RE: Religious exemptions and preferences for the religious over the nonreligious

2010-03-02 Thread Douglas Laycock
Examples of Alan's first point are alternative service for conscientious 
objectors to military service, which appears in a Rhode Island statute of 1673 
and in the 20th-century draft laws, and in the less attractive form of money 
payments in many 18th and 19th century draft laws, and the statutory 
requirement that conscientious objectors to union membership contribute to 
charity an amount equal to union dues.

Quoting "Brownstein, Alan" :

> I would only add two caveats to Doug's point. First, in some cases 
> (although not this one), it may be possible for the religious liberty 
> claimant to give up what I call the surplus secular benefit he  
> receives when a religious liberty accommodation that coincides with 
> self interest is granted. In that case, the granting of an 
> accommodation may be permissible. Second, this general problem helps 
> to demonstrate why Justice Scalia's creation of a hybrid rights 
> analysis to distinguish Wisconsin v. Yoder in the Smith case was so 
> wrongheaded. One area where religious liberty accommodations are 
> particularly inappropriate is conduct that constitutes the exercise 
> of a fundamental right. Religious individuals cannot be provided 
> preferences with regard to their freedom of speech, right to vote, 
> right to marry, right to have children or other areas of protected 
> conduct.
>
> Alan Brownstein
> UC Davis School of Law
>
>
>
> From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
> [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas 
> Laycock
> Sent: Tuesday, March 02, 2010 1:30 PM
> To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics; Volokh, Eugene
> Cc: 'Law & Religion issues for Law Academics'
> Subject: Re: Religious exemptions and preferences for the religious 
> over the nonreligious
>
> I have always said that if your religious claim aligns too closely 
> with self interest, you will lose, and that is the right result even 
> if it is sometimes an unfortunate result.  My standard classroom 
> example has been conscientious objection to paying taxes, but this 
> may become the new standard example.
>
> The court may write the opinion in a variety of ways.  It find the 
> claim insincere, or it may find that the claim invites many similar 
> claims that will be insincere, or it may find a compelling interest 
> in not trying to adjudicate all thsoe claims, or it may say that 
> allowing such a claim discriminates against people of other faiths 
> and nonbeleivers who can't make the same claim, or it may even 
> recognize that allowing such a claim creates pressure to convert.  In 
> terms of substantive neutrality, the impact on secular self-interest 
> changes incentives for every married prisoner -- and in the tax 
> example, for substantially the whole adult population.  These 
> incentive effects may collectively be much greater than the burden on 
> religious practice of those who would genuinely qualify with a 
> sincere claim.
>
> Quoting "Volokh, Eugene" :
>
>>                In Henderson v. Hubbard, 2010 WL 599886 (E.D. Cal.
>> Feb. 18), a prison inmate claimed that the denial of conjugal visits
>> with his wife violated RLUIPA and the Free Exercise Clause because he
>> believes that "as a Muslim, he is required to engage in sexual
>> relations with his wife."  Assume that his belief is sincere; I
>> suppose it might well be; and let's even set aside whether the
>> exception was justified under strict scrutiny.  (The court didn't
>> reach that, because it rejected the claim on statute of limitations
>> grounds.)
>>
>>                Instead, assume that a prison decided to grant this
>> exemption from the generally applicable ban on conjugal visits, on
>> its own judgment or as a matter of state law.  Would such an
>> exemption limited to religious objectors be constitutionally
>> permissible?  Or would it be an undue preference for the religious
>> over the nonreligious, and on top of that one that pressures people
>> into claiming religious beliefs and participating in religious
>> practices in order to do that?  (I assume that the incentive to claim
>> religious beliefs posed in this case is much greater than the
>> incentive to sit through a graduation prayer present in Lee v.
>> Weisman.)
>>
>>                Eugene
>>
>
>
>
> Douglas Laycock
> Yale Kamisar Collegiate Professor of Law
> University of Michigan Law School
> 625 S. State St.
> Ann Arbor, MI  48109-1215
>   734-647-9713
>

  

Douglas Laycock
Yale Kamisar Collegiate Professor of Law
University of Michigan Law School
625 S. State St.
Ann Arbor, MI  48109-1215
  734-6

RE: Religious exemptions and preferences for the religious over the nonreligious

2010-03-02 Thread Brownstein, Alan
I would only add two caveats to Doug's point. First, in some cases (although 
not this one), it may be possible for the religious liberty claimant to give up 
what I call the surplus secular benefit he  receives when a religious liberty 
accommodation that coincides with self interest is granted. In that case, the 
granting of an accommodation may be permissible. Second, this general problem 
helps to demonstrate why Justice Scalia's creation of a hybrid rights analysis 
to distinguish Wisconsin v. Yoder in the Smith case was so wrongheaded. One 
area where religious liberty accommodations are particularly inappropriate is 
conduct that constitutes the exercise of a fundamental right. Religious 
individuals cannot be provided preferences with regard to their freedom of 
speech, right to vote, right to marry, right to have children or other areas of 
protected conduct.

