RE: Florida Voucher Decision

2004-11-15 Thread A.E. Brownstein
-to-aid cases. It has been either explicitly or
implicitly
rejected there; and I think that it should be rejected in the aid
context
too (because in both cases, if there is a federal principle of
nondiscrimination -- whether free speech or free exercise -- the
state
provision is itself flawed and should not be given effect to bind
the
government).

Alan, I would be interested in hearing more about precisely why the
distinctions you raise would be relevant to the logic of this must
satisfy
both provisions argument.
 _ 
From: Alan Brownstein
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]]
Sent: Sat 11/13/2004 5:35 PM
To: Berg, Thomas C.; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Florida Voucher Decision


I think Tom may be half right here. 
First, Tom's concerns are only relevant if the Florida Court is wrong

about the free exercise issue regarding discrimination in subsidies 

between religious and non-religious institutions. (If the Florida Court

is right about the free exercise issue, this case isn't going to have any

application to forum cases, because it is completely clear that you can

not discriminatorily deny access to religious speech in a public or 

nonpublic forum.) 
If the Florida courts are wrong and the free exercise clause of the First

Amendment's prohibition of state discrimination against religion applies

to funding schemes that exclude subsidies for religious schools, I can

easily see a state supreme court holding that the Florida constitutional

provision is discriminatory and unconstitutional on its face and can not

be enforced to invalidate any Florida law. The Florida legislature would

be free to repeal a voucher program once it learned that by virtue of

federal constitutional mandate the program had to include religious 

schools. But I don't see how a facially invalid state constitutional

provision could force it to do so. I think Tom's point is well taken
here. 
On the other hand, I think a state supreme court could try to give the

state constitutional provision a construction that withstands federal

constitutional review and is faithful to the values expressed in the

state constitution. That could justify striking the entire voucher scheme

down on the ground that no such subsidy scheme could satisfy both 
constitutional guaranttees. Thus, I think Marty is correct that if the

Florida Court is wrong about the First Amendment, what is at issue here

may primarily be a matter of state constitutional law. 
I would look at the issue this way. If you sever the funding of religious

schools to comply with the Florida constitution, you violate the federal

constitution? If you don't sever the funding of religious schools and

strike the program down under the Florida Constitution because it 
involves funding religious schools, I also think you violate the federal

constitution. It is still a discriminatory provision that requires 
striking the program down. The only way you avoid violating the federal

constitution is by interpreting the Florida Constitution to prohibit all

funding programs for which religious institutions might be eligible 

recipients of state support. In essence, the Florida provision would be

interpreted to mandate that whenever the state legislature is required by

federal constitutional law to either fund religious institutions as part

of a neutral subsidy program or cancel the program in its entirety, the

legislature must cancel the program. If that is right, (and I concede it

is a real stretch), it is the interpretation of the Florida Constitution

that does most of the heavy lifting in this case -- the lack of 
severability is not all that important. Tom. Do you think that a state

constitutional provision that said this explicitly would violate the free

exercise clause? 
Further, unlike Tom, I do not think such a decision would necessarily

effect equal access cases relating to discrimination against religious

speech in public or nonpublic forums. 
I think the religion clauses and the free speech clause serve very 
different purposes and are doctrinally distinct in a variety of ways.

Accordingly, I do not think one can simply assume that the termination of

a voucher program including private religious schools in order to satisfy

both federal and state constitutional guarantees relating to free 
exercise and establishment clause concerns requires or is equivalent to

the closure of a forum including religious _expression_ to satisfy free

speech mandates. Maybe there is an argument why these two doctrinal 

frameworks have to track each other. I'm not saying that this argument

can't be made, just that Tom has not made it yet. 

Alan Brownstein 
UC Davis 



___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private

RE: Florida Voucher Decision

2004-11-13 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
 treatment by requiring the closure of the
entire voucher program.  Perhaps Davey will ultimately be read to reject
the challenge, but courts can't avoid deciding it.
 
Tom Berg
University of St. Thomas (Minnesota)
  

  _  

From: Marty Lederman [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Sat 11/13/2004 8:48 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Florida Voucher Decision


Once again, what I find most odd about this case is that, as a result of the
trial court's injunction, it does not involve any discrimination against
religious schools.  
 
Assume, for the sake of argument, that the majority is wrong in holding that
Davey controls here, and that, in fact, it would violate the Free Exercise
Clause for Florida to prevent religious schools from receiving vouchers that
are available for use in nonreligious private schools.  Even so, the Florida
Constitution, as construed by the trial court and by the majority of the
court of appeals, does not require discrimination against religion.  It
merely requires that no aid be diverted to religious schools.  The trial
court honored this injunction without discriminating against religion by
ruling that the entire private-school voucher program was invalid, as to
religious and secular private schools alike.
 
