Re: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA

2012-06-18 Thread Jesse Merriam
On Alan's second point, concerning the confusion between holding that
a statutory free-exercise accommodation is required because the state
cannot satisfy strict scrutiny and holding that a statutory
free-exercise accommodation is prohibited because it violates the
Establishment Clause, there is an interesting comparison that we can
draw here to affirmative action and the Equal Protection Clause.

If you recall, in the Court's affirmative-action cases, the
conservative Justices often mentioned how there would be no violation
of the EPC if the affirmative action functioned as a remedy for past
state-sanctioned racial discrimination.  But the Justices often
oscillated between referring to affirmative action in such a case as
being permissible because it would satisfy strict scrutiny or
permissible because it would be constitutionally required by the Equal
Protection Clause (based on the Swann and Green rulings).

We see a similar form of reasoning with free-exercise accommodations,
when they are granted (as in Amos) or denied (as in Davey).  Indeed,
we see such a confusion in Justice Scalia's Davey dissent, where he
referred to how Washington would be allowed to deny Joshua Davey the
scholarship on the basis of religion only if granting the scholarship
would have violated the Establishment Clause, because in such an
instance the state would have a compelling interest in the denial.

But I don't think it makes sense to use the strict-scrutiny framework
in these types of cases dealing with conflicting constitutional
obligations, because applying that framework involves saying there is
a compelling interest in enforcing one constitutional right over
another.  How could the Establishment Clause generate the state's
compelling interest to deny Davey the scholarship, if that denial
would clearly run afoul of the Smith test? If the government has a
compelling interest in complying with the Establishment Clause, it
must also have such an interest in complying with the Free Exercise
Clause.  Strict scrutiny really has no place in the analysis of
conflicting constitutional duties.


-Jesse
On Sun, Jun 17, 2012 at 5:18 PM, Alan Brownstein
 wrote:
> Let me continue Mark and Eugene and Chris' thoughtful line of thinking here.
>
>
>
> First, it may, indeed, be appropriate to use some form of intermediate level
> of scrutiny in some free exercise cases. It may also be appropriate to use a
> higher or lower standard of review in other cases. It has never been clear
> to me why it so often seems to be assumed that all free eercise cases must
> be reviewed under the same standard of review. Certainly, in the free speech
> area we recognize that a more nuanced doctrine is necessary that applies
> different standards of review in different circumstances. Some variation in
> standards of review may be necessary and appropriate in the free exercise
> area as well.
>
>
>
> Second, if we are talking about statutory accommodations (such as RFRA), it
> seems to me that there is a confusing dissonance between the explicitly
> rigorous strict scrutiny standard that many statutes employ and the extent
> to which an accommodation will be permitted under the Establishment Clause.
> Even if a court interprets a state RFRA to require an accommodation because
> the state's interest cannot satisfy strict scrutiny review, this application
> of RFRA may violate the Establishment Clause if it goes too far in
> privileging religion and imposing unacceptable costs on non-beneficiaries.
> That's certainly how I understand the Cutter opinion and its frequent
> references to accommodations not imposing unacceptable burdens on third
> parties or public institutions. If the Establishment Clause limit on
> accommodation costs is less demanding than a compelling state interest
> requirement (e.g., courts might not consider avoiding those costs to
> constitute a compelling state interest for statutory purposes), the
> constitutional standard will cap the accommodation whatever the statute
> says.
>
>
>
> Alan Brownstein
>
> 
> From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
> [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Christopher Lund
> [l...@wayne.edu]
> Sent: Sunday, June 17, 2012 1:36 PM
>
> To: 'Law & Religion issues for Law Academics'
> Subject: RE: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA
>
> I wanted to send out a thought relating to earlier posts by Mark Graber and
> Eugene Volokh.  They suggest an intermediate standard of review, somewhere
> between strict scrutiny and Smith.  I think they are right on the key
> point.  The usual  “strict scrutiny” standard – i.e., strict in theory,
> fatal in fact – won’t work for free exercise.   It’s too harsh a standard.
> I think defenders of regulatory exceptions g

