Re: market socialism, etc.

2000-07-24 Thread Ricardo Duchesne


JD writes:
 
 Marx distinguished an "industrial capitalist" (i.e., the capitalist who 
 organizes production) from capitalists in general (those who own the means 
 of production). This is not the same as the distinction between the 
 entrepreneur and the capitalist, but it is close.

No, it is not close - as is obvious in the dismissive (marxist) 
remarks which you and others in pen-l have made about 
entrepreneurship.

 Further, he talks about innovation (the activity which distinguishes the 
 "entrepreneur" in Austrian lingo), though I don't think he uses that word. 
 (The distinction seems an "Austrian" innovation.) For example, in chapter 
 12 of volume I of CAPITAL, he talks about one capitalist introducing an new 
 way of producing things and how it is then imitated by other capitalists, 
 due to the coercive force of competition.

But the Austrian would never say "coercive force of competition" - 
and this is a crucial distinction - since for them  it is not a matter of 
a *structure* pushing you do do something which you might 
otherwise not want/desire to do. 

 Marx's emphasis is on _process_ innovation (rather than product 
 innovation), 
 
 The Austrians put a big emphasis on prices as signals (of tastes  
 scarcity). My understanding of Marx is that one of the bases of his crisis 
 theory is that these signals are wrong in the sense that they do not allow 
 "entrepreneurs" to coordinate to prevent underconsumption and the like. 
 Prices cannot provide an understanding of the nature of the capitalist 
 totality and the conditions needed for its harmonious expanded reproduction 
 over time. Instead of gradual change, we see "equilibration" through sharp 
 crises.

Schumpeter, on the contrary, minimizes the role of prices in 
innovation. Emphasis on prices gives the impression that 
capitalists/entrepreneurs are always passively responding to 
market signals. But S's concept of "creative destruction" activates 
the capitalist  - at the micro-economic level - in a way that M's 
theory could never do, since, for starters, M has micro-economic 
analysis. S writes: "Economists are at long last emerging from the 
stage in which price competition was all they saw. As soon as 
quality competition and sales effort are admitted into the sacred 
precints of theory, the price variable is ousted from its dominant 
position.  "In capitalist reality [what counts is] the competition from 
the new commodity, the new technology, the new source of 
supply, the new type of organization..." 

S never failed to praise M for his emphasis on the dynamic quality 
of capitalism, that cap "can never be stationary", but criticises him 
for viewing the capitalist as a mere personification of capital, rather 
than as an *agent* who understands his own actions and is 
consciously, willingly engaged in the market. 


 
 The word "rational" in economics is basically a theoretical fiction. 

It is heuristically useful. You seem to confuse two meanings of 
rationality, formal and substantive, in the use of  the value-
judgement "narrow-minded individualistic..." in your definition of 
economic rationality. It is interesting to note that for Weber 
capitalism was irrational at the substantive level. 

I don't know about S, but using the word "rational behavior" does 
not imply undue emphasis on individuals  - as Michael Perelman 
narrowly thinks as well - since we are talikng about rational 
behavior as a pattern or sequence of behavior. No reason to keep 
fighting the intellectual ghosts of the 50s. 

 
 Marx believed, I think, that a holistic approach was superior 
 to an individualistic approach. 
That is, he made a sociological statement 
 that certain kinds of societies produce certain kinds of attitudes. Thus, 
 he saw capitalism -- and specifically the societal environment of 
 capitalist competition -- as encouraging narrow-minded individualistic 
 profit-seeking (one vision of "rationality"). If Marx is seen as explaining 
 the basis for profit-maximization, then all the results derived from that 
 assumption can be accepted by Marx (as long as unreasonable auxiliary 
 assumptions aren't introduced).
 
 Jim Devine [EMAIL PROTECTED]   http://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevine
 




Re: market socialism, etc.

2000-07-20 Thread Ricardo Duchesne

Not tyring to spoil the party (I agree this was a good post - the sort 
of stuff I am sure penners would read more if only they had not 
wasted their time finding them in the pile of  shabby responses 
which pollute this place when there's a heated debate) but I have to 
take issue with the comment below, not because I want to pretend 
I know something about the Austrians (except what I thought I had 
to learn as a TA for Henryk Flakierski, the one Paul had in mind 
from York):  
 
 The "Austrian" theory of competition is derivative from Marx and the 
 classicals. I'm pretty sure that Bohm-Bawerk developed most of his stuff in 
 response to Marx, while appropriating the parts of Marx he liked (e.g., the 
 dynamic vision of competition).

But here's Schumpeter himself, the one Austrian who was closest 
to Marx: For Marx the capitalist economy "is incessantly being 
revolutionized from within by new enterprise, i.e., by the intrusion of 
new commodities or new methods of production or new commercial 
opportunities into the industrial structure [...] This is how progress 
comes about in capitalist society. In order to escape being 
undersold, every firm is in the end compelled to follow suit, to 
invest in its turn and, in order to be able to do so, to plow back part 
of its profits, i.e., to accumulate. Thus, everyone else accumulates. 
Now Marx saw this process of industrial change more clearly...than 
any other economist of his time. This does not mean that he 
correctly understood its nature or correctly analyzed its 
mechanism. With him, *that mechanism resolves itself into mere 
mechanics of masses of capital. He had no adequate theory of 
enterprise and his failure to distinguish the entrepreneur from the 
capitalist*, together with a faulty theoretical technique, accounts for 
many cases of non sequitur and for many mistakes"

When S says no adequate theory of enterprise he means that M 
had no adequate theory of rational behavior. Marx has no concept 
of rational action, his 'rational miser' is a mere personification of the 
capitalist system. 




Re: market socialism, etc.

2000-07-20 Thread Yoshie Furuhashi

Ricardo quotes Schumpeter:

But here's Schumpeter himself, the one Austrian who was closest
to Marx: For Marx the capitalist economy "is incessantly being
revolutionized from within by new enterprise, i.e., by the intrusion of
new commodities or new methods of production or new commercial
opportunities into the industrial structure [...] This is how progress
comes about in capitalist society. In order to escape being
undersold, every firm is in the end compelled to follow suit, to
invest in its turn and, in order to be able to do so, to plow back part
of its profits, i.e., to accumulate. Thus, everyone else accumulates.
Now Marx saw this process of industrial change more clearly...than
any other economist of his time. This does not mean that he
correctly understood its nature or correctly analyzed its
mechanism. With him, *that mechanism resolves itself into mere
mechanics of masses of capital. He had no adequate theory of
enterprise and his failure to distinguish the entrepreneur from the
capitalist*, together with a faulty theoretical technique, accounts for
many cases of non sequitur and for many mistakes"

What "cases of non sequitur" and "mistakes" does Schumpeter have in mind?