Judge Wolf concludes that this was wrong, and that at the very least the
statute should be upheld as to nonreligious schools.  But the Governor did
not argue in favor of severability, and the majority concludes (fn. 4) --
not without reason -- that we cannot say that the Florida Legislature . . .
would have adopted the OSP without vouchers being provided to sectarian
schools.
 
What the trial court did, arguably, was to honor both constitutional
commands.  The Florida Constitution (arguably) says no aid to religious
schools.  The Free Exercise Clause (argubaly) says no discrimination against
religious private schools.  Thus, the only regime that is constitutional is
one in which no aid is given to any private schools.
 
Can there be a Free Exercise violation in such circumstances?  Is the
question analogous to Palmer v. Thompson?  The dissent says that facial
neutrality is not constitutionally sufficient if the exclusion of all
private schools is motivated by a desire to exclude religious schools.  In
support of this proposition, the dissent cites two district court decisions
-- one holding that a government cannot eliminate a public forum to avoid a
requirement of viewpoint neutrality, and the other holding that a government
canmot eliminate a public forum in order to avoid requirements of
race-neutrality.  The former holding is simply wrong as a matter of Free
Speech doctrine, I believe; and the latter is in considerable tension with
Palmer, if I'm not mistaken.
 
I suppose that if the burden of the injunction falls overwhelmingly on
religious schools, I suppose there might be an argument under Lukumi that
facial neutrality is not sufficient.  (Such an argument would be potentially
perilous, however.  If the fact that most private schools are religious can
be used as proof that an exclusion of vouchers to such schools is
impermissibly neutral despite its general applicability, then wouldn't the
legislature's initial decision to permit vouchers to be used at private
schools likewise betray a constitutionally dubious purpose to support
religious schools?)
 
Does anyone on the list think that the facially neutral trial court
injunction violates the Free Exercise Clause?  
 
 
- Original Message - 
From: Rick Garnett  mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Friday, November 12, 2004 5:31 PM
Subject: Re: Florida Voucher Decision


 Dear all,
 
 Thanks very much to Michael for forwarding the Florida court's decision.
I 
 am not surprised by the result, but I am surprised by (what I regard as) 
 the court's failure meaningfully to confront the original social meaning

 and purpose of Florida's no-aid provision and other similar provisions.
 
 For example:  In footnote 9, the Florida court states that [w]hether the 
 Blaine-era amendments are based on religious bigotry is a disputed and 
 controversial issue among historians and legal scholars and that [some] 
 commentators argue . . .  that anti-Catholic bigotry did not play a 
 significant role in the development of Blaine-era no-aid provisions in 
 state constitutions.  (True enough).  For the latter proposition, though,

 the court cites only (1) a detailed article on the Indiana no-aid 
 provision, which observed that, in 1850, Indiana had very few Catholics
and 
 concluded that the Indiana provision was neither nativist nor 
 anti-Catholic; and (2) Chief Justice Rehnquist's observation in Davey that

 the provision at issue in that case had not been connected by Davey to the

 Blaine Amendment.  But does Indiana's situation in 1850 -- even assuming 
 that the article's author is correct -- really support

Re: Florida Voucher Decision

2004-11-13 Thread Steven Jamar
It is lawful to discriminate for and against religions.  Indeed the 
Constitution mandates EXACTLY that.

The government can establish lots of  things (or seek to), e.g., 
patriotism, individualism, tolerance.  But it cannot establish 
religion.  It therefore must discriminate in what it chooses to 
establish on the  basis, at least in part, of religion.

The government can ban all sorts of behavior and can zone property in 
all sorts of ways.  But it cannot zone in such a way as to exclude all 
religious buildings or activity.  It could prohibit all multiple-unit 
dwellings.  Or all heavy industry.  Or all educational institutions.  
But it can't do that with respect to religion.  This is discrimination 
for religion.

Discrimination is not a sufficiently robust concept to handle the 
inevitable conflicts and nuances involved in religious cases.

The principles of non-discrimination and equal treatment have their 
place in constitutional religious freedom analysis, but they are not 
sufficient.  Nor is accommodation.  Nor is coercion.  Nor is separation.

The tension exposed in no-taxpayer support v. non-discrimination in the 
voucher cases can be resolved either by favoring one theory over the 
other a la the Rosenberger case (favoring equal treatment over no 
funding) or through some other balancing approach which forthrightly 
recognizes the conflict and chooses not to go one way or the other  on 
the basis of selecting which principle has priority, but rather 
choosing, in the Justice O'Connor mode, a nuanced, case by case 
analysis in which such principles play a part in the decision.

Of course this does not give us bright-line tests, which in itself 
creates problems.

But this, it seems to me, is the very nature of the beast and it cannot 
be tamed or beaten out of it no matter how many of us try to dance on 
the head of that metaphorical pin of logical consistency.

Steve
--
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8428
2900 Van Ness Street NW mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Washington, DC  20008  http://www.law.howard.edu/faculty/pages/jamar
The only things truly worth doing cannot be accomplished in a single 
lifetime.

