Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-29 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Nov 29, 2009, at 6:37 PM, James Gilmour wrote:


Robert Bristow-Johnson wrote (9 Nov 2009):

Of course IRV, Condorcet, and Borda use different methods  to  
tabulate

the votes and select the winner and my opinion is that IRV (asset
voting, I might call it commodity voting: your vote is a
commodity that you transfer according to your preferences) is a
kabuki dance of transferred votes.  and there is an *arbitrary*
evaluation in the elimination of candidates in the IRV rounds: 2nd-
choice votes don't count for shit in deciding who to eliminate (who
decided that?  2nd-choice votes are as good as last-choice?  under
what meaningful and consistent philosophy was that decided?), then
when your candidate is eliminated your 2nd-choice vote counts as  
much

as your 1st-choice.


These statements suggest a misunderstanding of how STV voting works  
and what preferences (US rankings) mean in the STV voting

system.


i know earlier someone (it might've been James, i dunno) wrote that  
STV (i think that's what it's called in Australia) is called IRV  
in the US.  i dunno to what extent that is true, but assuming it is,  
i understand exactly how IRV works as used by a few municipalities in  
the US, specifically what was used in Burlington VT which i think is  
identical to how it is in Cambridge MA, SF CA, someplace in NC, and  
Mpls/StP MN.  to how the method works in Australia, i do not know  
first hand.


also, i case you're interested, i voted for IRV for Burlington in  
2005 (it has been used in two elections since), and in the referendum  
it faces this coming spring, i'll likely vote against recalling  
(abolishing in favor of the FPTP/delayed_runoff we had before) IRV.   
the issue to me is that the single-transferrable vote (as done in our  
domestic IRV) is the wrong algorithm to tabulate the votes in a multi- 
candidate election where no candidate gets a majority of 1st-pick votes.



  In all STV elections, the preferences are contingency choices.


that is true.  i fully support a contingency choice is multi-party/ 
multi-candidate elections.



  Your vote is transferred to your second choice only in the
event that your first choice cannot secure election or does not  
need you support to secure election.


that is *one* way to use the information of the contingency choices.   
if you are working out a complex problem with multiple directions of  
interest (which an election with more than 2 sincere candidates would  
be), you don't necessarily quantify votes as a commodity with some  
fixed value, and then, as i still point out, transfer these  
commodities around according to a candidate viability metric that  
arbitrarily says that 2nd-choice is no better than the last choice.


you still haven't demonstrated why this contingent-choice information  
is the logical way to resolve a bunch of different competing  
contingency interests.  we know how, if there were only two  
candidates, to decide between the two (assuming they don't tie).  we  
know how to vote in that case (our sincere vote is the same as our  
tactical vote, easy), plurality = majority.  assuming no funny  
business, no one can dispute the popular legitimacy of the winner.


what we don't want to happen (assuming we want honest and democratic  
elections where tactical voting is not likely to work) is resolve an  
election differently between any two candidates differently than we  
would if those two were among a larger group of candidates.  we don't  
want to have to think how we would vote differently in the two  
cases.  if there is a Condorcet winner, and you are not that person,  
that Condorcet winner beat you, as far as the electorate is  
concerned.  if it was just the two of you, he beats you.  if it was  
you two along with N-2 other candidates, he still beats you (as well  
as beating everyone else).


This is most easily seen in single-winner STV elections (US = IRV),  
where the sequence of rounds is exactly analogous to the
sequence of rounds in an exhaustive ballot (eliminating one  
candidate at a time in successive ballots).


please don't patronize me.  there is nothing you're saying here that  
i don't know.  it is in how IRV does that that is the problem.  it  
doesn't accomplish the very goals we had when we adopted IRV (not  
rewarding tactical voting thus eliminating the need to consider  
tactical voting so we can vote the way we want to and not worry about  
contributing to defeating our own political interest - voter regret).



  The only difference is that
in an STV (IRV) election you don't know what all the other voters  
did in Round 1 when you come to give your second choice.


you mean you don't have transparency on how the rounds were performed  
or is it that your STV is a delayed runoff where you come in later?   
because i can't see the difference.  in the IRV i am familiar with,  
you order your candidates before knowing how any round turns out.  no  
one is returning to any polls.




  

Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-25 Thread robert bristow-johnson





On Nov 25, 2009, at 10:05 AM, Chris Benham wrote:


Robert Bristow-Johnson wrote (9 Nov 2009):

Of course IRV, Condorcet, and Borda use different methods to tabulate
the votes and select the winner and my opinion is that IRV (asset
voting, i might call it commodity voting: your vote is a
commodity that you transfer according to your preferences) is a
kabuki dance of transferred votes.  and there is an *arbitrary*
evaluation in the elimination of candidates in the IRV rounds: 2nd-
choice votes don't count for shit in deciding who to eliminate (who
decided that?  2nd-choice votes are as good as last-choice?  under
what meaningful and consistent philosophy was that decided?), then
when your candidate is eliminated your 2nd-choice vote counts as much
as your 1st-choice.

Regarding IRV's philosophy: each voter has single vote that is  
transferable
according to a rule that meets Later-no-Harm, Later-no-Help and  
Majority

for Solid Coalitions.

I rate IRV (Alternative Vote with unlimited strict ranking from the  
top) as the

best of the single-winner methods that meet Later-no-Harm.



