RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

2013-12-19 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
I cannot help but wonder what Alan's view is of the recent Utah polygamy case.  
It does seem to me that the arguments he so eloquently makes below should apply 
(easiest case) to adult old-Mormons who continue to believe that their 
religion encourages (compels?) multiple marriages.  In this instance, at least, 
I suspect there's be relatively little incentive to engage in strategic 
misrepresentation, though the obvious problem is the creation of a new sect, 
perhaps in Colorado, that preaches the virtues both of smoking marijuana and 
multiple marriage (polyandrous and well as polygamous).  I personally have no 
problem with this, though, to put it mildly, I would be surprised if Windsor 
were interpreted to require recognition of such marriages even if, by 
stipulation, Colorado did.

sandy

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Thursday, December 19, 2013 12:19 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

Sorry. My mistake. My post was focusing on statutory accommodations because 
RFRA has been the focus of most of the recent discussion on the list. Eugene is 
quite right that the case for an analogy to family relationships is stronger 
for statutory accommodations.

But there is some basis for analogizing the constitutional protection and 
accommodation of religious liberty to the protection and accommodation of 
family relationships. I don't want to overstate the point here, but the Court 
does discuss freedom of intimate association in Roberts and suggests that such 
associations might be exempt from anti-discrimination laws. Such cases rarely 
come up because statutes do not attempt to subject intimate associations such 
as families to anti-discrimination laws. But I assume that a family could 
assert a family/intimate association exemption should it be subject to 
anti-discrimination laws in various social settings.

Moore v. City of East Cleveland also requires in a sense a family exemption 
from zoning laws.

One might also argue that the right to marry protects the ability to form a 
family and marry the person one loves, even though doing so imposes costs on 
third parties. Cases like Zablocki are not necessarily cost free. A divorced 
father owing child support who starts a new family may have less resources 
available to support his earlier family.

Finally, some, but not all, of the debate about same-sex marriages could be 
characterized as a debate about providing constitutional protection to gay men 
(or lesbians) who love each other and want the state to recognize and protect 
their mutual commitments and the responsibilities they accept that arise from 
those commitments. Many argue that constitutional law requires states to 
accommodate the love, commitment and loyalty of same-sex partners who seek to 
be married notwithstanding state law that only permits marriages between one 
man and one woman. I must admit that I have never understood the argument that 
such marriages impose costs on third parties or the general public. But 
clearly, many people believe that such costs exist. Would proof of some such 
costs, however modest they might be, justify denying same-sex couples the right 
to marry? Or would we insist that it should require a showing of very, very, 
high costs before we would allow a state to refuse to acknowledge!
  and accommodate the right of two adults who love each other and are committed 
to caring for each other to marry.

Alan

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Volokh, Eugene [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Wednesday, December 18, 2013 4:17 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

I appreciate Alan's point, but I wonder how far it goes.

First, I might not have been clear enough on this in my post, 
but I was speaking of what should be a matter of constitutional entitlement, or 
entitlement under a generally applicable exemption scheme.  And we generally do 
not provide any constitutional exemption for love- and loyalty-based interests. 
 Loyalty to a friend, a child, a parent, or a spouse won't give you a 
constitutionally mandated exemption from, say, a duty to testify.  (The spousal 
testimonial privileges, I think, is a matter of common law and statute, not a 
constitutional mandate.)  If you quit a job because of a desire to spend more 
time with your children, your spouse, or your aging parents, you will not get a 
constitutional entitlement to unemployment compensation.

Second, even if we focus on exemptions created as a matter of 
legislative discretion (or common law), there are likewise very few in which 
familial love and loyalty exempt one from what would otherwise be a generally

RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

2013-12-19 Thread Alan Brownstein
There are arguments that the costs of accommodating polygamy are unacceptably 
high. I leave it to others to evaluate those arguments. But, from at least one 
perspective, concerns about polygamy do support an analogy between recognizing 
and accommodating the love and loyalty of family members (including same-sex 
marital partners) and recognizing and accommodating the needs of devout 
individuals who are loyal to their religious commitments.  I wrote some time 
ago that, The fear of having to recognize and protect polygamy has been the 
pit at the bottom of the slippery slope arguments that have been employed to 
deny the rights of both gays and lesbians and religious minorities.