Prof. Goler Teal Butcher, after Reinhold Neibuhr
___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.


Florida Voucher Decision

2004-11-13 Thread Marty Lederman



If I understandTom's post correctly, he 
agrees with the majority in the Florida casethat there is no 
FreeExercise violation here because Florida (i.e., the state courts, 
construing the legislature's intent as to "severability") is 
nottreating religious schools unfavorably vis-a-vis 
otherprivate schools. And that was the principal question that I was 
asking -- i.e., could the university in Widmar have opted to close all 
classrooms to student groups once it learned that religious groups would have to 
be included?Tom says "yes." But the dissent in the Florida 
case says "no"! -- that if the closure was motivated by the objective of 
excluding religious groups, then the facially neutral closure itself violates 
the Free Exercise Clause. I think that's probably wrong, and it 
appears Tom agrees.

If possible, I'd like to hear from any listmembers 
who disagree with this conclusion, before the discussion veers away to the very 
interesting subsidiary question that Tom addresses.

The next question -- the one Tom's e-mail 
principally addresses -- is this: If (i) the Free Exercise Clause would 
prohibit discrimination against religious schools (which is contrary to the 
Florida's court's holding, but assume arguendo that the dissent is correct to 
distinguish Davey), and (ii) the 
FloridaConstitutionprohibits use of vouchers in religious schools, 
could the Florida Legislatureignore the Florida Constitution and 
enact a plan that permits vouchers to be used at religious and nonreligious 
schools alike? Tom is absolutely correct that nothing in the 
federal Constitution would prohibit the legislature from doing 
so. In Tom's words, the state has the "choice" between all or 
nothing. The problem, as I see it, is that the state has chosen 
--the State Constitution appears to compel the answer of 
"nothing."

Tom suggests that the effect of the federal 
constitutional command is not only to require nondiscrimination, but also to, in 
effect, erase, or invalidate, the "flawed" state constitutional provision, or, 
in any event, to make it "not binding" on lower-level state 
decisionmakers. That's a very interesting jurisprudential question, I 
think. Of course, we all know that when a court declares a statute (or 
state constitutional provision) "invalid," it does not mean that the provision 
magically disappears, or is thereby repealed. What it means is that the 
courts will enjoin any application of the statute that violates the federal 
constitutional norm.

If, therefore, the state constitution required that 
religious schools be "singled out" for disfavored treatment, as Tom suggests, 
then of course the lower-level state actors could never apply that provision in 
a manner consistent with a federal rule that such discrimination is 
unconstitutional -- because any such application would be enjoined. The 
difficulty with Tom's analysis, as I see it, is that the state constitutional 
norm here does not require religious schools to be singled out -- it 
merely requires that they not receive aid. The federal Constitution has 
not "invalidated" the refusal of Florida to give aid to religious 
schools -- Tom concedes that Florida need not do so as long as secular and 
religious schools alike. It has merely (that is to say, hypothetically, if 
the Florida court is wrong) prohibited discrimination. Therefore there is 
no conflict between the two constitutions, and the lower-level state actors must 
honor both.

I genuinely do not know whether this is correct -- 
but I think that it is a question of state, not federal, law. 
This is essentially the conclusion that Van Alstyne reached in an analogous 
context in his "Thirty Pieces of Silver" article -- that if Congress offers the 
state funds only on a condition that the state do something that is 
independently barred by the state's own constitution, the state has no choice 
but to decline the federal funds. On the other hand, 
Lead/Deadwood suggests otherwise, and would probably be support for 
Tom's theory.




- Original Message - 
From: "Berg, Thomas C." [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: "Law  Religion issues for Law Academics" 
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Saturday, November 13, 2004 11:03 
AM
Subject: RE: Florida Voucher 
Decision
I haven't read the Florida decision yet; but I've heard such 
reasoning before. As Marty describes the reasoning, it is 
inconsistent with the premises and result of Widmar, and indeed of a 
vast number of other public-forum cases. In Widmar, the Missouri 
state constitutional principle singling out religious groups for 
exclusion (in the name of strict separation) was overridden by the 
federal constitutional right of equal access. The result was that 
the state university must *either* close its classrooms to student 
groups on a religion-neutral basis *or* allow the religious group to 
meet. Had the Wi

RE: Florida Voucher Decision

2004-11-13 Thread Volokh, Eugene
 
Steve Jamar writes:

It is lawful to discriminate for and against religions.  Indeed the
Constitution mandates EXACTLY that.


People keep saying things like this (cf., e.g., some recent posts by Mark 
Graber), but it strikes me as a vast overreading of the Constitutional text 
(and of the caselaw).  Yes, the Establishment Clause discriminatorily prevents 
the government from establishing religion.  The government may establish 
environmentalism or animal rights as the state's official ideology, but not 
Christianity.  Fine.  But why should we take the leap from that to the 
conclusion that the government must or even may discriminate among private 
speakers or private entities based on their religiosity?
 