When S says no adequate theory of enterprise he means that M
had no adequate theory of rational behavior. Marx has no concept
of rational action, his 'rational miser' is a mere personification of the
capitalist system.

Why "theory of enterprise" = "theory of rational behavior"?

Yoshie




Re: Re: market socialism, etc.

2000-07-20 Thread Michael Perelman

Because we are supposed to look at capitalism at the level of individual
behavior.

Yoshie Furuhashi wrote:


 Why "theory of enterprise" = "theory of rational behavior"?

 Yoshie

--
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929

Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]




Re: Re: market socialism, etc.

2000-07-20 Thread Jim Devine

I wrote:  The "Austrian" theory of competition is derivative from Marx 
and the classicals. I'm pretty sure that Bohm-Bawerk developed most of his 
stuff in response to Marx, while appropriating the parts of Marx he liked 
(e.g., the dynamic vision of competition).

RD comments: But here's Schumpeter himself, the one Austrian who was 
closest to Marx: For Marx the capitalist economy "is incessantly being 
revolutionized from within by new enterprise, i.e., by the intrusion of new 
commodities or new methods of production or new commercial opportunities 
into the industrial structure [...] This is how progress comes about in 
capitalist society. In order to escape being undersold, every firm is in 
the end compelled to follow suit, to invest in its turn and, in order to be 
able to do so, to plow back part of its profits, i.e., to accumulate. Thus, 
everyone else accumulates. Now Marx saw this process of industrial change 
more clearly...than any other economist of his time. This does not mean 
that he correctly understood its nature or correctly analyzed its 
mechanism. With him, *that mechanism resolves itself into mere mechanics of 
masses of capital. He had no adequate theory of enterprise and his failure 
to distinguish the entrepreneur from the capitalist*, together with a 
faulty theoretical technique, accounts for many cases of non sequitur and 
for many mistakes"

Marx distinguished an "industrial capitalist" (i.e., the capitalist who 
organizes production) from capitalists in general (those who own the means 
of production). This is not the same as the distinction between the 
entrepreneur and the capitalist, but it is close.

Further, he talks about innovation (the activity which distinguishes the 
"entrepreneur" in Austrian lingo), though I don't think he uses that word. 
(The distinction seems an "Austrian" innovation.) For example, in chapter 
12 of volume I of CAPITAL, he talks about one capitalist introducing an new 
way of producing things and how it is then imitated by other capitalists, 
due to the coercive force of competition.

Marx's emphasis is on _process_ innovation (rather than product 
innovation), though he does talk about new ways to add non-nutritious 
filler to food (in order to lower the cost of labor-power). This is partly 
a product of the historical era in which he lived.

He also does not sneak in the assumption (as Austrian economists do) that 
"innovation" is always a good thing (so that "entrepreneurs" should be 
rewarded) or that the market is the judge of what's good. This makes sense, 
since both Charles Ponzi and the unknown man or woman who introduced 
"crack" cocaine engaged in innovation and were thus entrepreneurs. Marx 
seems to assume that innovation can be good (i.e., building up the wealth 
needed for socialism) or bad (i.e., encouraging resistance to capitalism).

The Austrians put a big emphasis on prices as signals (of tastes  
scarcity). My understanding of Marx is that one of the bases of his crisis 
theory is that these signals are wrong in the sense that they do not allow 
"entrepreneurs" to coordinate to prevent underconsumption and the like. 
Prices cannot provide an understanding of the nature of the capitalist 
totality and the conditions needed for its harmonious expanded reproduction 
over time. Instead of gradual change, we see "equilibration" through sharp 
crises.

Since Schumpeter doesn't explain what he mans by "faulty theoretical 
technique," no comment can be made on that.

 When S says no adequate theory of enterprise he means that M had no 
adequate theory of rational behavior. Marx has no concept of rational 
action, his 'rational miser' is a mere personification of the capitalist 
system. 

The word "rational" in economics is basically a theoretical fiction. NC 
economists _assume_ that people are "rational." The usual textbook 
economist's meaning of this is that people are self-interested, not caring 
about other individuals. But the more sophisticated  theorists use a 
definition that's basically tautological, single-minded goal-seeking. The 
only thing that differentiates irrationality from rationality is that the 
latter involves consistent preferences (i.e., under similar conditions, A 
will be preferred to B). But that doesn't make sense over time (since 
"tastes" change) and ignores the preference for variety. Crucially, the 
concept of  rationality falls away when we realize that due to sociological 
effects, tastes are endogenous.

Whether or not this is a reasonable approach is another issue, since social 
scientists make a lot of unreasonable assumptions (simplifying in order to 
understand). It's my impression that it's not the assumption of 
"rationality" that produces predictions or understanding as much as an 
understanding of the _constraints_ that limit individual (consumer or firm) 
choice. Consumer rationality cannot be used to predict an increased supply 
of labor-power as wages rise (because there are income 

market socialism, etc.

2000-07-19 Thread Jim Devine

THE SHORT VERSION (but still too long!)

ellipsis

Justin writes  they [that famous rock'n'roll band, Hayek  the Austrians] 
don't have the particular vices of the NCEists, math worthship, a 
conception of markets that is essentially static, and based on utterly 
counterfactual assumptions. They have a feel for real-world markets, if too 
little appreciation of their limits.

I respond It's a mistake to use the NCEists as one's standard of 
comparison. It really doesn't settle anything, since there are a variety of 
schools (the institutionalists, the post-Keynesians, and a lot of other 
heterodox economists) that are better than the NCEs. Further, NC economists 
like George Akerlof are much better than the Austrians, to my mind. (His 
market for lemons paper is a classic. It's also a case where math is quite 
useful.)  But many of the heterodox economists disagree with each other. If 
anything, I learn much more from the PKs, among other things because they 
have a serious theory of money and have learned Keynes' lessons, which is 
something that the Austrians never will do.

The "Austrian" theory of competition is derivative from Marx and the 
classicals. I'm pretty sure that Bohm-Bawerk developed most of his stuff in 
response to Marx, while appropriating the parts of Marx he liked (e.g., the 
dynamic vision of competition).

And the Austrians have their own "particular vices." Every time I try to 
read the Austrian stuff, it (a) doesn't seem to add anything substantive; 
and (b) gets into naturalist ideology. Similarly, though they talk about 
business cycles (as well-summarized by Haberler), they (a) get stuff from 
the Marxian tradition about how upswings create imbalances that need to be 
purged in the recession (unlike the mainstream Keynesian tradition, e.g., 
Krugman or DeLong) but (b) assume Say's Law and that the downswing is 
"natural" and/or painless. Crucially, they ignore the roles of the rate of 
profit and aggressive accumulation (i.e., they ignore capitalism).