Alan

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Levinson, Sanford V
Sent: Thursday, December 19, 2013 7:47 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

I cannot help but wonder what Alan's view is of the recent Utah polygamy case.  
It does seem to me that the arguments he so eloquently makes below should apply 
(easiest case) to adult old-Mormons who continue to believe that their 
religion encourages (compels?) multiple marriages.  In this instance, at least, 
I suspect there's be relatively little incentive to engage in strategic 
misrepresentation, though the obvious problem is the creation of a new sect, 
perhaps in Colorado, that preaches the virtues both of smoking marijuana and 
multiple marriage (polyandrous and well as polygamous).  I personally have no 
problem with this, though, to put it mildly, I would be surprised if Windsor 
were interpreted to require recognition of such marriages even if, by 
stipulation, Colorado did.

sandy

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Thursday, December 19, 2013 12:19 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

Sorry. My mistake. My post was focusing on statutory accommodations because 
RFRA has been the focus of most of the recent discussion on the list. Eugene is 
quite right that the case for an analogy to family relationships is stronger 
for statutory accommodations.

But there is some basis for analogizing the constitutional protection and 
accommodation of religious liberty to the protection and accommodation of 
family relationships. I don't want to overstate the point here, but the Court 
does discuss freedom of intimate association in Roberts and suggests that such 
associations might be exempt from anti-discrimination laws. Such cases rarely 
come up because statutes do not attempt to subject intimate associations such 
as families to anti-discrimination laws. But I assume that a family could 
assert a family/intimate association exemption should it be subject to 
anti-discrimination laws in various social settings.

Moore v. City of East Cleveland also requires in a sense a family exemption 
from zoning laws.

One might also argue that the right to marry protects the ability to form a 
family and marry the person one loves, even though doing so imposes costs on 
third parties. Cases like Zablocki are not necessarily cost free. A divorced 
father owing child support who starts a new family may have less resources 
available to support his earlier family.

Finally, some, but not all, of the debate about same-sex marriages could be 
characterized as a debate about providing constitutional protection to gay men 
(or lesbians) who love each other and want the state to recognize and protect 
their mutual commitments and the responsibilities they accept that arise from 
those commitments. Many argue that constitutional law requires states to 
accommodate the love, commitment and loyalty of same-sex partners who seek to 
be married notwithstanding state law that only permits marriages between one 
man and one woman. I must admit that I have never understood the argument that 
such marriages impose costs on third parties or the general public. But 
clearly, many people believe that such costs exist. Would proof of some such 
costs, however modest they might be, justify denying same-sex couples the right 
to marry? Or would we insist that it should require a showing of very, very, 
high costs before we would allow a state to refuse to acknowledge!
  and accommodate the right of two adults who love each other and are committed 
to caring for each other to marry.

Alan

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives

RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

2013-12-19 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I appreciate Alan's point about Moore, which is indeed an exemption 
from a generally applicable law for family relationships.  But note how rare 
such an exemption is, and how minimal the costs are that it imposes on others.  
Neither neighbors nor taxpayers, I suspect, suffer appreciably from grandkids' 
being able to live with their grandmother.  Whatever social benefits zoning law 
provides, such a narrow exemption to the law does not materially undermine 
them.  Moore is thus an example of the low-cost accommodation, and to the 
extent that religious exemption claims can be analogized to it, Moore would 
only offer a precedent for similarly low-cost accommodations.

The use of freedom of intimate association to bar the application of 
certain antidiscrimination laws is also interesting, but it's not really about 
the love and loyalty pointed to in Alan's earlier post, I think.  The clearest 
example of such an application of intimate association, for instance, comes in 
the Ninth Circuit's recent Roommates.com decision, in which the Circuit 
concluded that people likely have a constitutional right to discriminate in 
choice of roommates.  Whatever is going on with that right, I don't think the 
point is protection of love and loyalty.  (Note also that the exemption from 
antidiscrimination law would again be cognate in the Religion Clauses context 
to a limited right to exemptions -- see Hosanna-Tabor -- and not a general 
Sherbert/Yoder exemption regime.)