On Nov 25, 2009, at 2:41 PM, Warren Smith wrote:


Are there any other voting methods besides IRV, meeting the
'later no harm' criterion?



my understanding is that the later-no-harm result happens only if the  
case of a Condorcet cycle (the prevalence of which i am dubious  
about).  where there is a Condorcet winner and that person is  
elected, is there still possible later harm?


i hadn't thought of it before but i s'pose that since Condorcet  
*does* give preference to centrist candidates over solid coalition  
candidates (in comparison to IRV rules).  i knew before that  
Condorcet sorta favors centrist candidates because voters in either  
the left or right fringes (that do not pick the centrist candidate as  
their 1st-choice) likely pick the centrist as their 2nd-choice.   
that's nice for political interests of centrist voters, but that is  
no reason to pick an election method.  the reason that IRV or *any*  
non-Condorcet method is problematic for the interest of democracy is  
that any candidate elected that is not the Condorcet winner is  
elected despite the fact that the majority of voters expressed that  
they wanted someone else *specifically* on their ballots.


when IRV or Borda or whatever happens to elect the Condorcet winner,  
they seem to do pretty well.  when they fail to do that, voters have  
reason to wonder: didn't more of us prefer that other guy?  how'd  
this guy get elected?  isn't that what democracy is about?: if more  
of us prefer Candidate A to Candidate B, then it isn't Candidate B  
who gets elected.


other than the possible cycle, in which some kinda pathologies can  
happen, i still don't see a pimple on it.


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-25 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

robert bristow-johnson wrote:

my understanding is that the later-no-harm result happens only if the 
case of a Condorcet cycle (the prevalence of which i am dubious about).  
where there is a Condorcet winner and that person is elected, is there 
still possible later harm?


As far as I remember, Condorcet and LNHarm has the property that LNHarm 
isn't, by itself, violated as long as there is a CW, but the transition 
from CW to no CW (or vice versa) makes it inevitable that there will be 
a LNHarm-violating discontinuity *somewhere*.


In other words, as long as you stay within the CW domain, there is no 
LNHarm failure, but there is no way to engineer a completion rule to 
maintain this for every CW-no CW transition.


I'm not entirely sure about that, though - can anyone confirm?


Not that this bothers me - LNHarm seems to me to be a criterion of 
don't take the full picture into account. Consider a negotiation 
situation: if everybody keeps their cards close to their chests (i.e. 
vote bullet style), there can be no compromise; but if they're willing 
to reach further, one might find an option that, while not the favorite 
of any, is good enough for all. An LNHarm-respecting method has to act 
as if people are voting cautiously before it can consider any additional 
information, and thus it misses such opportunities for compromise.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-25 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Nov 25, 2009, at 3:26 PM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:


robert bristow-johnson wrote:

my understanding is that the later-no-harm result happens only if  
the case of a Condorcet cycle (the prevalence of which i am  
dubious about).  where there is a Condorcet winner and that person  
is elected, is there still possible later harm?


As far as I remember, Condorcet and LNHarm has the property that  
LNHarm isn't, by itself, violated as long as there is a CW, but the  
transition from CW to no CW (or vice versa) makes it inevitable  
that there will be a LNHarm-violating discontinuity *somewhere*.


the degree of inevitability is an issue.  if inevitable is measured  
as a binary value, the i s'pose it's inevitable.  if inevitable is  
measured as a probability of a cycle occurring per election-year,  
then i think it's a small number.  if cycles are rare, the mean  
percentage of elections that have Condercet cycles is small.  when we  
somehow figure out a merit metric for an election system, a low- 
likelihood of a pathology that has low cost (say, if a cycle happens  
you elect using IRV rules, how bad can that be?) should contribute  
(negatively) negligibly to the merit metric.


In other words, as long as you stay within the CW domain, there is  
no LNHarm failure, but there is no way to engineer a completion  
rule to maintain this for every CW-no CW transition.


sure, but i'm still dubious about the product of likelihood times  
cost of occurrence of that.



I'm not entirely sure about that, though - can anyone confirm?


and i continue to wonder (really) how a possibly rare occurrence of a  
no-CW election (with its LNHarm consequence) becomes a greater  
concern than that of the likelihood and cost of electing a candidate  
against the expressed wishes of a majority of the electorate.  i  
think that cost (electing the wrong candidate) is reasonably high and  
that the likelihood of it happening is definitely non-zero because it  
has happened in the Vermont town i am a resident of.


Not that this bothers me - LNHarm seems to me to be a criterion of  
don't take the full picture into account. Consider a negotiation  
situation: if everybody keeps their cards close to their chests  
(i.e. vote bullet style), there can be no compromise; but if  
they're willing to reach further, one might find an option that,  
while not the favorite of any, is good enough for all.


i would call that the essential measure of a popular election.  it's  
utilitarian: we maximize satisfaction for the franchised about the  
governance of whatever organization by pleasing more people with a  
decision than we displease.  that's the reason we have elections, we  
could adopt rules to give it to the minority candidate if that  
candidate reaches a certain threshold, but we don't do that for  
binary decisions, we consistently give it to the majority.


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-25 Thread Dave Ketchum

Trying to sort this out as to Condorcet and LNH:

Seems that cycles are involved before, after, or both.  And the voters  
change their votes, getting more affect on result than they might  
expect.  So what, assuming the counters properly read the vote?


I agree with those who expect cycles to be rare.  Still, it is the  
more important races that are more likely to result in cycles.


What I see as important is that, assuming analysis of the election is  
done both officially and by others, it should be practical to decide  
whether the official result was correct, considering the N*N vote  
count.  In other words, the official analysis should not be complex -  
especially not to gain trivial improvement in quality of official  
result.


Dave Ketchum

On Nov 25, 2009, at 3:08 PM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:

On Nov 25, 2009, at 10:05 AM, Chris Benham wrote:

Robert Bristow-Johnson wrote (9 Nov 2009):

Of course IRV, Condorcet, and Borda use different methods to  
tabulate

the votes and select the winner and my opinion is that IRV (asset
voting, i might call it commodity voting: your vote is a
commodity that you transfer according to your preferences) is a
kabuki dance of transferred votes.  and there is an *arbitrary*
evaluation in the elimination of candidates in the IRV rounds: 2nd-
choice votes don't count for shit in deciding who to eliminate (who
decided that?  2nd-choice votes are as good as last-choice?  under
what meaningful and consistent philosophy was that decided?), then
when your candidate is eliminated your 2nd-choice vote counts as much
as your 1st-choice.

Regarding IRV's philosophy: each voter has single vote that is  
transferable
according to a rule that meets Later-no-Harm, Later-no-Help and  
Majority

for Solid Coalitions.