If I remember correctly, Nicholas Kaldor won his debate on business cycles 
with Fred von H (connected with the latter's "triangles," I believe). But 
the Austrians still like the idea of "letting nature take its course," so 
that the business cycle recession can drive wages down, etc. Before Keynes, 
the Austrian vision was dominant among policy-makers (as a rationalization 
for explicitly pro-business rule of people like Treasury Secretary Mellon). 
I think it was very apt for Robert MacEllvaine to title a chapter of his 
book on the Great Depression "Nature Takes Its Course."

(Currently, Austrian economics seems popular among the shrinking number of 
"new classical economists," who are much much worse than the more 
NC-oriented Monetarists (a.k.a. "new Keynesians").)

The Austrians may not believe in the "utterly counterfactual assumptions" 
of NC economics (which are what, by the way?) but a lot of them reject any 
kind of empirical testing of their theories. Deductive knowledge is totally 
privileged over inductive knowledge (while they can be dogmatic about their 
deductions because they're "self-evident"). Rothbart's Austrian book on the 
Great Depression starts with _an apology_ for using empirical evidence! He 
then goes on to make utterly counterfactual assumptions about the 
omniscience of his beloved entrepreneurs. That kind of stuff (a predecessor 
of the notion of "rational" expectations) is just as bad as -- if not worse 
than -- the Walrasians' assumption that an omniscient Auctioneer (the 
modern version of Smith's Invisible Hand) rules the roost. And the 
Austrians' belief in Say's law is quite counterfactual.

ellipsis

JS ... they [competitive markets] have postive results. Uncompetitive 
markets involve monopollies or oligopolies or price fixing and other bad 
things that lower production and increase prices while the gougers take rent. 

You may have noticed that I pointed to some advantages of monopolies. In 
fact, it may be that monopolies and competition are equally good. (The 
Industrial Organization economists seem to be going in that direction.) The 
key question is whether or not an industry can be controlled by the people, 
in a democratic way. Competition may make that _more_ difficult, by 
allowing each firm to avoid responsibility "I had to dump toxic waste in 
the woods (or put sawdust in the kids' meals or sell weapons to Hitler or 
...) because _everyone does it_ and I'd suffer a competitive disadvantage." 
A monopoly has a harder time evading responsibility. Note that most 
government regulation give special treatment for smaller businesses. This 
is not only because of the remaining clout of the petty-bourgeois types and 
of their ideology. It's also because it's harder to get information about 
them. (Nixon's price-control scheme -- after the initial freeze -- was 
similarly aimed only at the bigger businesses, the oligopolies.)

Competitive markets also involve competitive rent-seeking. 

Re: market socialism, etc.

2000-07-19 Thread Doug Henwood

Excellent stuff, Jim.

I'm emerging from my shell to add one point. Justin's faith in the 
informational content of prices is touching. Developments in 
financial theory over the last 15 or so years should counsel a bit 
more skepticism. Efficient market theory has been importantly 
discredited, and Shiller-style analyses of excess volatility and mean 
reversion are taken a lot more seriously, even by the likes of Eugene 
Fama. There are good psychological reasons behind overreaction - 
e.g., the human tendency to value the most recent piece of 
information excessively, at the expense of earlier knowledge. You 
also have herding, fads, crowd behavior, etc. So there's lots of 
noise mixed in with signal.

This newer thinking about financial market prices is not without real 
world implications. As Terry Marsh and Robert Merton wrote in 1986: 
"To reject the Efficient Market Hypothesis for the whole stock 
market...implies broadly that production decisions based on stock 
prices will lead to inefficient capital allocations. More generally, 
if the application of rational expectations theory to the virtually 
'ideal' conditions provided by the stock market fails, then what 
confidence can economists have in its application to other areas of 
economics...?"

Less than Justin does, apparently.

Doug




Re: Re: market socialism, etc.

2000-07-19 Thread Jim Devine

At 03:15 PM 7/19/00 -0400, you wrote:
Excellent stuff, Jim.

thanks! (In the long version, I told Justin to go read Zizek. Never having 
read the dude, not only did I probably misspell his name, but I haven't the 
slightest idea what to recommend...)

I'm emerging from my shell to add one point. Justin's faith in the 
informational content of prices is touching. Developments in financial 
theory over the last 15 or so years should counsel a bit more skepticism. 
Efficient market theory has been importantly discredited, and 
Shiller-style analyses of excess volatility and mean reversion are taken a 
lot more seriously, even by the likes of Eugene Fama. There are good 
psychological reasons behind overreaction - e.g., the human tendency to 
value the most recent piece of information excessively, at the expense of 
earlier knowledge. You also have herding, fads, crowd behavior, etc. So 
there's lots of noise mixed in with signal.

yeah, the analysis of what's wrong with prices in financial markets has 
informed our knowledge of what's wrong with prices elsewhere.

come back, Doug!

Jim Devine [EMAIL PROTECTED]   http://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevine




Re: Market socialism, etc.

2000-07-19 Thread Jim Devine

Justin writes:  I agree that Jim's replies are excellent, and I shall have 
to think about them. I wish that Jim would moderate his tone. If I have 
been repetitive, it is because some people--not Jim--weren't getting the 
point. 

I am sorry that I am irritated, but I've been familiar with the 
Hayek-kritik of totally-centralized planning for 30 years or so. It was in 
the intro textbook they assigned when I was a Frosh in college, just as it 
appears in Bowles  Edwards, UNDERSTANDING CAPITALISM, 2nd ed. I get tired 
of repetition, too. I think that one obligation of a radical political 
economist is to get beyond the usual cant, so I try.

I'll let others be the judge, but it's possible that (as with oysters) my 
irritation may have produced a pearl or two (perhaps discolored and 
misshapen, but what the hell). If there's someone out there in pen-l world 
who's an expert on this subject, do you want to be the (lead?) co-author to 
help me whip my points into a small book?
Jim Devine [EMAIL PROTECTED]  http://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~JDevine




Re: market socialism, etc.

2000-07-19 Thread Charles Brown



 [EMAIL PROTECTED] 07/19/00 03:15PM 
Excellent stuff, Jim.

__

CB: ditto





Re: Market socialism, etc.

2000-07-19 Thread Charles Brown



 [EMAIL PROTECTED] 07/19/00 05:10PM 
If there's someone out there in pen-l world 
who's an expert on this subject, do you want to be the (lead?) co-author to 
help me whip my points into a small book?

__

CB: You really should do that.




Re: Re: market socialism, etc.