Alan Brownstein
UC Davis School of Law



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Tuesday, March 02, 2010 1:30 PM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics; Volokh, Eugene
Cc: 'Law & Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: Re: Religious exemptions and preferences for the religious over the 
nonreligious

I have always said that if your religious claim aligns too closely with self 
interest, you will lose, and that is the right result even if it is sometimes 
an unfortunate result.  My standard classroom example has been conscientious 
objection to paying taxes, but this may become the new standard example.

The court may write the opinion in a variety of ways.  It find the claim 
insincere, or it may find that the claim invites many similar claims that will 
be insincere, or it may find a compelling interest in not trying to adjudicate 
all thsoe claims, or it may say that allowing such a claim discriminates 
against people of other faiths and nonbeleivers who can't make the same claim, 
or it may even recognize that allowing such a claim creates pressure to 
convert.  In terms of substantive neutrality, the impact on secular 
self-interest changes incentives for every married prisoner -- and in the tax 
example, for substantially the whole adult population.  These incentive effects 
may collectively be much greater than the burden on religious practice of those 
who would genuinely qualify with a sincere claim.

Quoting "Volokh, Eugene" :

>In Henderson v. Hubbard, 2010 WL 599886 (E.D. Cal.
> Feb. 18), a prison inmate claimed that the denial of conjugal visits
> with his wife violated RLUIPA and the Free Exercise Clause because he
> believes that "as a Muslim, he is required to engage in sexual
> relations with his wife."  Assume that his belief is sincere; I
> suppose it might well be; and let's even set aside whether the
> exception was justified under strict scrutiny.  (The court didn't
> reach that, because it rejected the claim on statute of limitations
> grounds.)
>
>Instead, assume that a prison decided to grant this
> exemption from the generally applicable ban on conjugal visits, on
> its own judgment or as a matter of state law.  Would such an
> exemption limited to religious objectors be constitutionally
> permissible?  Or would it be an undue preference for the religious
> over the nonreligious, and on top of that one that pressures people
> into claiming religious beliefs and participating in religious
> practices in order to do that?  (I assume that the incentive to claim
> religious beliefs posed in this case is much greater than the
> incentive to sit through a graduation prayer present in Lee v.
> Weisman.)
>
>Eugene
>



Douglas Laycock
Yale Kamisar Collegiate Professor of Law
University of Michigan Law School
625 S. State St.
Ann Arbor, MI  48109-1215
  734-647-9713
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Religious exemptions and preferences for the religious over the nonreligious

2010-03-02 Thread Douglas Laycock
I have always said that if your religious claim aligns too closely with self 
interest, you will lose, and that is the right result even if it is sometimes 
an unfortunate result.  My standard classroom example has been conscientious 
objection to paying taxes, but this may become the new standard example.

The court may write the opinion in a variety of ways.  It find the claim 
insincere, or it may find that the claim invites many similar claims that will 
be insincere, or it may find a compelling interest in not trying to adjudicate 
all thsoe claims, or it may say that allowing such a claim discriminates 
against people of other faiths and nonbeleivers who can't make the same claim, 
or it may even recognize that allowing such a claim creates pressure to 
convert.  In terms of substantive neutrality, the impact on secular 
self-interest changes incentives for every married prisoner -- and in the tax 
example, for substantially the whole adult population.  These incentive effects 
may collectively be much greater than the burden on religious practice of those 
who would genuinely qualify with a sincere claim.

Quoting "Volokh, Eugene" :

>                In Henderson v. Hubbard, 2010 WL 599886 (E.D. Cal. 
> Feb. 18), a prison inmate claimed that the denial of conjugal visits 
> with his wife violated RLUIPA and the Free Exercise Clause because he 
> believes that "as a Muslim, he is required to engage in sexual 
> relations with his wife."  Assume that his belief is sincere; I 
> suppose it might well be; and let's even set aside whether the 
> exception was justified under strict scrutiny.  (The court didn't 
> reach that, because it rejected the claim on statute of limitations 
> grounds.)
>
>                Instead, assume that a prison decided to grant this 
> exemption from the generally applicable ban on conjugal visits, on 
> its own judgment or as a matter of state law.  Would such an 
> exemption limited to religious objectors be constitutionally 
> permissible?  Or would it be an undue preference for the religious 
> over the nonreligious, and on top of that one that pressures people 
> into claiming religious beliefs and participating in religious 
> practices in order to do that?  (I assume that the incentive to claim 
> religious beliefs posed in this case is much greater than the 
> incentive to sit through a graduation prayer present in Lee v. 
> Weisman.)
>
>                Eugene
>

  

Douglas Laycock
Yale Kamisar Collegiate Professor of Law
University of Michigan Law School
625 S. State St.
Ann Arbor, MI  48109-1215
  734-647-9713___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.