I rate IRV (Alternative Vote with unlimited strict ranking from the  
top) as the

best of the single-winner methods that meet Later-no-Harm.



On Nov 25, 2009, at 2:41 PM, Warren Smith wrote:


Are there any other voting methods besides IRV, meeting the
'later no harm' criterion?



my understanding is that the later-no-harm result happens only if  
the case of a Condorcet cycle (the prevalence of which i am dubious  
about).  where there is a Condorcet winner and that person is  
elected, is there still possible later harm?


i hadn't thought of it before but i s'pose that since Condorcet  
*does* give preference to centrist candidates over solid coalition  
candidates (in comparison to IRV rules).  i knew before that  
Condorcet sorta favors centrist candidates because voters in either  
the left or right fringes (that do not pick the centrist candidate  
as their 1st-choice) likely pick the centrist as their 2nd-choice.   
that's nice for political interests of centrist voters, but that is  
no reason to pick an election method.  the reason that IRV or *any*  
non-Condorcet method is problematic for the interest of democracy is  
that any candidate elected that is not the Condorcet winner is  
elected despite the fact that the majority of voters expressed that  
they wanted someone else *specifically* on their ballots.


when IRV or Borda or whatever happens to elect the Condorcet winner,  
they seem to do pretty well.  when they fail to do that, voters have  
reason to wonder: didn't more of us prefer that other guy?  how'd  
this guy get elected?  isn't that what democracy is about?: if more  
of us prefer Candidate A to Candidate B, then it isn't Candidate B  
who gets elected.


other than the possible cycle, in which some kinda pathologies can  
happen, i still don't see a pimple on it.


r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting? (long)

2009-11-11 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Nov 10, 2009, at 7:40 AM, Matthew Welland wrote:


Also, again, your single vote is irrelevant.


except in a close election.


It is the aggregate of
thousands or millions of votes that will make or break A vs. B. How  
many

feel so strongly against A that they cannot vote for him or her?

The binary nature of approval is washed out by large numbers just  
as a class
D amplifier can directly produce smooth analog waveforms out of a  
pure 1 or 0

signal.


the mathematical function that does that is the low-pass filter on  
the output.  it's sorta the same idea that these 1-bit A/D (a.k.a.  
sigma-delta) converters use.  if we were voting with a range  
ballot, and our continuous range value gets a zero-mean uniform  
p.d.f. random dither signal added to it (or, to use your PWM  
example, a zero-mean number drawn sequentially, in chronological  
order of the vote submission) and that gets quantized to a yes/no  
Approval vote (i s'pose if the threshold is set to 50%), then you  
would have a comparable situation.


i just dunno if i like the idea of a zero-mean (and even symmetrical  
p.d.f.) random variable actually going into a governmental election.   
how well i approve or disapprove of a particular candidate that i am  
not actively supporting is a function of how i'm feeling on Election  
Day.  but it's less likely how i rank that candidate w.r.t. the other  
candidates would change.  like grading papers, sometimes to come up  
with a numerical score, we get out our dartboard and see how good our  
toss is.  but students might like a more deterministic method.


for governmental elections, i only support a system that is fully  
deterministic (and repeatable) except, i s'pose, if there is a dead  
heat, then i s'pose, some kind of drawing of lots would be  
necessary.  it should require enough information from voters that the  
system knows how any voter would choose between any subset of  
candidates (the ranked ballot does that, but the approval ballot does  
not).  and it shouldn't force voters to bring their dartboard (or  
dice or spinner, etc) to the polls to come up with a numerical  
approval rating for each candidate, because of GIGO.


the other principle that is important is that of anonymity of vote.   
it shouldn't matter if you really, really, really like your candidate  
and i only tepidly support his/her opponent.  my vote for the  
opponent should count just as much as your more enthusiastic vote for  
your candidate.  there should be nothing that tips the scale in favor  
of your candidate based on how enthusiastically she is supported,  
only by the numbers of voters that supports her.  our votes should  
have equal weight.


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting? (long)

2009-11-11 Thread Juho
In large elections with evenly spread voters and candidates and no  
strategies the distribution of Approval votes may indeed be such that  
the best candidate regularly wins. The situation may however be also  
different. I  gave one simple example where the left wing had two  
candidates and the right wing had only one. The distribution of votes  
may not bring fair results in this type of set-up.


The assumption was that the right wing voters would predominantly  
approve only their own candidate while many left wing voters would be  
tempted to indicate which one of the left wing candidates they prefer  
over the other (despite of clearly preferring both left wing  
candidates over the right wing candidate). The end result could  
therefore be biased. The right wing candidate might easily win even if  
right wing would have considerably smaller than 50% support.


With small number of candidates and with a candidate set-up that is  
not symmetric or well balanced Approval may well produce biased  
results. Methods that are capable of providing richer information  
(ranked methods) are likely to provide more balanced input data (and  
results).


Juho


On Nov 12, 2009, at 2:28 AM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:


On Nov 10, 2009, at 7:40 AM, Matthew Welland wrote:



It is the aggregate of
thousands or millions of votes that will make or break A vs. B. How  
many

feel so strongly against A that they cannot vote for him or her?

The binary nature of approval is washed out by large numbers just  
as a class
D amplifier can directly produce smooth analog waveforms out of a  
pure 1 or 0

signal.


the mathematical function that does that is the low-pass filter on  
the output.  it's sorta the same idea that these 1-bit A/D (a.k.a.  
sigma-delta) converters use.  if we were voting with a range  
ballot, and our continuous range value gets a zero-mean uniform  
p.d.f. random dither signal added to it (or, to use your PWM  
example, a zero-mean number drawn sequentially, in chronological  
order of the vote submission) and that gets quantized to a yes/no  
Approval vote (i s'pose if the threshold is set to 50%), then you  
would have a comparable situation.


i just dunno if i like the idea of a zero-mean (and even symmetrical  
p.d.f.) random variable actually going into a governmental  
election.  how well i approve or disapprove of a particular  
candidate that i am not actively supporting is a function of how i'm  
feeling on Election Day.  but it's less likely how i rank that  
candidate w.r.t. the other candidates would change.  like grading  
papers, sometimes to come up with a numerical score, we get out our  
dartboard and see how good our toss is.  but students might like a  
more deterministic method.