2000-07-19 Thread Ken Hanly

While we are voting, I also found Jim's post quite helpful. I
also support
Neil's return. He added little traffic. He didn't insult anyone.
Some people don't mind Spam. Personally I use Klik.
Von Mises saw co-operatives as special interest groups who like
every other special interest group wanted special grants and
favors from the state to help them compete in the market thus
distorting it. His article on Co-ops is availabe at the Von Mises
site.
   Cheers, Ken Hanly

Charles Brown wrote:
 
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] 07/19/00 03:15PM 
 Excellent stuff, Jim.
 
 __
 
 CB: ditto




Re: Re: market socialism, etc.

2000-07-16 Thread Jim Devine

Justin wrote:
Attacking Hayek for being too neoclassical is like attacking Marx for 
being too neoclassical. Hayek, Mises, and the Austrians dislike NCE for 
many of the same reasons that Marxists do: it's a poor description of 
actual markets (this is more Hayek than Mises) ...

I didn't say that Hayek and the Austrians were NC economists (or if I did 
it was due to inadequate consumption of caffeine). But the Austrians are 
typically even more right-wing than the mainstream of NC economists, 
bringing in all sorts of pseudo-anarchistic stuff about "natural" or 
"spontaneous" order. (It's hard to tell whether the Austrians are worse 
than the Chicago-school NCers, since the right/left scale is not useful 
except on a very abstract level.) These people are ignorant of the fact 
that markets are human-created institutions, instead seeing them as gifts 
from the gods.

Please, go read Hayek's Individualisma nd the Economic Order (Chicagao 
1940+/-); it's short, clear, accessible, and reading it will avoid many 
problems and misunderstandings in the discussion. Besides, it is a very 
good and important book.

I don't like being told: "go read this book" by some allegedly Great Man. 
It's a little bit like telling me to simply go away. Or like those folks 
who come the door with Good News who tell me that if read the Watch Tower, 
everything will make sense. "Go read X" is too much like appeal to 
authority, which is one of the basic logical fallacies. For a serious 
discussion, it's best to present a summary of one's viewpoint, defending it 
as well as one can, and then say "for more on this, go read X."

Anyway, I've found that when I go and read X, I have a different 
interpretation of it than did the person who urged me to read it. I'd 
rather skip the X and discuss the interpretation (i.e., the urger's own 
views).

Now, unlike Paul Phillips, I'm no expert on the subject under discussion, 
so someday when my research projects get into the territory of "how 
socialism should be organized" again, I'll read Hayek. (These days, of 
course, a Hayek-style information critique is applied to markets.) But I 
think I'll (re)read Horvat first. The reason is that I've never been one of 
those who thought that the whole economy could be planned using a 
spread-sheet or that GOSPLAN was the best thing since sliced bread. In 
fact, years ago, I would have described myself as some sort of "market 
socialist." As far as I can tell, Hayek's only relevant to those who think 
that planning is the only solution or those who think only in terms of a 
crude plan/market dichotomy.  I'm not one of those.

Anyway, tally-ho and all that, here's the discussion:

I wrote:
  The point is (to repeat myself) that if the _centralized_ part of the 
 planning process is only dealing with _abstract_ (or general) issues like 
 the growth rate of the economy or the percentage of the total product 
 that goes into investment or the balance between broad industrial 
 sectors, there's no need for some Hayekian all-knowledgeable mind. 

OK, I agree with that sort of planning, as long as there are competitive 
markets operating below the Fed level.

I don't see why it has to be a "competitive market," especially given the 
way "competitive markets" cause all sorts of negative results. (The fact 
that I have to repeat this is a sign of poor communication.) In many ways, 
monopolies are better (as when they are more able to pay high wages to 
their employees, while the textbook-standard monopoly's restriction of 
output can mean restriction of pollution, too). Competition in product 
markets encourages wage-cutting, which encourages the race to the bottom, 
increased human misery, and underconsumption. Among other things.

Now in a different missive, Justin explains that the kind of "market 
socialism" that he favors involves workers' control. You should have said 
so earlier, Justin, because there are a lot of different kinds of market 
socialism (cf. Roemer). In any event, if workers control factories, that 
would probably prevent a race to the bottom, or at least discourage it. But 
it does not negate the other problems with markets.

In yet another different missive, Justin writes that he thinks planning 
(without markets) won't work, would be inefficient. (In a market context, 
some, even much, planning is fine). 

I think that the comment that "planning (without markets) won't work, would 
be inefficient" begs the question. What is meant by "working" here? 
Different people have different definitions of success and therefore of 
"working" (as I noted, from the point of view of the military-industrial 
complex, a $500 toilet seat is a success -- while from the perspective of 
the Soviet ruling class, GOSPLAN worked for a long time).

The term "efficiency" also does not speak for itself. It refers to the 
successful attainment of given goals. That means that the "efficiency" of 
the market would be judged differently by socialists and 

Re: Re: Re: market socialism, etc.

2000-07-16 Thread JKSCHW

Jim offers a long, meaty, and substantive discussion. I will look it over 
tomorrow and see if I have more to say, but a few comparatively short 
responses on a quick read through. Btw, this is part I of II. The message was 
too long for my system to handle.

 I didn't say that Hayek and the Austrians were NC economists . But the 
Austrians are 
 typically even more right-wing than the mainstream of NC economists, 

Good, and true. However, they don't have the particular vices of the NCEists, 
math worthship, a conception of markets that is essentially static, and based 
on utterly counterfactual assumptions. They have a feel for real-world 
markets, if too little appreciation of their limits.
 
 I don't like being told: "go read this book" by some allegedly Great Man 
{Hayek]. . . . For a serious 
 discussion, it's best to present a summary of one's viewpoint, defending it 
 as well as one can, and then say "for more on this, go read X."

Sorry. I have, however, been summarizing and developing Hayekian arguments.
 
 But I 
 think I'll (re)read Horvat first. The reason is that I've never been one of 
 those who thought that the whole economy could be planned using a 
 spread-sheet or that GOSPLAN was the best thing since sliced bread. In 
 fact, years ago, I would have described myself as some sort of "market 
 socialist." 

Great!

As far as I can tell, Hayek's only relevant to those who think 
 that planning is the only solution or those who think only in terms of a 
 crude plan/market dichotomy.  I'm not one of those.

Right, but there a lot of them around here.
 
  I don't see why [we need] e a "competitive market," especially given the 
 way "competitive markets" cause all sorts of negative results.

Sure. But they have postive results. Uncompetitive markets involve 
monopollies or oligopolies or price fixing and other bad things that lower 
production and increase prices while the gougers take rent. 

   Competition in product 
 markets encourages wage-cutting, which encourages the race to the bottom, 
 increased human misery, and underconsumption. Among other things.

