Re: [peirce-l] ORDINARY DISCOURSE AS THE FINAL CAUSE OF ALL INTELLECTUAL ENDEAVORS

2012-05-13 Thread Gary Moore
Dear Benjamin Udell, 
Gary Moore: Although John Harvey’s reply was extremely good and very thought 
provoking, this is the best argued and most informative and just downright 
practically effective letter I have ever received on a philosophy thread on the 
internet in twelve years! I appreciate the distinction made in paragraph 2] 
very much. I did have trouble trying to find any sort of definition for 
precisely the terminological combination “prime necessity” which, though it 
combines two well known terms, is not at all self-explicative together as 
obviously Peirce wants them to be together. You are perfectly right in saying 
Peirce is just using it as an example. ¶
[Addendum] Gary Moore: To explain my interest I need to show an ongoing 
conflict with S. J. McGrath over another such combination term with a violent 
and variegated history: the analogia entis which he says is the primary concept 
of Thomas Aquinas. He says it is absolutely necessary to all thinking as such 
as well as to any meaningful theology. He obviously treats it as a form of 
logical argument. But it is not. It is a literary trope. Now, that does not 
diminish its importance because literary explication always goes with using 
language. Literary explication shows that psychology, explicit and implicit, 
governs all our expression. Yet in logic and philosophy it is only rarely 
acknowledged, and then only as a minor concern when it fact it is the 
overwhelming concern of the whole of language. Its formation of language comes 
long before logic and philosophy. Deely demonstrates that the analogia entis is 
NOTa logical argument but does show the analysis of
 the word “God”, which Aquinas definitively says we can never really say 
anything ‘real’ about, acts as I see it as a black whole around which theology, 
philosophy, and psychology revolve around and . . . The term analogia entis 
McGrath is so hot and bothered about does not even occur in Aquinas anywhere. 
Gary Moore: But your further analysis, as well as the Peirce you quote [3], 
have been vastly rewarding! You quote “Necessity de omni is that of a predicate 
which belongs to its whole subject at all times.” I take this to refer to 
“Firstness”. In turn, I take these to refer to John Deely’s use of Aquinas’ ens 
ut primum cogitum which is literally the first ‘thing’ you know and gives you 
the ability to know everything else. This is the key to all of Deely’s 
thinking. I searched for ens ut primum cogitum at Arisbe and found absolutely 
nothing which is probably my fault. Is the identification accurate? ¶
[Addendum] Gary Moore: In A Thief of Peirce: The Letters of Kenneth Laine 
Ketner and Walker Percy, Percy makes the strange statement [page 6] that “To 
tell the truth, I’ve never seen much use in CSP’s “Firstness”, except to make 
the system more elegant.”]
 Gary Moore: At paragraph 8], you say, “ordinary discourse itself can evolve 
and become less vague and more specialized”. This is true. That this evolution 
occurs is undeniable. But this indicates the nature of language itself which I 
am always ‘within’ and yet is the only viewpoint I have of it. This is why I 
disagree with Deely about his blanket condemnation of solipsism which, like 
Kant’s categories for the same reason, he is forced to do an about face. FOUR 
AGES OF UNDERSTANDING, page 588, ““But this is not sufficient for the 
preclusion of solipsism for the species anthropos, and hence for each 
individual within it; for whatever may be the mechanism of representative 
consciousness, that does not change the basic situation admitted on all hands: 
nothing directly experienced has as such an existence also apart from our 
experiencing of it. This view is the hallmark of modernity. But the moderns 
never succeeded in figuring out why they
 were speculatively driven, over and over again, into a solipsistic corner from 
which, as Bertrand Russell summarized the modern dilemma in the historical 
twilight of its dominance in philosophy, there seems no way out. For only the 
sign in its proper being can effect the needed passage. And ideas as 
representations are emphatically not signs, but the mere vehicles and 
foundations through which the action of signs works to achieve, over and above 
individual subjectivity, the interweave of mind and nature that we call 
experience.Ӧ
Gary Moore: And on page 645, Deely grudgingly gives Kant credit for influencing 
Peirce: “The second great scheme of categories was that of Kant. We passed over 
Kant’s categories without any discussion of their detail, except to point out 
that, in the nature of the case, they could provide no more than the essential 
categories of mind-dependent being insofar as it enters into discourse since, 
according to Kant, all phenomena are wholly the mind’s own construct. 
Nonetheless, do not be deceived by this fact into thinking that the Kantian 
scheme is not worth studying. It is filled with triads, which Peirce found very 
suggestive in finally 