RE: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA

2012-06-17 Thread Christopher Lund
If I understand it right, I think Eric's second paragraph is a better way
of putting it than I did.  I suggested that the compelling-interest test
is lighter in the Free Exercise context than in the Free Speech context.
Eric is saying, "No, it's the same test--there are just more compelling
governmental interests in the Free Exercise cases, because a person's
exercise of religion is more likely to impermissibly affect third parties
than a person's mere speech."  That's better, significantly better, than
what I said.  But vis-à-vis my conversation with Eugene, it's making the
same point: There is no problem if the compelling-interest test is "strict
in theory, fatal in fact" for Free Speech cases of content- and
viewpoint-discrimination, but not "strict in theory, fatal in fact" in
Free Exercise cases.  There's no problematic inconsistency.  And I've seen
no evidence of actual confusion in the cases.  (Though if I'm wrong, again
I'd like to know.)

On the other things too, I agree with Eric.  I agree that a fundamental
problem with Smith is that uniform laws backed by relatively weak
government interests get absolutely no scrutiny.  I don't even think it's
rational basis--I think Smith means no review at all.  In class I teach a
case, Filinovich v. Claar, 2006 WL 1994580 (N.D. Ill.), about a Jehovah's
Witness selected to be Director of Finance for a small town.  Four times a
year, she's supposed to go to the town's budget meetings, held on Saturday
mornings for a couple of hours.  She says she can't do that, for religious
reasons--she's a Sabbatarian.  She points out all these ways in which she
could easily be accommodated.  The district judge cuts her off at the
pleadings stage, explaining that she has gotten Employment Division v.
Smith all wrong: "For the employment requirement to be neutral and
generally applicable, Defendants need not make, or even try to make, a
reasonable accommodation for Plaintiff‘s religious practice."  Id. at *5.
They don't even need to try.  In the vast run of these cases, Smith means
no protection against governmental interference, no protection against
governmental neglect or indifference, and limited protection against
governmental bigotry because it is so difficult to prove.

Eric is also right that the compelling-interest test is noticeably
different in O Centro than it was in the Sherbert/Yoder days.  Justice
O'Connor is the middle justice in Smith, where she concurs.  She says that
there's a compelling interest, because peyote is a dangerous drug and any
exception at all will threaten the regulatory scheme.  But that logic is
rejected in O Centro.  It isn't just rejected; it's mocked, and by a
unanimous Court (as Eric quoted below).  That's a huge difference.  Again,
a variety of styles of "compelling-interest test" analysis both within
Free Exercise and outside of it.

The point of my initial post was this.  If you don't like the results that
courts are reaching under the compelling-interest test, then it makes
sense that you would want to do away with it.  But some people seem to
really like the results that RFRA and state RFRAs are reaching, but object
to the linguistics of the test.  That's what I'm not understanding.

Best,
Chris

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Eric Rassbach
Sent: Sunday, June 17, 2012 6:02 PM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA


Chris --

I don't think you should read as much as you do into "sensible balances"
in O Centro, since it is after all a quote from the statute. In fact, the
way I read it, the Court quotes the statute to affirm what Congress did,
namely define the full-throated compelling interest test as a method of
sensible balancing, i.e. the test works. Recall that the DEA's approach in
O Centro was to complain that applying RFRA to the Controlled Substances
Act would upset their supposedly carefully calibrated closed and
comprehensive system of drug regulation, make sure the Court was aware
that "mind-altering" hallucinogenic tea is really weird and scary and will
hurt babies in utero, and hope that the Court would give them a free pass
for security/law enforcement reasons. The Court responds to this approach
by defining the compelling interest test in its full vigor as a way of
sensible balancing while (gently) mocking the DEA's complaints as "the
classic rejoinder of bureaucrats throughout history." To my mind that is a
pretty strong rejection of the idea that there is something wrong with
applying the compelling interest test with full force to religious
exercise claims. The Court was expressly rejecting DEA's argument that the
compelling inte