Ah, but therea re no wages in worker-controlled market socialism. The workers 
take the profits, and are unl;ikely to reduce their own share to 
benefit--whom? 
 
  Now in a different missive, Justin explains that the kind of "market 
 socialism" that he favors involves workers' control. You should have said 
 so earlier, Justin, because there are a lot of different kinds of market 
 socialism (cf. Roemer). In any event, if workers control factories, that 
 would probably prevent a race to the bottom, or at least discourage it. But 
 it does not negate the other problems with markets.

Right. I guess I thought I had explained that.
 
 I think that the comment that "planning (without markets) won't work, would 
 be inefficient" begs the question. What is meant by "working" here? 

Well, I think it wouldn't work in the sense that without accurate information 
in the system, the planning would be inaccurate, needs would not be met, 
there would be massive waste, people would spend a lot oif time making stuff 
no one wanted, while there would chronic shortages and bottlenecks, and 
innovation would be stifled,. In short, pure planning would replicate many of 
the flaws of the former Soviet economy.

  The term "efficiency" also does not speak for itself. It refers to the 
 successful attainment of given goals. That means that the "efficiency" of 
 the market would be judged differently by socialists and capitalists, 

Sure. I defined efficiency in terms of lack of waste, real needs are actually 
met with minimal expenditure of available resources. That strikes me as a 
socialist, or anyway a humane, notion of efficiency.

  (The standard kind of 
 efficiency that economists invoke is Pareto Optimality, which preserves the 
 existing distribution of wealth.) Or you should be very specific by what 
 you mean by efficiency, adding qualifications, such as "allocative 
 efficiency".

I don't mean Pareto Optimality, obviously, or I wouldn't be a socialist.
 
  In any event, markets aren't efficient by any standard if externalities 
 exist (as they do, in spades), if information problems exist, if one of 
 your goals is egalitarian distribution of power, etc.  Economists outside of 
the University of Chicago and its pseudopodia are 
 quite conscious of market inefficiencies. 

Sure. That's why I am in favor of big government, aggressive regulation, etc.

  More importantly, I think that the parenthetical remark has things 
 precisely backward. I'd say instead that in a planning context, some, even 
 much, market allocation is fine. This requires qualification and 
 explanation, of course.
 
 First, I think ideas of "market socialism" (or even better, Diane Elston's 
 idea of "socialized markets") make sense as part of a _transitional 
 socialism_, since the idea of instantly abolishing markets is crazy. ( Of 
 course, _all_ socialisms are 

Designing Institutions: Is it Possible?, was Market Socialism, etc.

2000-07-15 Thread Carrol Cox



Rod Hay wrote:


 If rationing is required, I think that we can design other institutions that do the 
job better than the market can. Hence my advocacy (and I think Jim's) of democratic 
control.

When a debate goes on as wildly as this debate has (and as the same debate has in the 
past on other lists), one strong possibility is that (a) the parties to the debate (a) 
really do not and cannot understand each other and (b) the propositions explicitly 
argued are not the questions actully at issue.

I'm not sure myself what the core issues at stake are, but I want to make a 
preliminary stab at naming one of them.

*Both* parties to the debate are deeply suspicious of Planning. And *both* parties to 
the debate see the other as dangerously committed to planning -- the danger being that 
of authoritarian and terrorist rule.

Justin believes that socialist planning of the economy wrong for two reasons:

1. It won't work (it is inefficient) and those in control will therefore 
resort to terrorist or at least very heavy-handed methods ("Administrative Methods" 
the Chinese called them) to make work what is unworkable.

2. Workers need a clear goal in order to be brought to vote for a socialist 
system. Hence it is important to design in advance (plan) the institutions which can 
work. The sort of negative organizing which I for example advocate (there are many 
variations on this, discussed at the end of this post) is impractical, utopian, 
because it can never attract a sufficient number of workers to bring about a social 
change. (I'm not sure how to word what follows, so I won't necessarily defend my 
specific wording.) And as a result those who favor such
organizing will *in practice* end up supporting some sort of minority ("elitist," 
"bureaucratic") revolution imposing an authoritarian rule by bureaucracy.

-

Now, Rod is trying to make the debate as rational as possible, and very roughly 
speaking he and I are on the "same" side. There is a possible serious difference, 
however, as brought out in the wording of the post quoted above: Rod believes that 
institutions can be *designed*. He also believes in democratic control, however, and 
that may qualify the meaning of "design" in this context. In any case, I believe, 
roughly, that the designing of institutions *in thought* is fundamentally 
totalitarian. I object, that is, to the kind of "Planning" that Doug and
Justin both seem to propose: the planning in advance of the kind of institutions that 
will characterize a socialist order.

Now this kind of intellectual conviction will obviously be accompanied by reasonably 
strong feeling, and when that feeling comes out quickly, it results in the kind of 
insults that Justin and I exchanged.

Extrapolated into the future then, both sides (with some historical justification for 
each) believe that the other's position can only result in authoritarian terror. Now I 
doubt very much that either Justin or Doug would (at this time) propose shooting 
Carrol or Yoshie. And neither of us would propose shooting Justin or Doug. But they 
*do* think that our kind of "planning" will result (if successful) in people like them 
being shot. And we *do* think that that commitment to "planning" of their type will 
under quite possible historical conditions
(conditions that have in fact occurred in the past) result in the shooting of people 
like us.


This is clumsy. But I think Justin and Doug should recognize (even if they cannot 
understand) that both sides do object to planning -- it is just that each side has a 
different perception of the *kind* of planning which is most dangerous.

And it is important to see that each side also regards the other as impossibly 
utopian, and to see why this is so. And the kind of utopianism of which each suspects 
the other is the kind which, developed in practice, leads to authoritarian terror. But 
I'll leave that for another post.

Carrol





Re: Designing Institutions: Is it Possible?, was Market Socialism, etc.

2000-07-15 Thread Ken Hanly

I am not deeply suspicious of planning but of markets. I am not merely suspicious of 
markets but on the whole I think them (real markets)  evil and to be dispensed with as 
far as possible since they ration unjustly, do not take into account externalities, do 
not consider needs but effective demand only and  lead not to efficiency but anarchy 
(pace anarchists) in production. I do not favor top-down command planning with no 
citizen and NGO input into the plan but that is another matter.
   Cheers, Ken Hanly

Carrol Cox wrote:

 Rod Hay wrote:

 
  If rationing is required, I think that we can design other institutions that do 
the job better than the market can. Hence my advocacy (and I think Jim's) of 
democratic control.

 When a debate goes on as wildly as this debate has (and as the same debate has in 
the past on other lists), one strong possibility is that (a) the parties to the 
debate (a) really do not and cannot understand each other and (b) the propositions 
explicitly argued are not the questions actully at issue.