Likewise, the Free Exercise Clause discriminatorily protects religion against 
discrimination.  The government may single out rich people, short people, or 
people who use marijuana for negative action; but it may not single out 
religious people.  Fine.  But why should we take the leap from that to the 
conclusion that the government must or even may discriminate in favor of 
religion in other ways?
 
Certainly one can make normative arguments for why discrimination for or 
against religion more generally is proper.  The arguments for why equal 
treatment of religion is proper are normative arguments, though I do think that 
they are buttressed by the text of the Constitution (since establishment of 
religion, in my view, requires singling out religion for special benefit, 
since ignoring something generally doesn't establish it, and since free 
exercise of religion means at least exercise of religion free of government 
penalties imposed because of your exercise of religion).
 
But textual arguments for discrimination in favor of or against religion, based 
on supposed inferences from the Establishment Clause, strike me as quite 
unsound.  Congress [or states] shall make no law respecting an establishment 
of religion simply doesn't mean that states are required to, or even allowed 
to, discriminate among private individuals or groups based on religiosity.  
(Arguments for government discrimination in favor of religion, based on the 
text of the Free Exercise Clause, are a bit more plausible; but even those are 
hardly dispositive.)  If people want to make an argument that individuals' or 
groups' religious speech or religious practice deserves to be discriminated 
against, fine.  But I see no basis for claiming that the constitutional text 
authorizes or mandates such discrimination.
 
Eugene

 

Steve Jamar continued:

 


The government can establish lots of  things (or seek to), e.g.,
patriotism, individualism, tolerance.  But it cannot establish
religion.  It therefore must discriminate in what it chooses to
establish on the  basis, at least in part, of religion.

The government can ban all sorts of behavior and can zone property in
all sorts of ways.  But it cannot zone in such a way as to exclude all
religious buildings or activity.  It could prohibit all multiple-unit
dwellings.  Or all heavy industry.  Or all educational institutions. 
But it can't do that with respect to religion.  This is discrimination
for religion.

Discrimination is not a sufficiently robust concept to handle the
inevitable conflicts and nuances involved in religious cases.

The principles of non-discrimination and equal treatment have their
place in constitutional religious freedom analysis, but they are not
sufficient.  Nor is accommodation.  Nor is coercion.  Nor is separation.

The tension exposed in no-taxpayer support v. non-discrimination in the
voucher cases can be resolved either by favoring one theory over the
other a la the Rosenberger case (favoring equal treatment over no
funding) or through some other balancing approach which forthrightly
recognizes the conflict and chooses not to go one way or the other  on
the basis of selecting which principle has priority, but rather
choosing, in the Justice O'Connor mode, a nuanced, case by case
analysis in which such principles play a part in the decision.

Of course this does not give us bright-line tests, which in itself
creates problems.

But this, it seems to me, is the very nature of the beast and it cannot
be tamed or beaten out of it no matter how many of us try to dance on
the head of that metaphorical pin of logical consistency.

Steve

--
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8428
2900 Van Ness Street NW mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Washington, DC  20008  http://www.law.howard.edu/faculty/pages/jamar

The only things truly worth doing cannot be accomplished in a single
lifetime.

Prof. Goler Teal Butcher, after Reinhold Neibuhr

___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 

RE: Florida Voucher Decision

2004-11-13 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
I'll let others opine on the specific question Marty asks.  Since I'll be
unable to post for a while this afternoon, let me just make one comment on
the issue I raised, in response to Marty.  It may be true, as Marty says,
that the Florida constitutional provision doesn't require the singling out
of religious schools for no aid -- it just requires that they not receive
aid.  But the provision unquestionably does single out religious schools for
no aid:  it forbids aid to them while not forbidding aid to nonreligious
schools.  In that sense, the provision is surely discriminatory, even if the
state could also deny aid to other schools in order to produce an overall
nondiscriminatory result.  I don't see why a provision that is inherently
discriminatory in this way should be given the effect of forcing the state's
hand in this way.
 
Marty, do you agree with my claim that if the Florida court's argument is
right, it would not only require the invalidation of private-school
vouchers, but also would require the closure of forums in many of the
equal-access cases (all the ones where there was a general state or local
rule above the individual-school level that forbade, or was interpreted to
forbid, the use of classrooms for religious purposes) -- and that it could
also require the closure of forums in many cases where the excluded
perspective was not religious?  In other words, do you agree that the
Florida court's rationale could cut a very wide swath through the previous
equal-access logic of accept the excluded group or close the forum
altogether?
 
Tom Berg
 

  _  

From: Marty Lederman [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Sat 11/13/2004 10:45 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Florida Voucher Decision


If I understand Tom's post correctly, he agrees with the majority in the
Florida case that there is no Free Exercise violation here because Florida
(i.e., the state courts, construing the legislature's intent as to
severability) is not treating religious schools unfavorably vis-a-vis
other private schools.  And that was the principal question that I was
asking -- i.e., could the university in Widmar have opted to close all
classrooms to student groups once it learned that religious groups would
have to be included?  Tom says yes.  But the dissent in the Florida case
says no! -- that if the closure was motivated by the objective of
excluding religious groups, then the facially neutral closure itself
violates the Free Exercise Clause.  I think that's probably wrong, and it
appears Tom agrees.
 