Re: [peirce-l] ORDINARY DISCOURSE AS THE FINAL CAUSE OF ALL INTELLECTUAL ENDEAVORS

2012-05-13 Thread Benjamin Udell
I don't find anything on /ens ut primum cognitum/ at Arisbe, and I find 
very little about it in connection with Peirce on the Internet. Be sure 
to put quotes around Peirce's name as well as around the sought phrase 
(like so: Peirce ens ut primum cognitum), otherwise Google includes 
results for Pierce. Also be sure to type it cognitum, not cogitum, a 
typo that probably results from associating cognition with cogitation, 
but the words are not cognate.


I've read little Deely or Kant and no McGrath. There are a few passages 
of Aquinas that I read many times many years ago. Anyway I won't be able 
to address a good deal of what you've said. I might point out /à la/ 
Merleau-Ponty that one is in language as one is in one's body. (Also, as 
Peirce said, as the body is /in/ motion, so one is /in/ thought, all 
thought is /in/ signs, etc.) One can't get out of one's body but one can 
self-relate as by thumb against finger, hand against hand, etc., some 
sort of interplay of external and internal where the circuit is never 
quite closed. It's one's own body, extended and flexible in space and 
lingering with one in time, that lets one deals with one's own body from 
outside. One also finds other bodies that, from the outside, are like 
one's own. Body and language can access themselves from outside so to 
speak. Moreover, in or as one's body, one moves in the world. One pushes 
against the ground and thus moves oneself, and so on; motion is relative 
but, for example, a center of gravity is not merely perspectival. 
Something like pushing against or standing upon the past is how one can 
conceive of volition regarding the past, /pace/ the scholastics. We 
empower ourselves in one sense with things that our beyond our power in 
another sense. One does get to test, and learn about, oneself, one's 
body, one's language, in their interplay with things over which one has 
often very little control, and so external perspectives get further into 
one's awareness. The distinction and indeed struggle, between self and 
other, seem to appear within a whole of experience (or maybe I should 
say like Peirce, within the whole phaneron) which is already there. If 
one thinks of that interface and struggle as 'external', then one can 
get Peirce's view that knowledge of the internal world comes by surmise 
from external facts. At least from the external as struggled with by 
oneself. Now, a solipsistic world in which one has little or no control 
over many things and in which one is often surprised and is often 
unable, for example, to fully anticipate or emulate another's mind, - 
such a supposedly solipsistic world seems to lack any conceivable 
/practical difference/ from the world as we usually think of it. 
Something like that seems to be Peirce's view of it. Then solipsism 
seems as superfluous as the idea of the Ptolemaic epicycles, or the idea 
of the luminiferous ether. However, I don't know whether that view would 
keep philosophy from continually sliding toward solipsism as Deely 
describes; it feels above my paygrade to make an assertion about that. 
Peirce's view of self-other relations seems to have its locus in his 
phaneroscopy, or phenomenology, i.e., prior to logic (as formal 
semiotic). Now, I'm kind of ignorant here; I'm not sure to what extent 
he would view the idea of representation as the solution against 
solipsism; maybe he thought the problem needs to be revisited in 
semiotic in order to be solved, or maybe he could address representation 
enough to deal with solipsism in his phaneroscopy since representation 
and mediation are Thirdness, a topic in phaneroscopy.  But in any case 
representation is how he has one expand beyond one's direct acquaintance 
with things, in prospective, generalizing, and at least conceivably 
testable ways.


As to ordinary discourse as the final cause of all intellectual 
endeavor, it's not clear to me why one shouldn't just as well view all 
intellectual endeavor as at least one of the final causes of ordinary 
discourse. Among such things it seems to me a two-way street, or a whole 
concourse, what with endeavors of imagination, sensory and so-called 
intuitive faculties, and concrete perception. A further final cause of 
all these things would seem some sort of evolution of humanity, or 
intelligent life, including the evolution both of ordinary discourse and 
of cognitive endeavors, among others.


I should note for the sake of some readers reading your Deely quote that 
Deely and a few others use the word sign otherwise than how Peirce 
uses it. For Peirce, representamen is a technical term just in case 
/sign/ as theoretically defined turns out to diverge from /sign/ as 
commonly understood. See Representamen 
http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/terms/representamen.html  at 
the Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms . Peirce eventually stopped 
using the word representamen (except in at least one late manuscript 
in which he seems to be working anew on a