 I'm not sure myself what the core issues at stake are, but I want to make a 
preliminary stab at naming one of them.

 *Both* parties to the debate are deeply suspicious of Planning. And *both* parties 
to the debate see the other as dangerously committed to planning -- the danger being 
that of authoritarian and terrorist rule.

 Justin believes that socialist planning of the economy wrong for two reasons:

 1. It won't work (it is inefficient) and those in control will therefore 
resort to terrorist or at least very heavy-handed methods ("Administrative Methods" 
the Chinese called them) to make work what is unworkable.

 2. Workers need a clear goal in order to be brought to vote for a socialist 
system. Hence it is important to design in advance (plan) the institutions which can 
work. The sort of negative organizing which I for example advocate (there are many 
variations on this, discussed at the end of this post) is impractical, utopian, 
because it can never attract a sufficient number of workers to bring about a social 
change. (I'm not sure how to word what follows, so I won't necessarily defend my 
specific wording.) And as a result those who favor such
 organizing will *in practice* end up supporting some sort of minority ("elitist," 
"bureaucratic") revolution imposing an authoritarian rule by bureaucracy.

 -

 Now, Rod is trying to make the debate as rational as possible, and very roughly 
speaking he and I are on the "same" side. There is a possible serious difference, 
however, as brought out in the wording of the post quoted above: Rod believes that 
institutions can be *designed*. He also believes in democratic control, however, and 
that may qualify the meaning of "design" in this context. In any case, I believe, 
roughly, that the designing of institutions *in thought* is fundamentally 
totalitarian. I object, that is, to the kind of "Planning" that Doug and
 Justin both seem to propose: the planning in advance of the kind of institutions 
that will characterize a socialist order.

 Now this kind of intellectual conviction will obviously be accompanied by reasonably 
strong feeling, and when that feeling comes out quickly, it results in the kind of 
insults that Justin and I exchanged.

 Extrapolated into the future then, both sides (with some historical justification 
for each) believe that the other's position can only result in authoritarian terror. 
Now I doubt very much that either Justin or Doug would (at this time) propose 
shooting Carrol or Yoshie. And neither of us would propose shooting Justin or Doug. 
But they *do* think that our kind of "planning" will result (if successful) in people 
like them being shot. And we *do* think that that commitment to "planning" of their 
type will under quite possible historical conditions
 (conditions that have in fact occurred in the past) result in the shooting of people 
like us.

 This is clumsy. But I think Justin and Doug should recognize (even if they cannot 
understand) that both sides do object to planning -- it is just that each side has a 
different perception of the *kind* of planning which is most dangerous.

 And it is important to see that each side also regards the other as impossibly 
utopian, and to see why this is so. And the kind of utopianism of which each suspects 
the other is the kind which, developed in practice, leads to authoritarian terror. 
But I'll leave that for another post.

 Carrol




market socialism, etc.

2000-07-14 Thread Jim Devine

1. Justin writes: Please show me how the Hayekian argument I have been 
running depends on any particular features of planning that are peculiar to 
a Soviet-style planning process. It doesn't. The argument is abosolutely 
general. Waving the words "decentralized" and "democratic" doesn't expalin 
where we get incentives to find out correct information, reduce waste, 
innovate new producrs, services and production methids. "Decentralized 
democratic planning" is a shibboleth, meaningless. It answers NO questions. 

So you say. And I did NOT use the phrase "decentralized democratic 
planning" but instead _explained_ what I meant. Please read what I say.

The point is (to repeat myself) that if the _centralized_ part of the 
planning process is only dealing with _abstract_ (or general) issues like 
the growth rate of the economy or the percentage of the total product that 
goes into investment or the balance between broad industrial sectors, 
there's no need for some Hayekian all-knowledgeable mind. If the Federal 
Reserve can make the decisions it makes in planning the US economy (along 
with its spillovers to the rest of the world), it's pretty easy for a 
democratically-controlled planning agency to deal with equally general 
issues. It might be more difficult, because there are more issues, but not 
impossible.

 I also think it's not planning: I mean, what makes it planned, if the 
decisions are made indeoendently of each other by production units and not 
coordinated? How's that different from markets operating "behind the backs 
of the producers," with all their disadvantages and none of theor 
advantages? But set that aside.

Did you read the part where I noted that individual units made decisions 
within the framework set by the central planning agency? If so, you would 
have noted that decisions are not made "independently of each other." I 
used the word "independent" to mean as opposed to being under the thumb of 
the central bureaucracy. True independence of all of society is in any case 
impossible.

 The point is that we can learn from the Soviet experience of planning 
just as we can learb from the capitalist experience of markets. But the 
Hayek argument is general. It applies to all situations where there are no 
markets and production and distribution are authoritatively (or if you 
will, democratically) allocated. The objection is not based on the Soviet 
experience: in fact it antedates the Soviet experience. It does not 
presuppose an undemocratic one party state and a top down planning process. 
It presupposes only lack of competition and production being determined by 
some sort of targets arrived at politically. So let's avoid this red 
herring and actually argue the issues, shall we?

One of the problems with the Hayekian argument is that it ignores the role 
of the undemocratic one-party state. In fact, Hayekians want such a state 
in order to prevent popular-democratic meddling with the beloved and sacred 
free market. (If he's like other "great thinker," Hayek was superior to his 
followers.) The ideal _laissez-faire_ system has a Pinochet in charge or a 
denatured democracy with many important powers spun off to "independent" 
agencies like the Fed which respond to the moneyed interests.

Another problem is that there's an either/or here: plan _versus_ market. We 
don't have to go that way. For example, in Pat (no relation) Devine's model 
of planning, markets are used to make static decisions (subject to all 
sorts of government regulations to deal with externalities, unlike in the 
Hayekian vision) whereas the plan is used for more dynamic decisions. Note 
that in a different post, Justin gives a vague description of Schweickart's 
scheme that sounds similar to P. (NR) Devine's scheme. Maybe this can get 
us away from false market vs. plan dichotomies and allow some agreement.

And what is competition? is it the mythical passive competition of lemonade 
stands for the consumer's business? is it the competition of small 
workshops hiring small numbers of workers who had similar resources to 
their "masters" that Smith saw? is it the grinding competition that drives 
small farmers out of business, into the hands of agribusiness, or under the 
thumbs of the agro-industrial complex? is it the aggressive competition of 
oligopolistic firms, trying by hook or crook or dirty trick to get 
advantage and market share? is it the competition of factions within the 
CPSU? We need clarity, not the wielding of neoclassical shibboleths.

2. in a different message, Justin wrote: No, we are not against democracy. 
But we have to recognize that not all its effects are wholly good in every 
context. In the context of planning, democarcy would make the calculation 
problem worse by amplifying the information distortions it involves. 
Democracy is not part of the solution to the calculation problem.