for governmental elections, i only support a system that is fully  
deterministic (and repeatable) except, i s'pose, if there is a dead  
heat, then i s'pose, some kind of drawing of lots would be  
necessary.  it should require enough information from voters that  
the system knows how any voter would choose between any subset of  
candidates (the ranked ballot does that, but the approval ballot  
does not).  and it shouldn't force voters to bring their dartboard  
(or dice or spinner, etc) to the polls to come up with a numerical  
approval rating for each candidate, because of GIGO.


the other principle that is important is that of anonymity of vote.   
it shouldn't matter if you really, really, really like your  
candidate and i only tepidly support his/her opponent.  my vote for  
the opponent should count just as much as your more enthusiastic  
vote for your candidate.  there should be nothing that tips the  
scale in favor of your candidate based on how enthusiastically she  
is supported, only by the numbers of voters that supports her.  our  
votes should have equal weight.


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for  
list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Matthew Welland wrote:

So, to re-frame my question. What is the fatal flaw with approval? I'm 
not interested in subtle flaws that result in imperfect results. I'm 
interested in flaws that result in big problems such as those we see 
with plurality and IRV.


IMHO, it is that you need concurrent polling in order to consistently 
elect a good winner. If you don't have polling and thus don't know where 
to put the cutoff (between approve and not-approve), you'll face the 
Burr dilemma: If you prefer A  B  C, if you approve both A and B, 
you might get B instead of A, but if you approve only A, you might get C!


Thus the kind of Approval that homes in on a good winner employs 
feedback. The method is no longer Approval alone, but Approval plus 
polling. That /can/ work (people approve {Nader, Gore} if Nader has 
fewer votes than Gore, so that Bush doesn't win from the split, but only 
approve either Nader or Gore if both are large), but why should we need 
to be burdened with the feedback?


Some, like Abd, argue that we always reason based on others' positions 
to know how much we can demand, and so that this is a feature rather 
than a bug. That doesn't quite sound right to me. In any event, if you 
want Approval + bargaining (which the feedback resolves to), make that 
claim. Approval alone, without feedback, will be subject to the flaws 
mentioned earlier, however.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Raph Frank
On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 10:37 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm
km-el...@broadpark.no wrote:
 IMHO, it is that you need concurrent polling in order to consistently elect
 a good winner. If you don't have polling and thus don't know where to put
 the cutoff (between approve and not-approve), you'll face the Burr dilemma:
 If you prefer A  B  C, if you approve both A and B, you might get B
 instead of A, but if you approve only A, you might get C!

However, the same logic can be applied to plurality voting.  If people
had to vote blind, then the results would be even worse.

History with plurality has shown that it is reasonable to expect
people to know who the top-2 candidates are.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Matthew Welland
On Tuesday 10 November 2009 03:37:56 am Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
 Matthew Welland wrote:
  So, to re-frame my question. What is the fatal flaw with approval? I'm
  not interested in subtle flaws that result in imperfect results. I'm
  interested in flaws that result in big problems such as those we see
  with plurality and IRV.

 IMHO, it is that you need concurrent polling in order to consistently
 elect a good winner. If you don't have polling and thus don't know where
 to put the cutoff (between approve and not-approve), you'll face the
 Burr dilemma: If you prefer A  B  C, if you approve both A and B,
 you might get B instead of A, but if you approve only A, you might get
 C!

This seems to me to be a minor, not major, flaw.  Having to vote A  B to 
hedge your bets is not ideal but you might even be able to argue some 
benefits to it. A will see B as a serious threat and vice versa. They may 
make adjustments to their stands on issues to accommodate voters like you. 
Approval voting is enough to bring competition for votes back into the arena 
and I think it makes negative campaigning a very risky strategy. 

Also, again, your single vote is irrelevant. It is the aggregate of 
thousands or millions of votes that will make or break A vs. B. How many 
feel so strongly against A that they cannot vote for him or her?

The binary nature of approval is washed out by large numbers just as a class 
D amplifier can directly produce smooth analog waveforms out of a pure 1 or 0 
signal.

 Thus the kind of Approval that homes in on a good winner employs
 feedback. The method is no longer Approval alone, but Approval plus
 polling. That /can/ work (people approve {Nader, Gore} if Nader has
 fewer votes than Gore, so that Bush doesn't win from the split, but only
 approve either Nader or Gore if both are large), but why should we need
 to be burdened with the feedback?

Sure, in any real election there will be many dynamics at work. Feedback 
polls, debates etc. will all improve an election. Approval might benefit from 
feedback but I don't see why it becomes fatally flawed without it, only 
mildly flawed.

 Some, like Abd, argue that we always reason based on others' positions
 to know how much we can demand, and so that this is a feature rather
 than a bug. That doesn't quite sound right to me. In any event, if you
 want Approval + bargaining (which the feedback resolves to), make that
 claim. Approval alone, without feedback, will be subject to the flaws
 mentioned earlier, however.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Jobst Heitzig wrote:

Dear Kristofer,

both Approval Voting and Range Voting *are* majoritarian: A majority
can always get their will and suppress the minority by simply bullet-voting.

So, a more interesting version of your question could be: Which
*democratic* method (that does not allow any sub-group to suppress the
rest) has (usually or on average or in the worst case) the least
Bayesian Regret.


Yes. A majority that acts in a certain way can get what it wants. That's 
true for Range and Approval, and it's true for Condorcet, Plurality, 
etc. However, my point was that Range goes further: a minority that acts 
in a certain way can get what it wants, too; all that's required is that 
the majority does not vote Approval style (either max or min) and that 
the minority does, and that the minority is not too small.


It is in that respect I mean that Range is more radical, because it 
permits a minority to overrule a majority that otherwise agrees about 
which candidates it prefers. For those who mean that elections have to 
be, at least, majoritarian, Range may contain a surprise.