If possible, I'd like to hear from any listmembers who disagree with this
conclusion, before the discussion veers away to the very interesting
subsidiary question that Tom addresses.
 
The next question -- the one Tom's e-mail principally addresses -- is this:
If (i) the Free Exercise Clause would prohibit discrimination against
religious schools (which is contrary to the Florida's court's holding, but
assume arguendo that the dissent is correct to distinguish Davey), and (ii)
the Florida Constitution prohibits use of vouchers in religious schools,
could the Florida Legislature ignore the Florida Constitution and enact a
plan that permits vouchers to be used at religious and nonreligious schools
alike?  Tom is absolutely correct that nothing in the federal Constitution
would prohibit the legislature from doing so.  In Tom's words, the state has
the choice between all or nothing.  The problem, as I see it, is that the
state has chosen -- the State Constitution appears to compel the answer of
nothing.
 
Tom suggests that the effect of the federal constitutional command is not
only to require nondiscrimination, but also to, in effect, erase, or
invalidate, the flawed state constitutional provision, or, in any event,
to make it not binding on lower-level state decisionmakers.  That's a very
interesting jurisprudential question, I think.  Of course, we all know that
when a court declares a statute (or state constitutional provision)
invalid, it does not mean that the provision magically disappears, or is
thereby repealed.  What it means is that the courts will enjoin any
application of the statute that violates the federal constitutional norm.
 
If, therefore, the state constitution required that religious schools be
singled out for disfavored treatment, as Tom suggests, then of course the
lower-level state actors could never apply that provision in a manner
consistent with a federal rule that such discrimination is unconstitutional
-- because any such application would be enjoined.  The difficulty with
Tom's analysis, as I see it, is that the state constitutional norm here does
not require religious schools to be singled out -- it merely requires that
they not receive aid.  The federal Constitution has not invalidated the
refusal of Florida to give aid to religious schools -- Tom concedes that
Florida need not do so as long as secular and religious schools alike.  It
has merely (that is to say

Re: Florida Voucher Decision

2004-11-13 Thread Marty Lederman



I don't have time just now to respond to Tom's 
question. But I did want to make clear that the argument about which Tom 
is concerned is not the argument of the Florida court 
majority.

The majority's argument is:

1. The Florida Constitution prohibits the use 
of vouchers in religiousschools.

2. The voucher statute is not severable as 
between secular and religious private schools, i.e., the Florida legislature 
would not have intended that vouchers could be used at secular schools if they 
cannot be used at religious schools.

3. Hence, the entire statute is invalid and 
enjoined, and vouchers may not be used at any private 
schools.

4. Because that injunction does not favor 
secular over religious private schools, it is facially and formally neutral, and 
therefore does not implicate Lukumi or the Free Exercise Clause. 
(The dissent takes issue with this conclusion; but as I understand Tom's earlier 
post, he agrees with me that the majority is probably correct.)

5. Even if there were discrimination against 
religious schools here -- i.e., even if the statute were severable, or the 
legislature were to enact a new statute permitting use of vouchers at private 
secular schools only -- that disparate treatment would be 
constitutional under Davey.

I am interested in others' views on point No. 
4.

Tom's question, by contrast,assumes arguendo 
that point No. 5 came out the other way, and asks whether, in that case, a state 
court or legislature could permit the use of vouchers at all private schools, or 
whether, instead, the state constitution would require that the voucher plan be 
prohibited for all private schools, unless and until the state 
constitution is amended. In my view, that is a question of state 
law.

