since 51 voters don't like her.

Yours, Jobst


pgp9sEhTbdSjT.pgp
Description: PGP signature

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [Election-Methods] method design challenge + new method AMP

2008-05-08 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Dear Raphfrk,

you wrote
 There needs to be some system for providing an incentive for people
 to give their honest ratings.? A random system with trading seems
 like a reasonable solution.

I am glad that I am no longer alone with this opinion...

 If a majority has a 100% chance of getting their candidate elected,
 then there is no incentive for them to trade.? If the voters are 100%
 strategic, they will know this.

Yes, although some Range Voting supporters try hard to convince us of 
the opposite, it seems.

 OTOH, a support of a majority should be better than support of a
 minority.

Absolutely! Usually I consider Random Ballot a benchmark method for 
this very reason: the default winning probability of a candidate 
should equal the proportion of the voter who favour her. Any deviances 
from this default distribution should be justified somehow, for example 
by an increase in some measure of social utility. 

(The underlying rationale for methods like D2MAC or AMP is even 
stronger: every voter should have full control over her share of the 
winning probability, so that in particular when she bullet votes, this 
share must goes to her favourite. Only such methods are truly 
democratic.)

 Optimal utility via trade requires that voters have something to
 trade, and fractions of a win probability seems to be quite a
 reasonable solution.

I cannot really imagine any other thing unless we consider money 
transfers...

Yours, Jobst


pgpQdRGiMeeWy.pgp
Description: PGP signature

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [Election-Methods] method design challenge + new method AMP

2008-05-08 Thread Juho

On May 9, 2008, at 0:56 , Jobst Heitzig wrote:


For A1,A2 to be considered clones, the ratings would have to be
something like
51: A1 100  A2 99  C 55  B 0
49: B 100  C 55  A1 1  A2 0



Could be also e.g.
A  C 99  B 0
and after inserting the clones
A1 100  A2 99  C 98  B 0

There are thus many cases where separating clones from non-clones is  
not easy. In this example also the number of rating levels impacts  
the outcome.



You also seem to think so, since you wrote:

One approach to try to avoid this problem would be to use a more
limited clone concept: candidates that are ranked/rated equal with
each others.


But that would never really occur in practice. I think one should  
define

the notion clone like this: A1,A2 are clones if and only if on each
ballot, the difference in ratings between any pair of options is
smallest for the pair A1,A2.


Yes, this is one possible definition (that can be used to formulate  
the clone criterion).


Juho








___ 
All new Yahoo! Mail The new Interface is stunning in its simplicity and ease of use. - PC Magazine 
http://uk.docs.yahoo.com/nowyoucan.html



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [Election-Methods] method design challenge + new method AMP

2008-05-08 Thread Juho

On May 9, 2008, at 1:09 , Jobst Heitzig wrote:


Usually I consider Random Ballot a benchmark method for
this very reason: the default winning probability of a candidate
should equal the proportion of the voter who favour her. Any deviances
from this default distribution should be justified somehow, for  
example

by an increase in some measure of social utility.


I commented this point also in my reply to raphfrk. Random ballot is  
a perfect benchmark for many elections. But there are also  
elections that should be benchmarked against different methods /  
criteria. Sometimes the intention is to elect a candidate that is  
e.g. considered to be a good compromise, and one could e.g.  
intentionally try to avoid electing extremists.


It would be good to always make it clear what kind of election method  
one is looking for. Both probability based and deterministic  
methods are needed.


Juho





___ 
Now you can scan emails quickly with a reading pane. Get the new Yahoo! Mail. http://uk.docs.yahoo.com/nowyoucan.html



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [Election-Methods] method design challenge + new method AMP

2008-05-05 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

I wanted to consider this afresh.

At 01:58 PM 4/28/2008, Jobst Heitzig wrote:

Hello folks,

over the last months I have again and again tried to find a solution to
a seemingly simple problem:

The Goal
-
Find a group decision method which will elect C with near certainty in
the following situation:
- There are three options A,B,C
- There are 51 voters who prefer A to B, and 49 who prefer B to A.
- All voters prefer C to a lottery in which their favourite has 51%
probability and the other faction's favourite has 49% probability.
- Both factions are strategic and may coordinate their voting behaviour.


First of all, a method which elects C unambiguously from these 
conditions is problematic. This is a very close election, but the 
majority prefer A. Voters, however, may not like taking risks; for 
the A voters to purely shoot for an A victory is very dangerous, slip 
up and they get B. As stated, there is no way to know who is the best 
winner from the SU measure, which, however, Jobst fixes:



Those of you who like cardinal utilities may assume the following:
51: A 100  C 52  B 0
49: B 100  C 52  A 0


That's down in the noise, however.


Note that Range Voting would meet the goal if the voters would be
assumed to vote honestly instead of strategically. With strategic
voters, however, Range Voting will elect A.


That depends on their knowledge. If this is a zero-knowledge 
situation, and they vote according to personal expected outcome 
maximization, and it is Range 100, all voters will vote C 52. Which 
shows up to problems: human beings don't have preferences that fine, 
unless special abstractions allow them to assign precise utilities, 
such as known monetary return from outcomes.


However, all voters would vote, in Range 2 and Range 10, C as 
midrange. In Range 2, this would give us A 5100, B: 5000, C:4900. A 
wins. But with Range 100, and assuming, instead, that 52% is the 
*average* sincere rating, which makes more sense than assuming they 
are uniform, they would, if it's zero-knowledge and they vote 
intelligently to maximize personal utility, elect B. The certainty of 
this increases with the number of voters.