What do _you_ mean by the "calculation problem"? To me, ultimately the 
democratic electorate 

Re: market socialism, etc.

2000-07-14 Thread JKSCHW

Jim:

Attacking Hayek for being too neoclassical is like attacking Marx for being too 
neoclassical. Hayek, Mises, and the Austrians dislike NCE for many of the same reasons 
that Marxists do: it's a poor description of actual markets (this is more Hayek than 
Mises) and does not correctly model how they work. Austrians tend to go overboard 
about their good effects, as Marxists do about their bad ones, but they are of one 
mind that NCE is not very impressive. Please, go read Hayek's Individualisma nd the 
Economic Order (Chicagao 1940+/-); it's short, clear, accessible, and reading it will 
avoid many problems and misunderstandings in the discussion. Besides, it is a very 
good and important book.

In a message dated Fri, 14 Jul 2000  4:51:08 PM Eastern Daylight Time, Jim Devine 
[EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:
 The point is (to repeat myself) that if the _centralized_ part of the 
planning process is only dealing with _abstract_ (or general) issues like 
the growth rate of the economy or the percentage of the total product that 
goes into investment or the balance between broad industrial sectors, 
there's no need for some Hayekian all-knowledgeable mind. 

OK, I agree with that sort of planning, as long as there are competitive markets 
operating below the Fed level.

I asked:  I also think it's not planning: I mean, what makes it planned, if the 
decisions are made indeoendently of each other by production units and not 
coordinated? 

 Did you read the part where I noted that individual units made decisions 
within the framework set by the central planning agency? If so, you would 
have noted that decisions are not made "independently of each other." I 
used the word "independent" to mean as opposed to being under the thumb of 
the central bureaucracy. True independence of all of society is in any case 
impossible.

OK, so we have competitive production units operating within Fed-like constraints? Or 
we have little monopolies meeting targets (set by whom?) as they see fit under the 
very broad and general supervision of government planning boards which exercise some 
kind of oversight, but not central planning? I am hazy here, help me out.

  One of the problems with the Hayekian argument is that it ignores the role 
of the undemocratic one-party state.

This concedes taht nothing in the Hayekian argument depends on the existence of such a 
state.

  In fact, Hayekians want such a state 
in order to prevent popular-democratic meddling with the beloved and sacred 
free market. 

Well, in his political philosophy, Hayek was no fan of democracy. He blamed Hitler on 
democracy, foolish man. Hayek did not advocate a  single-party state but rather a 
Schumpterian elite-compition democracy and a fairly minimal state. But I am no fan of 
Hayek's political philosophy. I do not have to be to see he is onto something with his 
calculation argument, any more than I have to subscribe to Marx's romantic ideal of 
planning to appreciate his critique of capitalism.

 (If he's like other "great thinker," Hayek was superior to his 
followers.)

Meaning what, that he was smarter and more creative than them? Pretty much, yes, as 
Marx was smarter and more creative  than we are. 

  Another problem is that there's an either/or here: plan _versus_ market. We 
don't have to go that way. 

Sure, of course. I am a _market SOCIALIST_ after all. Plan what you can, I say, and 
market what you must.


 And what is competition? is it the mythical passive competition of lemonade 
stands for the consumer's business? is it the competition of small 
workshops hiring small numbers of workers who had similar resources to 
their "masters" that Smith saw? is it the grinding competition that drives 
small farmers out of business, into the hands of agribusiness, or under the 
thumbs of the agro-industrial complex? is it the aggressive competition of 
oligopolistic firms, trying by hook or crook or dirty trick to get 
advantage and market share? is it the competition of factions within the 
CPSU? We need clarity, not the wielding of neoclassical shibboleths.

Ideally, it is fairly vigorous competition between worker-managed cooperatives who are 
actively trying to promote markets for products and services with new ways of makiing 
old ones and new products and services that no one has thought of, with at least 
enough coops in play so that there is actual consumer choice. For technical reasons 
(the Ward effect), coops will tend to be smallish, so more vigorous competition is 
likelier. i will explain this later.

I said:
 Democracy is not part of the solution to the calculation problem.

Jim asks, "What do you mean by the calculation problem?"

Sigh. The calculation problem is the name given in the literature to the set of 
objections to planning that I have been pushing. It goes back to Mises' 1920 article 
on "Economic Calculationa nd the Socialist Commonwealth."

  To me, ultimately the 
democratic electorate must be sovereign, i.e., 

Re: Re: market socialism, etc.

2000-07-14 Thread michael

A paper at the History of Economics session connected Hayek with A.
Carr-Saunders, an important eugenicist, who apparently inspired much of
Hayek's thinking on spontaneous order.  I also used C.-S., many years ago,
because I was impressed with his analysis of pre-industrial women's
ability to control their reproductive systems.
 -- 
Michael Perelman
Economics Department
California State University
Chico, CA 95929

Tel. 530-898-5321
E-Mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]




[PEN-L:8707] Re: market socialism, etc.

1997-02-18 Thread Justin Schwartz


I agree that putting the costs on others and taking the advantages for
oneself is how capitalist politics works. In fact my statement is a very
close paraphrase of one by Justice Holmes (talking about capitalist
legislation). The point that this is a psecial problems for planned
socialism is that in it, the whole economy is politicized; there's no room
for any nonpoliticized decisionmaking. I agree that rich coops exercising
power in virtue of their wealth would be a problem in MS. --jks

On Mon, 17 Feb 1997 [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:

 About a Hahnel  Albert-type socialism, Justin S writes: 
 Politicization of the whole economy will mean that each group 
 will try to put the burdens and costs on other groups while
 reapin[g] advantages for themselves.
 
 Wait a sec, Justin! that's _exactly_ the way a capitalist market 
 works (see, e.g., E.K. Hunt's critique of welfare economics in 
 the Ed Nell edited volume, GROWTH, PROFITS, AND PROPERTY). I see 
 _no_ reason to see a "socialist market" not acting in the same 
 way. A "socialized market" would involve a lot of regulation, 
 special taxes, etc. This in turn would encourage lobbying by the 
 producers (whether they're run as cooperatives or not), in order 
 to ease their regulatory burden and the effluent taxes they have 
 to pay (and raise the bounties they get from central authorities 
 for producing external benefits). Of course, the wealthier or 
 luckier producers (co-ops) would have the most influence... They 
 can then turn that influence into greater wealth. So they could 
 dump costs on others and "internalize the external economies" of 
 others. 
 