I conjecture that at least when the nomination of additional options
is allowed, the method SEC described recently is a hot candidate for
this award, since it seems that SEC will lead to the election of the
option at the *mean* (instead of the median) voter position, and I guess
that in most spacial utility models the mean position is in many senses
better and will in particular have less Bayesian Regret than the
median position. (Recall that in a one-dimensional spacial model where
additional options can be nominated, all majoritarian methods likely
lead to median positions being realized and are thus basically all
equivalent.)


You could probably devise a whole class of SEC-type methods. They would 
go: if there is a consensus (defined in some fashion), then it wins - 
otherwise, a nondeterministic strategy-free method is used to pick the 
winner. The advantage of yours is that it uses only Plurality ballots.


I suppose the nondeterministic method would have to be bad enough to 
provide incentive to pick the right consensus, yet it shouldn't be so 
bad as to undermine the process itself if the voters really can't reach 
a consensus.


Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information 
from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with 
respect to Random Ballot? It would lead to a better outcome if the 
consensus fails, but so also make it more likely that the consensus does 
fail. Or would it? The reasoning from a given participant's point of 
view is rather: do I get something *I* would like by refusing to take 
part in consensus -- not, does *society* get something acceptable.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Hello Kristofer,

you wrote:
 However, my point was that Range goes further: a minority that acts
 in a certain way can get what it wants, too; all that's required is that
 the majority does not vote Approval style (either max or min) and that
 the minority does, and that the minority is not too small.
 
 It is in that respect I mean that Range is more radical, because it
 permits a minority to overrule a majority that otherwise agrees about
 which candidates it prefers. For those who mean that elections have to
 be, at least, majoritarian, Range may contain a surprise.

That's true. Methods in which a group can suppress the rest are
certainly bad, even more so when the group can be small...

 You could probably devise a whole class of SEC-type methods. They would
 go: if there is a consensus (defined in some fashion), then it wins -
 otherwise, a nondeterministic strategy-free method is used to pick the
 winner. The advantage of yours is that it uses only Plurality ballots.

The hard point is, I think, to define what actually a potential
consensus option is. And here the idea was to say everything unanimously
preferred to some benchmark outcome qualifies as potential consensus.
The benchmark then cannot be any feasible option but must be a lottery
of some options, otherwise the supporters of the single option would
block the consensus. But which lottery you take as a benchmark could be
discussed. I chose the Random Ballot lottery since it seems the most
fair one and has all nice properties (strategy-freeness, proportional
allocation of power).

 I suppose the nondeterministic method would have to be bad enough to
 provide incentive to pick the right consensus, yet it shouldn't be so
 bad as to undermine the process itself if the voters really can't reach
 a consensus.

Although I can hardly imagine real-world situations in which no
consensus option can be found (maybe be combining different decisions
into one, or using some kind of compensation scheme if necessary).

 Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information
 from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with
 respect to Random Ballot? 

This sounds interesting, but what exactly do you mean by Random Pair?
Pick a randomly chosen pair of candidates and elect the pairwise winner
of them? I will think about this...

 It would lead to a better outcome if the
 consensus fails, but so also make it more likely that the consensus does
 fail. Or would it? The reasoning from a given participant's point of
 view is rather: do I get something *I* would like by refusing to take
 part in consensus -- not, does *society* get something acceptable.

I'm not sure I know what you mean here.

Yours, Jobst

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Jobst Heitzig wrote:

Hello Kristofer,

you wrote:



You could probably devise a whole class of SEC-type methods. They would
go: if there is a consensus (defined in some fashion), then it wins -
otherwise, a nondeterministic strategy-free method is used to pick the
winner. The advantage of yours is that it uses only Plurality ballots.


The hard point is, I think, to define what actually a potential
consensus option is. And here the idea was to say everything unanimously
preferred to some benchmark outcome qualifies as potential consensus.
The benchmark then cannot be any feasible option but must be a lottery
of some options, otherwise the supporters of the single option would
block the consensus. But which lottery you take as a benchmark could be
discussed. I chose the Random Ballot lottery since it seems the most
fair one and has all nice properties (strategy-freeness, proportional
allocation of power).


I suppose the nondeterministic method would have to be bad enough to
provide incentive to pick the right consensus, yet it shouldn't be so
bad as to undermine the process itself if the voters really can't reach
a consensus.


Although I can hardly imagine real-world situations in which no
consensus option can be found (maybe be combining different decisions
into one, or using some kind of compensation scheme if necessary).


That might be true for a consensus in general, but I was referring to 
the SEC method, where all it takes is for a single voter to submit a 
different consensus ballot than the rest.



Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information
from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with
respect to Random Ballot? 


This sounds interesting, but what exactly do you mean by Random Pair?
Pick a randomly chosen pair of candidates and elect the pairwise winner
of them? I will think about this...


Yes. The CW now has a greater chance to win - but note that it's not 
given that the CW will win, because if he's not picked as one of the 
pair candidates, he doesn't come into play at all.



It would lead to a better outcome if the
consensus fails, but so also make it more likely that the consensus does
fail. Or would it? The reasoning from a given participant's point of
view is rather: do I get something *I* would like by refusing to take
part in consensus -- not, does *society* get something acceptable.


I'm not sure I know what you mean here.


Well, I was thinking that the SEC method provides an incentive for 
people to reach a common consensus because the alternative, which is the 
random ballot, isn't very good. Any (random or deterministic) method 
that favors some group would lead to that group having less of an 
incentive to participate in the consensus process because they know 
they'll get something they'll like.


Therefore, I at first thought that even though Random Pair would provide 
a result more people would be happy with, it would make the voters less 
interested in actually finding a consensus because the alternative isn't 
so bad anymore. However, then I realized that any given voter, if he's 
at the point where he doesn't care about the consensus option, will not 
be deterred from such a line of thinking because the alternative is 
suboptimal for society, only if it is suboptimal in his point of view. 
That means that you could replace Random Ballot with Random Pair as long 
as the fairness (what you call proportional allocation of power) remains 
intact, because if the improvement in result lifts all the groups 
equally, there's no more incentive for some group to cheat with 
respect to any other.