The right to marry is complicated by the fact that so many of the 
debates about the right are about equality rules, not substantive rights 
claims.  (Indeed, most cases recognizing same-sex marriages have focused on 
equal treatment claims, not on a substantive right to marry.)  It is further 
complicated by the fact that, with the repeal of fornication bans, the right to 
marry doesn't function as a negative liberty from government interference, and 
more as a positive claim to government recognition.  But in any event, the 
right to marry (as a substantive right rather than an equality right) offers a 
very narrow range of protection from government conduct, and again in a context 
that is fairly low-cost for others.  (A divorced father owing child support, 
after all, may well start a new family even without getting married, and very 
many fathers do; it's not the right to marry that's creating that much of a 
cost.)  I don't see that a right to marry offers much analogy to an asse!
 rted constitutional right to inflict significant costs on others (or on 
society) simply because one believes that God wants one to do something that 
the law forbids.

Eugene

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Wednesday, December 18, 2013 9:19 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

Sorry. My mistake. My post was focusing on statutory accommodations because 
RFRA has been the focus of most of the recent discussion on the list. Eugene is 
quite right that the case for an analogy to family relationships is stronger 
for statutory accommodations.

But there is some basis for analogizing the constitutional protection and 
accommodation of religious liberty to the protection and accommodation of 
family relationships. I don't want to overstate the point here, but the Court 
does discuss freedom of intimate association in Roberts and suggests that such 
associations might be exempt from anti-discrimination laws. Such cases rarely 
come up because statutes do not attempt to subject intimate associations such 
as families to anti-discrimination laws. But I assume that a family could 
assert a family/intimate association exemption should it be subject to 
anti-discrimination laws in various social settings.

Moore v. City of East Cleveland also requires in a sense a family exemption 
from zoning laws.

One might also argue that the right to marry protects the ability to form a 
family and marry the person one loves, even though doing so imposes costs on 
third parties. Cases like Zablocki are not necessarily cost free. A divorced 
father owing child support who starts a new family may have less resources 
available to support his earlier family.

Finally, some, but not all, of the debate about same-sex marriages could be 
characterized as a debate about providing constitutional protection to gay men 
(or lesbians) who love each other and want the state to recognize and protect 
their mutual commitments and the responsibilities they accept that arise from 
those commitments. Many argue that constitutional law requires states to 
accommodate the love, commitment and loyalty of same-sex partners who seek to 
be married notwithstanding state law that only permits marriages between one 
man and one woman. I must admit that I have never understood the argument

RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

2013-12-18 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
This is very helpful.  For Rick's argument, I still think the central question 
is why we would accommodate, even if the costs are relatively low, someone with 
religious objections, say, to working on an assembly line producing munitions, 
but not a secularist with a very tender conscience.  (As always, we return to 
Seeger and Welch, but are those cases really limited to the particularity of 
conscientious objection against service in the military.

Now one answer is that what's crucial about religious obligations, unlike 
merely conscientious ones, is that one is in fear of divine retribution for 
disobedience.  I.e., God doesn't simply say it would be nice if you'd honor 
your parents (you never call, you never write), but, instead if you don't 
call at least once a week, I will make things very difficult for you in the 
afterlife (and don't even ask about the consequences of adultery or murder).  
As I've written in other contexts, I do treat this as a troublesome conflict 
of law' (and not simply or conflicting moral duties), and it is understandable 
why anyone who takes Divine Sovereignty really seriously-and who believes that 
the Divine Sovereign has a system of rewards and punishments to back up mere 
moral injunctions-may believe that the state must always take second place in 
any such conflicts.