- Original Message - 
From: "Berg, Thomas C." [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: "Law  Religion issues for Law Academics" 
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Saturday, November 13, 2004 2:02 
PM
Subject: RE: Florida Voucher 
Decision
 I'll let others opine on the specific question Marty asks. 
Since I'll be unable to post for a while this afternoon, let me just 
make one comment on the issue I raised, in response to Marty. It 
may be true, as Marty says, that the Florida constitutional provision 
doesn't "require the singling out of religious schools" for no aid -- it 
just requires that they not receive aid. But the provision 
unquestionably does single out religious schools for no aid: it 
forbids aid to them while not forbidding aid to nonreligious 
schools. In that sense, the provision is surely discriminatory, even if 
the state could also deny aid to other schools in order to produce an 
overall nondiscriminatory result. I don't see why a provision that 
is inherently discriminatory in this way should be given the effect of 
forcing the state's hand in this way. Marty, do 
you agree with my claim that if the Florida court's argument is right, 
it would not only require the invalidation of private-school vouchers, 
but also would require the closure of forums in many of the equal-access 
cases (all the ones where there was a general state or local rule above 
the individual-school level that forbade, or was interpreted to forbid, 
the use of classrooms for religious purposes) -- and that it could also 
require the closure of forums in many cases where the excluded 
perspective was not religious? In other words, do you agree that 
the Florida court's rationale could cut a very wide swath through the 
previous equal-access logic of "accept the excluded group or close the 
forum altogether"? Tom Berg 
 _   From: Marty Lederman 
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] Sent: Sat 11/13/2004 10:45 
AM To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics Subject: 
Florida Voucher Decision   If I understand Tom's post 
correctly, he agrees with the majority in the Florida case that there is 
no Free Exercise violation here because Florida (i.e., the state courts, 
construing the legislature's intent as to "severability") is not 
treating religious schools unfavorably vis-a-vis other private 
schools. And that was the principal question that I was asking -- 
i.e., could the university in Widmar have opted to close all classrooms 
to student groups once it learned that religious groups would have to be 
included? Tom says "yes." But the dissent in the Florida 
case says "no"! -- that if the closure was motivated by the objective 
of excluding religious groups, then the facially neutral closure 
itself violates the Free Exercise Clause. I think that's probably 
wrong, and it appears Tom agrees. If possible, I'd 
like to hear from any listmembers who disagree with this conclusion, 
before the discussion veers away to the very interesting subsidiary 
question that Tom addresses. The next question -- the one 
Tom's e-mail principally addresses -- is this: If (i) the Free Exercise 
Clause would prohibit discrimination against religious schools (wh

RE: Florida Voucher Decision

2004-11-13 Thread Alan Brownstein
 of private-school
 vouchers, but also would require the closure of forums in many of the
 equal-access cases (all the ones where there was a general state or 
local
 rule above the individual-school level that forbade, or was interpreted 
to
 forbid, the use of classrooms for religious purposes) -- and that it 
could
 also require the closure of forums in many cases where the excluded
 perspective was not religious?  In other words, do you agree that the
 Florida court's rationale could cut a very wide swath through the 
previous
 equal-access logic of accept the excluded group or close the forum
 altogether?
  
 Tom Berg
  
 
   _  
 
 From: Marty Lederman [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Sent: Sat 11/13/2004 10:45 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Florida Voucher Decision
 
 
 If I understand Tom's post correctly, he agrees with the majority in the
 Florida case that there is no Free Exercise violation here because 
Florida
 (i.e., the state courts, construing the legislature's intent as to
 severability) is not treating religious schools unfavorably vis-a-vis
 other private schools.  And that was the principal question that I was
 asking -- i.e., could the university in Widmar have opted to close all
 classrooms to student groups once it learned that religious groups would
 have to be included?  Tom says yes.  But the dissent in the Florida 
case
 says no! -- that if the closure was motivated by the objective of
 excluding religious groups, then the facially neutral closure itself
 violates the Free Exercise Clause.  I think that's probably wrong, and 
it
 appears Tom agrees.
  
 If possible, I'd like to hear from any listmembers who disagree with 
this
 conclusion, before the discussion veers away to the very interesting
 subsidiary question that Tom addresses.
  
 The next question -- the one Tom's e-mail principally addresses -- is 
this:
 If (i) the Free Exercise Clause would prohibit discrimination against
 religious schools (which is contrary to the Florida's court's holding, 
but
 assume arguendo that the dissent is correct to distinguish Davey), and 
(ii)
 the Florida Constitution prohibits use of vouchers in religious schools,
 could the Florida Legislature ignore the Florida Constitution and enact 
a
 plan that permits vouchers to be used at religious and nonreligious 
schools
 alike?  Tom is absolutely correct that nothing in the federal 
Constitution
 would prohibit the legislature from doing so.  In Tom's words, the 
state has
 the choice between all or nothing.  The problem, as I see it, is that 
the
 state has chosen -- the State Constitution appears to compel the answer 
of
 nothing.
  
 Tom suggests that the effect of the federal constitutional command is 
not
 only to require nondiscrimination, but also to, in effect, erase, or
 invalidate, the flawed state constitutional provision, or, in any 
event,
 to make it not binding on lower-level state decisionmakers.  That's a 
very
 interesting jurisprudential question, I think.  Of course, we all know 
that
 when a court declares a statute (or state constitutional provision)
 invalid, it does not mean that the provision magically disappears, or 
is
 thereby repealed.  What it means is that the courts will enjoin any
 application of the statute that violates the federal constitutional 
norm.
  