Contrary to Jobst's first intuition, Range *does* satisfy this, if 
the resolution is adequate.


Imagine a continuum of voters who are described, in sum, as above. 
The numbers Jobst gives for the C utility are averages. Given that 
all voters vote strategically, all voters vote the extremes. So the 
only question is how they will rate C.


The claim is often made that strategic voters in Range will bullet 
vote. However, a bullet vote risks the election of the least-desired 
candidate. The issue is often complicated by Range critics by 
aasuming some weak utility, then assuming that the voter will, 
knee-jerk, bullet vote for the favorite, as if the voter is strongly 
motivated. What has been done is to assume two contradictory voter 
utilities: a weak one and a strong one. A voter who votes, say, a 
straight party ticket, without regard for the individual candidates, 
has a strong utility for the party's candidate, not a weak one. Very 
strong. Only if you grab this voter by the scruff and shake him and 
say, No, you are not going to elect Abe Lincoln. Now that we have 
settled that, and stricken Lincoln's name from the ballot, whom do 
you prefer, Adolf Hitler or Josef Stalin? Never mind that the 
voter's response may well be a serious abstention, caused by rapidly 
leaving the jurisdiction in question. If the voter has any sense and 
is able to do so.


If we assume that the voters exist in a curve such that 52 is the 
median vote (as well as the average one), and they vote 
strategically, using the best game theory to do so, Approval probably 
satisfies the problem. At 50% utility, bullet voting and voting for 
two are exactly matched, take your pick, if there are enough voters. 
(When I studied this in detail, I found that bullet voting was 
slightly better in expected outcome, but it was only with very small 
numbers of voters. With many voters, they are equal. But if the 
expected utility is higher than 50%, in Approval, the zero-knowledge 
strategic vote is to vote for both. And a lot of words have been 
written to the contrary without actually studying the game matrix and 
election probabilities.)


If the median vote is 52, what is the average vote, if voters can 
only vote 0 or 100? (Approval). Under the strategic voting 
assumption, it would surely be above 50. And probably more than 1% 
above, with high certainty, but I haven't done the exact math, and 
the shape of the curve is not precisely stated.


If they can vote Range 100, and if they know their utilities and the 
math and vote strategically, they vote their average vote, which, if 
the bell curve is symmetrical, would probably be 52. C wins.


Why is this contrary to what so many have written? Well, zero knowledge.

So let's look at the opposite extreme? Perfect knowledge. Range 100. 
But there is a 

[Election-Methods] method design challenge + new method AMP

2008-04-28 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Hello folks,

over the last months I have again and again tried to find a solution to
a seemingly simple problem:

The Goal
-
Find a group decision method which will elect C with near certainty in
the following situation:
- There are three options A,B,C
- There are 51 voters who prefer A to B, and 49 who prefer B to A.
- All voters prefer C to a lottery in which their favourite has 51%
probability and the other faction's favourite has 49% probability.
- Both factions are strategic and may coordinate their voting behaviour.


Those of you who like cardinal utilities may assume the following:
51: A 100  C 52  B 0
49: B 100  C 52  A 0

Note that Range Voting would meet the goal if the voters would be
assumed to vote honestly instead of strategically. With strategic
voters, however, Range Voting will elect A.

As of now, I know of only one method that will solve the problem (and
unfortunately that method is not monotonic): it is called AMP and is
defined below.


*** So, I ask everyone to design some ***
*** method that meets the above goal! ***


Have fun,
Jobst


Method AMP (approval-seeded maximal pairings)
-

Ballot:

a) Each voter marks one option as her favourite option and may name
any number of offers. An offer is an (ordered) pair of options
(y,z). by offering (y,z) the voter expresses that she is willing to
transfer her share of the winning probability from her favourite x to
the compromise z if a second voter transfers his share of the winning
probability from his favourite y to this compromise z.
(Usually, a voter would agree to this if she prefers z to tossing a
coin between her favourite and y).

b) Alternatively, a voter may specify cardinal ratings for all options.
Then the highest-rated option x is considered the voter's favourite,
and each option-pair (y,z) for with z is higher rated that the mean
rating of x and y is considered an offer by this voter.

c) As another, simpler alternative, a voter may name only a favourite
option x and any number of also approved options. Then each
option-pair (y,z) for which z but not y is also approved is considered
an offer by this voter.


Tally:

1. For each option z, the approval score of z is the number of voters
who offered (y,z) with any y.

2. Start with an empty urn and by considering all voters free for
cooperation.

3. For each option z, in order of descending approval score, do the
following:

3.1. Find the largest set of voters that can be divvied up into disjoint
voter-pairs {v,w} such that v and w are still free for cooperation, v
offered (y,z), and w offered (x,z), where x is v's favourite and y is
w's favourite.

3.2. For each voter v in this largest set, put a ball labelled with the
compromise option z in the urn and consider v no longer free for
cooperation.

4. For each voter who still remains free for cooperation after this was
done for all options, put a ball labelled with the favourite option of
that voter in the urn.

5. Finally, the winning option is determined by drawing a ball from the
urn.

(In rare cases, some tiebreaker may be needed in step 3 or 3.1.)


Why this meets the goal: In the described situation, the only strategic
equilibrium is when all B-voters offer (A,C) and at least 49 of the
A-voters offer (B,C). As a result, AMP will elect C with 98%
probability, and A with 2% probability.




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info