There's also another way of looking at it, which I just saw now: my 
first idea was that you can't move to a lottery that gives consistently 
good results because that will diminish people's interest in determining 
a consensus. But if the lottery is both fair and provides good results, 
then who cares? The consensus option will only come into play if the 
people can explicitly agree on a choice that's better than the expected 
value of the lottery. If figuring out a consensus is worth it (much 
better than the lottery, relatively speaking), then people will care, 
otherwise they won't. Thus improving the lottery part of the method will 
improve the method in general - it'll make up the amount it no longer 
encourages people to determine the consensus, by just giving better results.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Raph Frank
On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 8:11 PM, Jobst Heitzig heitzi...@web.de wrote:
 Hello Kristofer,
 Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information
 from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with
 respect to Random Ballot?

 This sounds interesting, but what exactly do you mean by Random Pair?
 Pick a randomly chosen pair of candidates and elect the pairwise winner
 of them? I will think about this...

Presumably, it means that the voter submits 2 ballots, a ranking and a
nomination for the 2nd round?

Clearly, your rankings should be honest, as it is only looked at once
the 2 candidates have been decided.

However, your nomination would have to be made tactically.

It would require that the voter decide the probability of the
candidate they nominate winning.

If you nominate the condorcet winner, then the odds of your candidate
winning the second round is 100%, as no other candidate can possibly
beat him..

However, if you nominate an extremist, then your nomination is almost
certain to fail, as he will lose to virtually any other candidate.

If the voter distribution is symmetric (and voter utility is
symmetric) around a central point, then the nominated candidate who is
closest to the centre will win.

If each voter nominates their favourite, then you best strategy is to
nominate the the candidate which maximises

f(distance)*utility

f(distance) is the fraction of the nominations that nominate
candidates further away than that distance from the centre.

f(0) is automatically 1 and f(most extremist candidate's distance) is
automatically 0.  Also, f(d) is a monotonic decreasing function.

Thus, when considering 2 candidates of near equal utility, you should
nominate the candidate nearest the centre.

However, if all voters do that, then most of the nominations will
start to be clustered near the centre.  This means that the voters
should nominate candidates even closer to the centre.

I.e. if f(d) = 0.1, then you would have to prefer that candidate at
least 10 times better than the condorcet winner in order to nominate
him.

I think the effect could very easily end up being that the condorcet
winner normally wins.

It could also be implemented in 2 formal rounds.  In the first round,
each voter votes for 1 candidate.  2 candidates are picked at random,
using random ballot.

Those 2 candidates then proceed to the run off.  This might even make
people accept random ballot.  The problem that a candidate with 1%
support could get to be President is eliminated.  (Unless it happens
twice in 1 election.)

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Raph Frank wrote:

On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 8:11 PM, Jobst Heitzig heitzi...@web.de wrote:

Hello Kristofer,

Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information
from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with
respect to Random Ballot?

This sounds interesting, but what exactly do you mean by Random Pair?
Pick a randomly chosen pair of candidates and elect the pairwise winner
of them? I will think about this...


Presumably, it means that the voter submits 2 ballots, a ranking and a
nomination for the 2nd round?


In the context of SEC, it would be:

Voter submits two ballots - one is ranked and the other is a Plurality 
ballot. Call the first the fallback ballot, and the second the consensus 
ballot.


If everybody (or some very high percentage, e.g. 99%) votes for the same 
consensus ballot, it wins. Otherwise, construct a Condorcet matrix based 
on the fallback ballots. Pick two candidates at random and the one that 
pairwise beats the other, wins.


To my knowledge, Random Pair is strategy-free. It might also be 
proportional, but I'm not sure about that (partly because I'm not sure 
how you'd define proportional for ranked ballots).


You seem to be suggesting a more Condorcet way of doing the consensus 
balloting. A possible option would be to look at how e.g. Debian handles 
supermajority issues. On the other hand, grafting Condorcet onto the 
consensus option would make the actual consensus more opaque, and one 
may in any case argue: if you have a consensus, there's an agreement 
and so you don't need a complex method to determine what the consensus 
actually is.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Raph Frank
On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 10:52 PM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm
km-el...@broadpark.no wrote:
 In the context of SEC, it would be:

 Voter submits two ballots - one is ranked and the other is a Plurality
 ballot. Call the first the fallback ballot, and the second the consensus
 ballot.

 If everybody (or some very high percentage, e.g. 99%) votes for the same
 consensus ballot, it wins. Otherwise, construct a Condorcet matrix based on
 the fallback ballots. Pick two candidates at random and the one that
 pairwise beats the other, wins.

How do you pick the random candidates?

For that to be clone independent, there would actually need to be 3 ballots:

- consensus ballot

If more than X% of the ballots pick the same candidate, then that
candidate wins.

- nomination ballot
- fallback ranking

2 nomination ballots are picked to decide the candidate and the
pairwise winner according to the rankings wins.

However, as I said in my last post, the nomination ballot isn't strategy free.

 To my knowledge, Random Pair is strategy-free. It might also be
 proportional, but I'm not sure about that (partly because I'm not sure how
 you'd define proportional for ranked ballots).

The problem is picking the 2 candidates.  If 2 are picked at random,
then the method isn't clone independent.

Also, it favours the condorcet winner, so may suffer from tyranny of
the majority.

However, if you had a divided society, then both ethnic groups would
still have some say.

For example, if the split was 55% (A) and 45 (B), and each ethnic
group only voted for their own candidate, then the results would be

2 A's: 30% = ethnic group A wins
A+B:  50% = ethnic group A wins (as they are the majority)
2 B's: 20% = ethnic group B wins

Thus group B gets some power, but not proportional power.

However, once the society starts working better, it would seamlessly
transition to a near condorcet method.

Also, in a divided society condorcet voting might reduce the issue directly.

In both cases, there would be an incentive for politicians from ethnic
group A to try to get support from voters in ethnic group B.