 At least you have to admit that Robin is addressing the issue of 
 how one can structure a socialist economy to avoid encouraging 
 the aggressive-individualistic or particularistic motives that 
 are both encouraged by and mess up the capitalist market and the 
 "socialized market."  
 
 BTW, Marx accurately pointed to the increasingly overt 
 socialization of individualized production. In more common-sense 
 terms, this refers to the growth of economic power, 
 interdependency, the importance of external costs  benefits, 
 etc., etc. Increased socialization of production automatically 
 produces increased politicization of individual activities. We 
 can't avoid that politicization (meaning that we can't go up to 
 our cabins in the woods, become totally self-sufficient, and 
 avoid all other people). The question is: is the politicization 
 going to be democratic (one person/one vote) or capitalist (one 
 dollar/one vote)? 
 
 I didn't see my pen-l missive on this subject from last week in 
 the pen-l archives at csf.colorado.edu (or even in my own 
 archives), so here it is again. Sorry if it is repetitive, 
 redundant, pleonastic, or duplicative. 
 
 In addition to the issue of external costs  benefits, Robin 
 Hahnel is onto something that Kenneth Arrow noted a long time 
 ago:
 
 "Under the system of a free market, such feelings [social values, 
 the ordering of social states according to moral standards] play 
 no direct part in social choice... The market mechanism... takes 
 into account only the ordering according to tastes [the ordering 
 according to the direct consumption by the individual]." (SOCIAL 
 CHOICE AND INDIVIDUAL VALUES, 1963: p. 18). Social preferences, 
 like feelings of solidarity, cannot be expressed in an atomized 
 market setting. 
 
 Robin also stresses how a competitive environment encourages the 
 type of personality that actively externalizes external costs 
 (i.e., dumps) and internalizes internal benefits (cream-skims, 
 etc.) Since external costs and benefits (including the 
 "pecuniary" ones) are omnipresent, this argument has to be 
 answered seriously.
 
 I'll get back to the NAIRU later...
 
 in pen-l solidarity,
 
 Jim Devine   [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Econ. Dept., Loyola Marymount Univ.
 7900 Loyola Blvd., Los Angeles, CA 90045-8410 USA
 310/338-2948 (daytime, during workweek); FAX: 310/338-1950
 "Segui il tuo corso, e lascia dir le genti." (Go your own way
 and let people talk.) -- K. Marx, paraphrasing Dante A.
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 








[PEN-L:8668] Re: market socialism, etc.

1997-02-17 Thread Anders Schneiderman

At 09:45 AM 2/17/97 -0800, Jim wrote:
In addition to the issue of external costs  benefits, Robin 
Hahnel is onto something that Kenneth Arrow noted a long time 
ago:
"Under the system of a free market, such feelings [social values, 
the ordering of social states according to moral standards] play 
no direct part in social choice... The market mechanism... takes 
into account only the ordering according to tastes [the ordering 
according to the direct consumption by the individual]." (SOCIAL 
CHOICE AND INDIVIDUAL VALUES, 1963: p. 18). Social preferences, 
like feelings of solidarity, cannot be expressed in an atomized 
market setting. 

And more recently, Soros of all people said something quite similar; for an
interesting, somewhat bizarre read, check out the latest Atlantic.  Among
other things, Soros admits that (surprise!) simply unleashing capitalism in
Eastern Europe failed miserably, and he says that unfettered laissez-faire
policies may destroy our society. Not exactly a shocker for folks here, but
it's fun to have someone like Soros to smack Right-wingers over the head.  

Anders Schneiderman
Progressive Communications





[PEN-L:8658] market socialism, etc.

1997-02-17 Thread JDevine

About a Hahnel  Albert-type socialism, Justin S writes: 
Politicization of the whole economy will mean that each group 
will try to put the burdens and costs on other groups while
reapin[g] advantages for themselves.

Wait a sec, Justin! that's _exactly_ the way a capitalist market 
works (see, e.g., E.K. Hunt's critique of welfare economics in 
the Ed Nell edited volume, GROWTH, PROFITS, AND PROPERTY). I see 
_no_ reason to see a "socialist market" not acting in the same 
way. A "socialized market" would involve a lot of regulation, 
special taxes, etc. This in turn would encourage lobbying by the 
producers (whether they're run as cooperatives or not), in order 
to ease their regulatory burden and the effluent taxes they have 
to pay (and raise the bounties they get from central authorities 
for producing external benefits). Of course, the wealthier or 
luckier producers (co-ops) would have the most influence... They 
can then turn that influence into greater wealth. So they could 
dump costs on others and "internalize the external economies" of 
others. 

At least you have to admit that Robin is addressing the issue of 
how one can structure a socialist economy to avoid encouraging 
the aggressive-individualistic or particularistic motives that 
are both encouraged by and mess up the capitalist market and the 
"socialized market."  

BTW, Marx accurately pointed to the increasingly overt 
socialization of individualized production. In more common-sense 
terms, this refers to the growth of economic power, 
interdependency, the importance of external costs  benefits, 
etc., etc. Increased socialization of production automatically 
produces increased politicization of individual activities. We 
can't avoid that politicization (meaning that we can't go up to 
our cabins in the woods, become totally self-sufficient, and 
avoid all other people). The question is: is the politicization 
going to be democratic (one person/one vote) or capitalist (one 
dollar/one vote)? 

I didn't see my pen-l missive on this subject from last week in 
the pen-l archives at csf.colorado.edu (or even in my own 
archives), so here it is again. Sorry if it is repetitive, 
redundant, pleonastic, or duplicative. 

In addition to the issue of external costs  benefits, Robin 
Hahnel is onto something that Kenneth Arrow noted a long time 
ago:

"Under the system of a free market, such feelings [social values, 
the ordering of social states according to moral standards] play 
no direct part in social choice... The market mechanism... takes 
into account only the ordering according to tastes [the ordering 
according to the direct consumption by the individual]." (SOCIAL 
CHOICE AND INDIVIDUAL VALUES, 1963: p. 18). Social preferences, 
like feelings of solidarity, cannot be expressed in an atomized 
market setting. 

Robin also stresses how a competitive environment encourages the 
type of personality that actively externalizes external costs 
(i.e., dumps) and internalizes internal benefits (cream-skims, 
etc.) Since external costs and benefits (including the 
"pecuniary" ones) are omnipresent, this argument has to be 
answered seriously.

I'll get back to the NAIRU later...

in pen-l solidarity,

Jim Devine   [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Econ. Dept., Loyola Marymount Univ.
7900 Loyola Blvd., Los Angeles, CA 90045-8410 USA
310/338-2948 (daytime, during workweek); FAX: 310/338-1950
"Segui il tuo corso, e lascia dir le genti." (Go your own way
and let people talk.) -- K. Marx, paraphrasing Dante A.