RE: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA

2012-06-17 Thread Eric Rassbach

Chris --

I don't think you should read as much as you do into "sensible balances" in O 
Centro, since it is after all a quote from the statute. In fact, the way I read 
it, the Court quotes the statute to affirm what Congress did, namely define the 
full-throated compelling interest test as a method of sensible balancing, i.e. 
the test works. Recall that the DEA's approach in O Centro was to complain that 
applying RFRA to the Controlled Substances Act would upset their supposedly 
carefully calibrated closed and comprehensive system of drug regulation, make 
sure the Court was aware that "mind-altering" hallucinogenic tea is really 
weird and scary and will hurt babies in utero, and hope that the Court would 
give them a free pass for security/law enforcement reasons. The Court responds 
to this approach by defining the compelling interest test in its full vigor as 
a way of sensible balancing while (gently) mocking the DEA's complaints as "the 
classic rejoinder of bureaucrats throughout history." To my mind that is a 
pretty strong rejection of the idea that there is something wrong with applying 
the compelling interest test with full force to religious exercise claims. The 
Court was expressly rejecting DEA's argument that the compelling interest test 
should be kept out of the drug regulation system. So I don't see how you get 
from there to the idea that the Court was saying that the compelling interest 
test should be softer with respect to a religious exercise claim than it is 
elsewhere. How else can you explain the Court's reliance on Ashcroft v. ACLU?

On the broader notion that we need a "soft" or "weak" version of the compelling 
interest test for religious exercise claims: Why? The fact that lower federal 
courts or state courts have been reluctant to provide certain kinds of remedies 
(partly because they are exercising a form of docket control) doesn't seem like 
a strong argument for shaving down federal civil rights laws like RLUIPA. That 
is especially so since the compelling interest test is naturally more 
government-friendly when it comes to religious conduct cases: Religious conduct 
claims will rightfully trigger strict scrutiny much more often than speech 
claims because the effect on third parties in speech cases--hearing something 
they disagree with--is much less than conduct that affects third parties 
directly. Put another way, there is no speech analogue to the CGI invoked by 
the government in a child-sacrifice-to-Moloch free exercise case; even stopping 
someone from shouting fire in crowded theater is not as strong a CGI. So courts 
will naturally find more CGIs to defeat religious conduct claims than they will 
find to defeat speech claims. (This is a point that Doug Laycock has made 
before.) That means that the compelling interest test is working, not that 
there is a problem with it.

Moreover, there is a real problem with the underlying analytical approach here 
that unjustly puts the burden on the religious entity to justify the exception. 
 All of the arguments I have seen so far seem to take for granted that there's 
some problem with making exceptions to the rules our government agencies come 
up with. Do we really think the DEA is that smart or well-meaning? Given that 
everyone concedes that a government made up of human beings doesn't and can't 
possibly get everything right, why is the baseline presumption when it comes to 
religious exercise claims that government got the rules right in the first 
place? The presumption should instead be that government actually goofs up with 
great frequency and we should be on the lookout for mistakes. That means that 
government rules should be viewed with a jaundiced eye, and when it comes to 
core constitutional rights like religious liberty or speech we need strong 
safeguards to account for the certainty of government mistakes/overreaching.  
So if anything I'd argue that the main problem with both federal RFRA and state 
RFRAs right now is if anything lower court incomprehension, not a need for 
squishier standards that can easily be overcome by inevitable government 
invocations of "security."

Eric


___
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
On Behalf Of Christopher Lund [l...@wayne.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 17, 2012 4:36 PM
To: 'Law & Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA

I wanted to send out a thought relating to earlier posts by Mark Graber and 
Eugene Volokh.  They suggest an intermediate standard of review, somewhere 
between strict scrutiny and Smith.  I think they are right on the key point.  
The usual  “strict scrutiny” standard – i.e., strict in theory, fatal in fact – 
won’t work for free exercise.   It’s too harsh a standard.  I think de

Re: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA

2012-06-17 Thread Douglas Laycock
Alan is too modest for shameless plugs, but he has written very thoughtfully 
about the need for more fine-grained analysis of free exercise questions, with 
multiple tests depending on context, in an article in 2006 or so. I think it's 
called Taking Free Exercise Seriously.