But, as Eugene well argues, it is not sensible to say that the state, even if 
understanding (and under a duty to engage in reasonable accommodation) must 
also suspend enforcement of its own laws whenever someone utters the magic 
words God is ordering me to do it, and I will pay a cost in the afterlife-or, 
depending on one's theology, even on earth-if I disobey.'  We're always going 
to balance.

Incidentally, if Hobby Lobby should win its ,case, will this not mean that 
Congress should know that it if it wants to be sure of achieving its purposes, 
it must tax and spend.'  But what if Hobby Lobby says that my God tells me 
that I ought to render unto Caesar if and only if Caesar will not be spending 
any of the revenues on patent violations of divine commands'?  I confess I've 
always found peculiar Randy Barnett's concession that Obamacare would have been 
perfectly constitutional, albeit unwise, a simple extension of Medicare, but 
that what doomed it was its reliance on various choice mechanisms, including 
the fabled  mandate to purchase insurance in the first place.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Wednesday, December 18, 2013 2:25 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics (religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu)
Subject: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

Rick Garnett's and (less directly) Michael Worley's posts 
highlight, I think, the fact that there are two kinds of religious exemption 
arguments that are often heard.

The first is Rick's argument, at least in this instance, which 
focuses on what might see as low-cost accommodations.  If there is a way of 
accommodating religious objectors that imposes very low costs on others, or on 
the government as a whole (which means others, albeit indirectly), why not do 
that?  Religious headgear in courtrooms where the normal rule is no hats is a 
classic example.

The second is an argument that exemptions should be given even 
when they are not low-cost -- when they do impose serious costs on third 
parties or the government, or at least can be credibly said to do so.  That's 
the implication of strict scrutiny.  And it's also the implication of most 
analogies to non-equality rights (though perhaps the time-place-and-manner 
analogy might be something of an exception, partly because it uses a test 
that's well below strict scrutiny).  After all, free speech is often protected 
even when it imposes serious costs on others (e.g., Hustler, Snyder, NAACP v. 
Claiborne Hardware, Florida Star v. BJF, New York Times v. Sullivan).  The 
Compulsory Process Clause is all about imposing serious costs on others.  Many 
of the criminal procedure amendments, such as the Fourth Amendment and the 
privilege against self-incrimination, doubtless impose serious costs on others, 
though less directly.  The same is true of most other non-equality 
constitutional rules.

Now it seems to me -- though of course others disagree -- that 
the normative case for a right to impose costs on others through conduct simply 
because you think God requires that conduct is not an appealing case.  Your God 
is your God, not mine; why should I lose some of my legal rights, or some of 
the benefits that various laws seek to confer on me, just because you want to 
do what your God tells you to do?

And indeed, as I've mentioned before, I don't think that we would accept 
religious exemption claims in some of the cases where we accept free speech 
claims.  The Free Speech Clause immunizes inflicting emotional distress 

RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

2013-12-18 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I would think that, if Hobby Lobby wins the case, this will 
just mean that future Congresses who are worried about such things should add a 
RFRA will not apply to this statute provision to statutes when they don't 
want any religious exemptions from those statutes.  That's one advantage of the 
RFRA model over the Free Exercise Clause model -- if the legislature disagrees 
with the courts' view of what is the least restrictive means of serving a 
compelling government interest, or expects to disagree with it, it can override 
that view (assuming, of course, that there are enough votes for that in the 
legislature).

Eugene


Sandy Levinson writes:

Incidentally, if Hobby Lobby should win its ,case, will this not mean that 
Congress should know that it if it wants to be sure of achieving its purposes, 
it must tax and spend.'  But what if Hobby Lobby says that my God tells me 
that I ought to render unto Caesar if and only if Caesar will not be spending 
any of the revenues on patent violations of divine commands'?  I confess I've 
always found peculiar Randy Barnett's concession that Obamacare would have been 
perfectly constitutional, albeit unwise, a simple extension of Medicare, but 
that what doomed it was its reliance on various choice mechanisms, including 
the fabled  mandate to purchase insurance in the first place.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

2013-12-18 Thread Alan Brownstein
  Eugene writes,

Now it seems to me -- though of course others disagree -- that the normative 
case for a right to impose costs on others through conduct simply because you 
think God requires that conduct is not an appealing case.  Your God is your 
God, not mine; why should I lose some of my legal rights, or some of the 
benefits that various laws seek to confer on me, just because you want to do 
what your God tells you to do?