OTOH, a random election method may not be the best plan in a society
where corruption is a problem.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-08 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Warren Smith wrote:

It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the

strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal
improvement of other methods is fairly small. Can anyone point me to
analysis, preferably at a layman level, that contradicts or supports this
assertion?

Or, in succinct terms, what are the strategic flaws in approval or range

voting?

Thanks, Matthew Welland


--well... there is the whole rangevoting.org website...
my more-recent papers at
math.temple.edu/~wds/homepage/works.html
discuss range voting including some ways it is provably better than every
rank-order voting system for either honest or strategic voters...

--but those are not exactly succinct...

OK Let me try:
1. Range for 100% honest voters behaves better than IRV, Borda,
Condorcet and it is pretty intuitively clear why -- strength of
preference info used, not discarded.


There is, of course, the flipside of that property. If one wants a 
voting method where the majority wins, then Range won't work, simply 
because a minority of strong opinions can outweigh a majority of weak 
ones. You might argue that that is no bug at all (strong opinions 
*should* outweigh weak ones), but for those for which Majority 
compliance is a must-have, it should be mentioned - particularly since 
that is supposed to be one aspect of the fairness of traditional democracy.


In that sense, moving to Range (and perhaps Approval - depends on how 
you interpret it) is a more radical proposal than, for instance, moving 
to Condorcet (which passes Majority).


(And now I wonder which election method that passes Majority has the 
least Bayesian regret.)


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-08 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Dear Kristofer,

both Approval Voting and Range Voting *are* majoritarian: A majority can always 
get their will and suppress the minority by simply bullet-voting.

So, a more interesting version of your question could be: Which *democratic* 
method (that does not allow any sub-group to suppress the rest) has (usually or 
on average or in the worst case) the least Bayesian Regret. 

I conjecture that at least when the nomination of additional options is 
allowed, the method SEC described recently is a hot candidate for this award, 
since it seems that SEC will lead to the election of the option at the *mean* 
(instead of the median) voter position, and I guess that in most spacial 
utility models the mean position is in many senses better and will in 
particular have less Bayesian Regret than the median position. (Recall that in 
a one-dimensional spacial model where additional options can be nominated, all 
majoritarian methods likely lead to median positions being realized and are 
thus basically all equivalent.)

Yours, Jobst

 
 -Ursprüngliche Nachricht-
 Von: Kristofer Munsterhjelm km-el...@broadpark.no
 Gesendet: 08.11.09 10:23:11
 An: Warren Smith warren@gmail.com
 CC: election-methods election-meth...@electorama.com
 Betreff: Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and 
 range voting?


 Warren Smith wrote:
  It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the
  strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal
  improvement of other methods is fairly small. Can anyone point me to
  analysis, preferably at a layman level, that contradicts or supports this
  assertion?
  Or, in succinct terms, what are the strategic flaws in approval or range
  voting?
  Thanks, Matthew Welland
  
  --well... there is the whole rangevoting.org website...
  my more-recent papers at
  math.temple.edu/~wds/homepage/works.html
  discuss range voting including some ways it is provably better than every
  rank-order voting system for either honest or strategic voters...
  
  --but those are not exactly succinct...
  
  OK Let me try:
  1. Range for 100% honest voters behaves better than IRV, Borda,
  Condorcet and it is pretty intuitively clear why -- strength of
  preference info used, not discarded.
 
 There is, of course, the flipside of that property. If one wants a 
 voting method where the majority wins, then Range won't work, simply 
 because a minority of strong opinions can outweigh a majority of weak 
 ones. You might argue that that is no bug at all (strong opinions 
 *should* outweigh weak ones), but for those for which Majority 
 compliance is a must-have, it should be mentioned - particularly since 
 that is supposed to be one aspect of the fairness of traditional democracy.
 
 In that sense, moving to Range (and perhaps Approval - depends on how 
 you interpret it) is a more radical proposal than, for instance, moving 
 to Condorcet (which passes Majority).
 
 (And now I wonder which election method that passes Majority has the 
 least Bayesian regret.)
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-07 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Nov 7, 2009, at 3:12 PM, Matthew Welland wrote:


It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the
strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal
improvement of other methods is fairly small. Can anyone point me to
analysis, preferably at a layman level, that contradicts or  
supports this

assertion?

Or, in succinct terms, what are the strategic flaws in approval or  
range

voting?


this is no published analysis, but it should qualify as layman  
level.  this is why i don't like either approval or range voting in a  
governmental election.


in a sentence: Approval Voting does not collect enough information  
from voters and Range Voting requires too much.


since any of these methods we discuss here really exist for the  
purpose of dealing with more than two candidates (if there are  
exactly two candidates no one really disagrees about what to do)  
let's see if we have to do with multiple candidates.  in fact we can  
use the 2009 mayoral election in Burlington VT as an object lesson.


we have Candidate A (we'll call Andy), Candidate B (we'll call  
Bob), Candidate C (we'll call Curtis, but in Burlington his name  
was Kurt), and candidate D (we'll call Dan).


Approval Voting: so i approve of Andy and Bob, maybe Dan (not likely)  
and definitely not Kurt (err Curtis, candidate C).  but, if the  
election comes down to Andy vs. Bob, i want to register my preference  
for Andy.  how do i do that?  so then i'm thinking (tactically) that  
the Bob supporters aren't gonna be reciprocating with an approval  
vote for Andy, so what do i do if i really support Andy, am willing  
to settle for Bob, but really want Andy.  i will agonize over the  
decision and likely just vote approval for Andy, just like i would in  
a traditional FPTP election.  but then there is no information coming  
from me that i prefer Bob a helluva lot more than i approve of  
Curtis.  so Approval Voting has not relieved me, as a voter, from the  
need to consider tactics, if i want my vote to be effective.