On Sun, 17 Jun 2012 21:18:31 +
 Alan Brownstein  wrote:
>Let me continue Mark and Eugene and Chris' thoughtful line of thinking here.
>
>
>

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA

2012-06-17 Thread Alan Brownstein
Let me continue Mark and Eugene and Chris' thoughtful line of thinking here.



First, it may, indeed, be appropriate to use some form of intermediate level of 
scrutiny in some free exercise cases. It may also be appropriate to use a 
higher or lower standard of review in other cases. It has never been clear to 
me why it so often seems to be assumed that all free eercise cases must be 
reviewed under the same standard of review. Certainly, in the free speech area 
we recognize that a more nuanced doctrine is necessary that applies different 
standards of review in different circumstances. Some variation in standards of 
review may be necessary and appropriate in the free exercise area as well.



Second, if we are talking about statutory accommodations (such as RFRA), it 
seems to me that there is a confusing dissonance between the explicitly 
rigorous strict scrutiny standard that many statutes employ and the extent to 
which an accommodation will be permitted under the Establishment Clause. Even 
if a court interprets a state RFRA to require an accommodation because the 
state's interest cannot satisfy strict scrutiny review, this application of 
RFRA may violate the Establishment Clause if it goes too far in privileging 
religion and imposing unacceptable costs on non-beneficiaries. That's certainly 
how I understand the Cutter opinion and its frequent references to 
accommodations not imposing unacceptable burdens on third parties or public 
institutions. If the Establishment Clause limit on accommodation costs is less 
demanding than a compelling state interest requirement (e.g., courts might not 
consider avoiding those costs to constitute a compelling state interest for 
statutory purposes), the constitutional standard will cap the accommodation 
whatever the statute says.



Alan Brownstein


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Christopher Lund [l...@wayne.edu]
Sent: Sunday, June 17, 2012 1:36 PM
To: 'Law & Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA

I wanted to send out a thought relating to earlier posts by Mark Graber and 
Eugene Volokh.  They suggest an intermediate standard of review, somewhere 
between strict scrutiny and Smith.  I think they are right on the key point.  
The usual  “strict scrutiny” standard – i.e., strict in theory, fatal in fact – 
won’t work for free exercise.   It’s too harsh a standard.  I think defenders 
of regulatory exceptions generally believe that.  But we also all know that, in 
the Shebert/Yoder days, the test wasn’t applied like that.  “Strict in theory, 
feeble in fact,” as people say.

Justice Scalia says in Smith that this is a problem—that it won’t work to have 
a “compelling interest” test in Free Exercise that is less stringent that the 
“compelling interest” test in Free Speech.  It will either (1) water down the 
test in the Free Speech setting, or (2) improperly heighten the test in the 
Free Exercise setting.  Judges will be confused between the two domains, and 
one domain will screw the other up.  Eugene says something similar below.

But I don’t know quite why that is; I haven’t seen any evidence of confusion.  
It seems to me that we could quite sensibly have a compelling-interest test in 
Free Exercise that is lighter than the compelling-interest test in other areas. 
 The compelling-interest test applies differently in different domains: 
“Context matters in applying the compelling interest test.” Gonzales v. O 
Centro, 546 U.S. 418, 431 (2006).  Grutter and Lawrence were decided the same 
term.  Grutter upheld an affirmative action program under a deferential version 
of strict scrutiny; Lawrence struck down a sodomy law under an aggressive 
version of rational basis.  That’s confusing, but no judge tasked with actually 
applying Grutter will be confused by Lawrence (or vice versa).