I think one answer to Eugene's question is that we value interests such as  
love and loyalty - particularly when they arise in certain kinds of 
relationships.  Suppose the question is why should we respect the duties and 
obligations that arise out of family relationships. After all, I could say, it 
is Eugene's relationship to his wife, and children and family, not mine, that 
might require him to do things that impose costs on others. Of course, there 
are limits as to the scope of those costs we are willing to incur to 
accommodate family relationships, and a strict scrutiny regime may be the wrong 
way to evaluate and balance such costs. But that is different than saying we 
should never accommodate the duties and obligations arising out of family 
relationships if doing so imposes costs on others.

I think it is reasonable to question which relationships in our society should 
receive accommodations and protection. Certainly, religion and family life may 
not exhaust the range of accommodated relationships. But that is a different 
question than asking whether these relationships warrant accommodation in the 
first place.

Alan


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

2013-12-18 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I appreciate Alan's point, but I wonder how far it goes.

First, I might not have been clear enough on this in my post, 
but I was speaking of what should be a matter of constitutional entitlement, or 
entitlement under a generally applicable exemption scheme.  And we generally do 
not provide any constitutional exemption for love- and loyalty-based interests. 
 Loyalty to a friend, a child, a parent, or a spouse won't give you a 
constitutionally mandated exemption from, say, a duty to testify.  (The spousal 
testimonial privileges, I think, is a matter of common law and statute, not a 
constitutional mandate.)  If you quit a job because of a desire to spend more 
time with your children, your spouse, or your aging parents, you will not get a 
constitutional entitlement to unemployment compensation.

Second, even if we focus on exemptions created as a matter of 
legislative discretion (or common law), there are likewise very few in which 
familial love and loyalty exempt one from what would otherwise be a generally 
applicable rule.  The spousal testimonial privileges are one example, but note 
that even they don't extend to children, parents, or other family members.  
Likewise, the few statutes that impose a general duty to report crimes 
sometimes exempt people from having to report on close relatives.  The Family 
Medical Leave Act might be seen as a statute protecting familial love and 
loyalty against generally applicable employer policies, though there the matter 
might not be so much love and loyalty as providing social goods (care for sick 
family members).  Perhaps the historical exemptions from the draft for fathers 
might qualify, though that too might be best seen as a means of providing 
social goods (financial support and parental guidance for children) rather than 
just avoiding intrusion on family relationships.

So the analogy to family relationships, I think, cuts against 
any constitutional exemption regime (as in Sherbert/Yoder), though it can 
indeed support some statute-by-statute exemptions, including potentially 
high-cost exemptions.  (As I mentioned, low-cost exemptions are subject to 
different arguments.)

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Wednesday, December 18, 2013 2:18 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

  Eugene writes,

Now it seems to me -- though of course others disagree -- that the normative 
case for a right to impose costs on others through conduct simply because you 
think God requires that conduct is not an appealing case.  Your God is your 
God, not mine; why should I lose some of my legal rights, or some of the 
benefits that various laws seek to confer on me, just because you want to do 
what your God tells you to do?

I think one answer to Eugene's question is that we value interests such as  
love and loyalty - particularly when they arise in certain kinds of 
relationships.  Suppose the question is why should we respect the duties and 
obligations that arise out of family relationships. After all, I could say, it 
is Eugene's relationship to his wife, and children and family, not mine, that 
might require him to do things that impose costs on others. Of course, there 
are limits as to the scope of those costs we are willing to incur to 
accommodate family relationships, and a strict scrutiny regime may be the wrong 
way to evaluate and balance such costs. But that is different than saying we 
should never accommodate the duties and obligations arising out of family 
relationships if doing so imposes costs on others.