 If, therefore, the state constitution required that religious schools be
 singled out for disfavored treatment, as Tom suggests, then of course 
the
 lower-level state actors could never apply that provision in a manner
 consistent with a federal rule that such discrimination is 
unconstitutional
 -- because any such application would be enjoined.  The difficulty with
 Tom's analysis, as I see it, is that the state constitutional norm here 
does
 not require religious schools to be singled out -- it merely requires 
that
 they not receive aid.  The federal Constitution has not invalidated 
the
 refusal of Florida to give aid to religious schools -- Tom concedes that
 Florida need not do so as long as secular and religious schools alike.  
It
 has merely (that is to say, hypothetically, if the Florida court is 
wrong)
 prohibited discrimination.  Therefore there is no conflict between the 
two
 constitutions, and the lower-level state actors must honor both.
  
 I genuinely do not know whether this is correct -- but I think that it 
is a
 question of state, not federal, law.  This is essentially the conclusion
 that Van Alstyne reached in an analogous context in his Thirty Pieces 
of
 Silver article -- that if Congress offers the state funds only on a
 condition that the state do something that is independently barred by 
the
 state's own constitution, the state has no choice but to decline the 
federal
 funds.  On the other hand, Lead/Deadwood suggests otherwise, and would
 probably be support for Tom's theory.
  
  
  
   
 - Original Message - 
 From: Berg, Thomas C.  mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
 To: Law

FWD: Florida voucher decision / Alan's question

2004-11-13 Thread Alan Brownstein

Dear Alan -- I cannot post to the list.  Would you mind forwarding this 
response
(to you).  Hope you are well . . .

* * *

Dear Alan (and colleagues),

John Witte's Religion and the American Constitutional Experiment 
explores this
possibility, I think.  And, John Courtney Murray (S.J.) pressed a related
argument w/r/t what the McCollum and Everson Courts claimed were the 
Madisonian
roots (Memorial and Remonstrance, etc.) of the Establishment Clause in 
his
1949 essay, Law or Prepossessions?

Best wishes,

Rick


___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Florida Voucher Decision

2004-11-12 Thread Rick Garnett
Dear all,
Thanks very much to Michael for forwarding the Florida court's decision.  I 
am not surprised by the result, but I am surprised by (what I regard as) 
the court's failure meaningfully to confront the original social meaning 
and purpose of Florida's no-aid provision and other similar provisions.

For example:  In footnote 9, the Florida court states that [w]hether the 
Blaine-era amendments are based on religious bigotry is a disputed and 
controversial issue among historians and legal scholars and that [some] 
commentators argue . . .  that anti-Catholic bigotry did not play a 
significant role in the development of Blaine-era no-aid provisions in 
state constitutions.  (True enough).  For the latter proposition, though, 
the court cites only (1) a detailed article on the Indiana no-aid 
provision, which observed that, in 1850, Indiana had very few Catholics and 
concluded that the Indiana provision was neither nativist nor 
anti-Catholic; and (2) Chief Justice Rehnquist's observation in Davey that 
the provision at issue in that case had not been connected by Davey to the 
Blaine Amendment.  But does Indiana's situation in 1850 -- even assuming 
that the article's author is correct -- really support the statement that 
Florida's 1868 (and 1885) no-aid provision was not tainted by post-war 
nativism?   What about the Chief Justice's observations about what he 
regarded as the lack of a connection between one particular Washington 
provision and the Blaine Amendment movement generally?  (Now, I have not 
done the historical research on Florida's provision specifically; perhaps 
it really is the case that Florida's no-aid provision was anomalously free 
of nativist support.  But the Florida court's citations do not, in my view, 
make the case).

What's more -- Putting aside the fact that concern about the perceived 
anti-democratic effects and aims of 19th Century Catholicism need not be 
regarded as bigotry (even if, as I believe, this concern was, for the 
most part, misplaced); and putting aside also the question whether, under 
current doctrine, it matters today that the Florida no-aid provision 
reflected (among other things), a widespread desire to constrain the 
influence of Catholicism (in the same footnote, the court suggests that the 
1968 retention of the provision removes any possible taint); I am quite 
surprised by the court's casual confidence that anti-Catholicism did not 
play a role in the adoption of the no-aid provision.  There is, in my view, 
an innocents abroad quality to the discussion.  On page 15, for example, 
the court quotes Justice Brennan's (questionable) claim in Lemon that the 
no-aid provisions and the common-school movement reflected a desire for 
secular public schools, rather than private sectarian schools.  And, in 
footnote 7, the court notes President Grant's 1875 call for a no-aid 
amendment to the United States Constitution, without mentioning at all the 
overtly anti-Catholic (which does not, again, mean bigoted) nature of 
Grant's appeal (see, e.g., John T. McGreevy, Catholicism and American 
Freedom (2003)).

I know that Marc Stern, Steve Green, and others have written powerfully and 
well that the Blaine Amendments are more complicated than some of the 
amendments' critics (including, perhaps, me) have appreciated.  Still . . 
. I'd welcome others' reactions.