Range Voting:  so i have 100 points that i can distribute among the 4  
candidates.  well definitely Candidate C (Curtis, really Kurt) gets  
zero of my points.  i might toss Dan 5 points, but i would likely not  
waste them.  so how do i divide my points between Andy and Bob?  i  
like them both, but prefer Andy over Bob, so what do i do?  i have to  
think tactically again.  are the Bob supporters gonna be tossing any  
points to Andy?  i can't trust that they will, they will probably  
just put all of their support for the candidate that they are  
behind.  if i want my vote to compete effectively with theirs, i will  
end up putting all 100 points behind my candidate Andy.  so, if we  
have any political identification at all, my vote under Range will  
convey no more information than it would with FPTP.


IRV, Condorcet, and Borda, use the simple ranked-order ballot where  
we say who we support first (candidate A for me), who is our second  
choice (candidate B), who is our third choice (candidate D for me)  
and who is our last choice (candidate C for me).  so if the election  
was just between A and B, we know that this voter (me) would vote for  
A.  if the election was just between B and D, we know this voter  
would vote for B.  if the election was between C and D, we know this  
voter would choose D.  of course, for a single voter (not necessarily  
for the aggregation of votes) there is no circular preference, we  
know that if the election was between A and D, this voter would vote  
for A.  we know that this voter would vote for B if the election was  
between B and C.  and we know that this voter would vote for A if it  
were between A and C.  from that simple ranked-order ballot, we know  
how the voter would vote between any selected pair of candidates in  
the hypothetical two-candidate election between those two.


of course IRV, Condorcet, and Borda use different methods to tabulate  
the votes and select the winner and my opinion is that IRV (asset  
voting, i might call it commodity voting: your vote is a  
commodity that you transfer according to your preferences) is a  
kabuki dance of transferred votes.  and there is an *arbitrary*  
evaluation in the elimination of candidates in the IRV rounds: 2nd- 
choice votes don't count for shit in deciding who to eliminate (who  
decided that?  2nd-choice votes are as good as last-choice?  under  
what meaningful and consistent philosophy was that decided?), then  
when your candidate is eliminated your 2nd-choice vote counts as much  
as your 1st-choice.


i don't like Borda because it has another arbitrary valuation.  the  
difference in score between your 1st and 2nd choice is the same as  
the difference in score between your 2nd and 3rd choice.  but what  
eternal value is that based on?  what if i like my 1st and 2nd choice  
almost equally, but think my 3rd choice is a piece of crap?  (this is  
what Range 

Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-07 Thread Raph Frank
On Sat, Nov 7, 2009 at 8:12 PM, Matthew Welland m...@kiatoa.com wrote:
 It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the
 strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal
 improvement of other methods is fairly small.

The recommended strategy in approval is to approve one of the top 2
and also any other candidates who are above your approval threshold.

The threshold is not so important, as it is likely that one of the top
2 will win, so that approval is the only one that matters.

You should approve all you prefer to the best of the top 2 and should
never approve someone you like less than the worst of the top-2.

Some possible thresholds

- approve all you prefer to the expected winner
- approve all you prefer to the expected utility of the election
- approve all you prefer to the best of the top 2
- approve all you prefer to the worst of the top 2

I prefer to the first first one as it will results in the condorcet
winner winning the election if there are accurate polls.

As long as voters know who are the contenders, then approval strategy
is pretty easy.

Where there are 3 contenders, there is still some issue with regard to
handling the middle candidate.  The voter would need to make a call
about which tie was more likely and also the differences in utility.

Also, strategy isn't necessarily a bad thing.

The problem with plurality is that it converges on the 2 party system.

It is a Nash equilibrium.

If you could go through each voter after an election and ask them if
they want to change their vote, most of them wouldn't.

It would normally just reduce the margin or victory for their
favourite of the top-2.

However, with approval, you can have a sequence that goes like:

A and B are the top 2, but C is the condorcet winning candidate.

Voters follow the policy that they will approve one of the top 2 and
any candidate they prefer to the expected winner.

Since every voter will only vote for one of A and B (since they are
the top-2), one of them must end up with less than 50% of the vote.

C is the condorcet winner, so he is preferred to whoever is the
expected winner by at least half of the voters.

Thus the first poll will show something like

A: 45
B: 55
C: 51

Thus C will suddenly be one of the top-2.

This might take a few polls, but as C gets more press reports, his
percentage will increase.

Once he is one of the top-2, he cannot be displaced.  No matter who is
the other one, he will be preferred to that candidate by more than
50%.

Also, once he is one of the top 2, any voters who prefer him to all
other candidates will suddenly stop approving either of A or B.  Thus
one of them will drop in popularity.


The point is that it isn't strategy that is the problem.  It is that
strategy results in the voters ending up with the the better of 2
evils.

With approval, the result is that a condorcet winner should normally
win, so any strategy results in a fair result.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-07 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Raph Frank wrote:

On Sat, Nov 7, 2009 at 8:12 PM, Matthew Welland m...@kiatoa.com wrote:

It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the
strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal
improvement of other methods is fairly small.


The recommended strategy in approval is to approve one of the top 2
and also any other candidates who are above your approval threshold.


That's strategy T. Some times (see Rob LeGrand's dissertation defense 
slides) a strategy A is better: approve all that you like better than 
whoever's getting the most Plurality votes, and approve of him as well 
if you prefer him to the one in second place on the Plurality count.


(I think it's a Plurality count. Late here, so vote-getter may refer 
to Approval votes - I'm not sure.)


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-07 Thread Raph Frank
On Sat, Nov 7, 2009 at 10:57 PM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm
km-el...@broadpark.no wrote:
 The recommended strategy in approval is to approve one of the top 2
 and also any other candidates who are above your approval threshold.

 That's strategy T. Some times (see Rob LeGrand's dissertation defense
 slides) a strategy A is better: approve all that you like better than
 whoever's getting the most Plurality votes, and approve of him as well if
 you prefer him to the one in second place on the Plurality count.

Strategy A, as you defined it, is almost equivalent to just setting
the threshold to the utility of the expected winner.

 (I think it's a Plurality count. Late here, so vote-getter may refer to
 Approval votes - I'm not sure.)

I don't think that actually matters much.  They should be roughly the same.

The main point is that the top-2 candidates are the 2 candidates who
are most likely to tie, so you should approve one of them and not the
other.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info