I think it is reasonable to question which relationships in our society should 
receive accommodations and protection. Certainly, religion and family life may 
not exhaust the range of accommodated relationships. But that is a different 
question than asking whether these relationships warrant accommodation in the 
first place.

Alan


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

2013-12-18 Thread Alan Brownstein
Sorry. My mistake. My post was focusing on statutory accommodations because 
RFRA has been the focus of most of the recent discussion on the list. Eugene is 
quite right that the case for an analogy to family relationships is stronger 
for statutory accommodations.

But there is some basis for analogizing the constitutional protection and 
accommodation of religious liberty to the protection and accommodation of 
family relationships. I don't want to overstate the point here, but the Court 
does discuss freedom of intimate association in Roberts and suggests that such 
associations might be exempt from anti-discrimination laws. Such cases rarely 
come up because statutes do not attempt to subject intimate associations such 
as families to anti-discrimination laws. But I assume that a family could 
assert a family/intimate association exemption should it be subject to 
anti-discrimination laws in various social settings.

Moore v. City of East Cleveland also requires in a sense a family exemption 
from zoning laws.

One might also argue that the right to marry protects the ability to form a 
family and marry the person one loves, even though doing so imposes costs on 
third parties. Cases like Zablocki are not necessarily cost free. A divorced 
father owing child support who starts a new family may have less resources 
available to support his earlier family.

Finally, some, but not all, of the debate about same-sex marriages could be 
characterized as a debate about providing constitutional protection to gay men 
(or lesbians) who love each other and want the state to recognize and protect 
their mutual commitments and the responsibilities they accept that arise from 
those commitments. Many argue that constitutional law requires states to 
accommodate the love, commitment and loyalty of same-sex partners who seek to 
be married notwithstanding state law that only permits marriages between one 
man and one woman. I must admit that I have never understood the argument that 
such marriages impose costs on third parties or the general public. But 
clearly, many people believe that such costs exist. Would proof of some such 
costs, however modest they might be, justify denying same-sex couples the right 
to marry? Or would we insist that it should require a showing of very, very, 
high costs before we would allow a state to refuse to acknowledge and 
accommodate the right of two adults who love each other and are committed to 
caring for each other to marry.

Alan

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Volokh, Eugene [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Wednesday, December 18, 2013 4:17 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Two kinds of religious exemption arguments

I appreciate Alan’s point, but I wonder how far it goes.

First, I might not have been clear enough on this in my post, 
but I was speaking of what should be a matter of constitutional entitlement, or 
entitlement under a generally applicable exemption scheme.  And we generally do 
not provide any constitutional exemption for love- and loyalty-based interests. 
 Loyalty to a friend, a child, a parent, or a spouse won’t give you a 
constitutionally mandated exemption from, say, a duty to testify.  (The spousal 
testimonial privileges, I think, is a matter of common law and statute, not a 
constitutional mandate.)  If you quit a job because of a desire to spend more 
time with your children, your spouse, or your aging parents, you will not get a 
constitutional entitlement to unemployment compensation.

Second, even if we focus on exemptions created as a matter of 
legislative discretion (or common law), there are likewise very few in which 
familial love and loyalty exempt one from what would otherwise be a generally 
applicable rule.  The spousal testimonial privileges are one example, but note 
that even they don’t extend to children, parents, or other family members.  
Likewise, the few statutes that impose a general duty to report crimes 
sometimes exempt people from having to report on close relatives.  The Family 
Medical Leave Act might be seen as a statute protecting familial love and 
loyalty against generally applicable employer policies, though there the matter 
might not be so much love and loyalty as providing social goods (care for sick 
family members).  Perhaps the historical exemptions from the draft for fathers 
might qualify, though that too might be best seen as a means of providing 
social goods (financial support and parental guidance for children) rather than 
just avoiding intrusion on family relationships.

So the analogy to family relationships, I think, cuts against 
any constitutional exemption regime (as in Sherbert/Yoder), though it can 
indeed support some statute-by-statute exemptions, including potentially 
high-cost exemptions.  (As I mentioned