Best,
Rick Garnett
Notre Dame Law School
At 03:11 PM 11/12/2004, you wrote:
The First District Court of Appeal today again held Florida's voucher
system violated the no aid provision of Florida's constitution.  The 114
page opinion with dissents, is available on line at:
http://www.1dca.org/opinion/opinions2004/11-12-04/02-3160rh.pdf (en banc)
Michael R. Masinter Visiting Professor of Law
On Leave From   University of Miami Law School
Nova Southeastern University(305) 284-3870 (voice)
Shepard Broad Law Center(305) 284-6619 (fax)
[EMAIL PROTECTED]   Chair, ACLU of Florida Legal Panel

___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are 
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or 
wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the messages 

Re: Florida Voucher Decision

2004-11-12 Thread A.E. Brownstein
Rick's thoughtful post reminded me of an issue I had planned to raise on 
the list but never got around to. Having read only a few pieces by early 
writers, such as the Elisha Williams excerpt in the McConnell, Garvey, 
Berg, Religion and the Constitution casebook, I was struck by the 
anti-Catholic foundation underlying William's commentary. I began to wonder 
whether there is an anti-Catholic taint not only to no-aid provisions in 
state constitutions but to the entire American constitutional commitment to 
free exercise rights -- the theological justification for which resonates 
with Protestant beliefs of the period and, it may be argued, stands in 
contrast to a Catholic perspective of the time. (I recognize that 
proponents of religious liberty had reasons to fear oppression from a 
variety of sources -- and distinctions drawn between Protestant and 
Catholic thought at most could only be part of the story. My question is 
simply how much of a part of the story of our commitment to religious 
liberty is it, if any?)

Does anyone know if anyone has written anything on this issue?
Alan Brownstein
UC Davis

At 05:31 PM 11/12/2004 -0500, you wrote:
Dear all,
Thanks very much to Michael for forwarding the Florida court's 
decision.  I am not surprised by the result, but I am surprised by (what I 
regard as) the court's failure meaningfully to confront the original 
social meaning and purpose of Florida's no-aid provision and other 
similar provisions.

For example:  In footnote 9, the Florida court states that [w]hether the 
Blaine-era amendments are based on religious bigotry is a disputed and 
controversial issue among historians and legal scholars and that [some] 
commentators argue . . .  that anti-Catholic bigotry did not play a 
significant role in the development of Blaine-era no-aid provisions in 
state constitutions.  (True enough).  For the latter proposition, though, 
the court cites only (1) a detailed article on the Indiana no-aid 
provision, which observed that, in 1850, Indiana had very few Catholics 
and concluded that the Indiana provision was neither nativist nor 
anti-Catholic; and (2) Chief Justice Rehnquist's observation in Davey that 
the provision at issue in that case had not been connected by Davey to the 
Blaine Amendment.  But does Indiana's situation in 1850 -- even assuming 
that the article's author is correct -- really support the statement that 
Florida's 1868 (and 1885) no-aid provision was not tainted by post-war 
nativism?   What about the Chief Justice's observations about what he 
regarded as the lack of a connection between one particular Washington 
provision and the Blaine Amendment movement generally?  (Now, I have not 
done the historical research on Florida's provision specifically; perhaps 
it really is the case that Florida's no-aid provision was anomalously free 
of nativist support.  But the Florida court's citations do not, in my 
view, make the case).

What's more -- Putting aside the fact that concern about the perceived 
anti-democratic effects and aims of 19th Century Catholicism need not be 
regarded as bigotry (even if, as I believe, this concern was, for the 
most part, misplaced); and putting aside also the question whether, under 
current doctrine, it matters today that the Florida no-aid provision 
reflected (among other things), a widespread desire to constrain the 
influence of Catholicism (in the same footnote, the court suggests that 
the 1968 retention of the provision removes any possible taint); I am 
quite surprised by the court's casual confidence that anti-Catholicism did 
not play a role in the adoption of the no-aid provision.  There is, in my 
view, an innocents abroad quality to the discussion.  On page 15, for 
example, the court quotes Justice Brennan's (questionable) claim in Lemon 
that the no-aid provisions and the common-school movement reflected a 
desire for secular public schools, rather than private sectarian 
schools.  And, in footnote 7, the court notes President Grant's 1875 call 
for a no-aid amendment to the United States Constitution, without 
mentioning at all the overtly anti-Catholic (which does not, again, mean 
bigoted) nature of Grant's appeal (see, e.g., John T. McGreevy, 
Catholicism and American Freedom (2003)).

I know that Marc Stern, Steve Green, and others have written powerfully 
and well that the Blaine Amendments are more complicated than some of the 
amendments' critics (including, perhaps, me) have appreciated.  Still . . 
. I'd welcome others' reactions.

Best,
Rick Garnett
Notre Dame Law School
At 03:11 PM 11/12/2004, you wrote:
The First District Court of Appeal today again held Florida's voucher
system violated the no aid provision of Florida's constitution.  The 114
page opinion with dissents, is available on line at:
http://www.1dca.org/opinion/opinions2004/11-12-04/02-3160rh.pdf (en banc)
Michael R. Masinter Visiting Professor of Law
On Leave From