And what could be more confusing than the current situation?  Right now, we 
have two different compelling-interest tests in the area of Free Exercise 
alone.  Gonzales v. UDV applied RFRA’s compelling-interest test and said that 
it required “sensible balances” between religious liberty and governmental 
interests.  (Gonzales repeats “sensible balances” three times.)  That language 
has been used in state RFRA cases as well.  That’s light years away from 
Lukumi’s compelling-interest test, which really is 
strict-in-theory-and-fatal-in-fact.  But having two different 
compelling-interest tests seems to have worked fine for Free Exercise.  
Students get the difference between them.  We get it.  Courts get it.  I mean, 
occasionally a plaintiff will cite the Lukumi line of cases in support of his 
RFRA or state RFRA claim, thereby making it seem as if state RFRAs create that 
sort of ruthless presumption of invalidity.  But I don’t think courts are 
fooled.  (One great example of a court not bein

Re: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA

2012-06-17 Thread Steven Jamar
I think our levels of scrutiny are too involved and that there are too many. I 
think the court stumbled upon a way forward in the abortion limitation cases 
with the "undue burden" test.  It changes the focus properly to the the fact 
that almost any regulation will burden somebody's liberty or rights or equality 
and the question should be whether in light of all the interests involved, that 
burden is undue.  Of course not all interests are of the same weight and what 
may be undue in one setting (free exercise or free speech) may be acceptable in 
another area (carrying arms).

I think we could profit from rethinking equality along these lines -- is there 
a need now for race-based strict scrutiny or would undue burden analysis be 
enough and allow for appropriate group-based remedies?  

Maybe someday I'll write that useless article -- useless since I don't see any 
likelihood in the next 50 years of such a sweeping change in approach, no 
matter how dysfunctional our current tests have become in many areas.

Steve

On Jun 17, 2012, at 4:36 PM, Christopher Lund wrote:

> I wanted to send out a thought relating to earlier posts by Mark Graber and 
> Eugene Volokh.  They suggest an intermediate standard of review, somewhere 
> between strict scrutiny and Smith.  I think they are right on the key point.  
> The usual  “strict scrutiny” standard – i.e., strict in theory, fatal in fact 
> – won’t work for free exercise.   It’s too harsh a standard.  I think 
> defenders of regulatory exceptions generally believe that.  But we also all 
> know that, in the Shebert/Yoder days, the test wasn’t applied like that.  
> “Strict in theory, feeble in fact,” as people say.
>  
> Justice Scalia says in Smith that this is a problem—that it won’t work to 
> have a “compelling interest” test in Free Exercise that is less stringent 
> that the “compelling interest” test in Free Speech.  It will either (1) water 
> down the test in the Free Speech setting, or (2) improperly heighten the test 
> in the Free Exercise setting.  Judges will be confused between the two 
> domains, and one domain will screw the other up.  Eugene says something 
> similar below.
>  
> But I don’t know quite why that is; I haven’t seen any evidence of confusion. 
>  It seems to me that we could quite sensibly have a compelling-interest test 
> in Free Exercise that is lighter than the compelling-interest test in other 
> areas.  The compelling-interest test applies differently in different 
> domains: “Context matters in applying the compelling interest test.” Gonzales 
> v. O Centro, 546 U.S. 418, 431 (2006).  Grutter and Lawrence were decided the 
> same term.  Grutter upheld an affirmative action program under a deferential 
> version of strict scrutiny; Lawrence struck down a sodomy law under an 
> aggressive version of rational basis.  That’s confusing, but no judge tasked 
> with actually applying Grutter will be confused by Lawrence (or vice versa).
>  
> And what could be more confusing than the current situation?  Right now, we 
> have two different compelling-interest tests in the area of Free Exercise 
> alone.  Gonzales v. UDV applied RFRA’s compelling-interest test and said that 
> it required “sensible balances” between religious liberty and governmental 
> interests.  (Gonzales repeats “sensible balances” three times.)  That 
> language has been used in state RFRA cases as well.  That’s light years away 
> from Lukumi’s compelling-interest test, which really is 
> strict-in-theory-and-fatal-in-fact.  But having two different 
> compelling-interest tests seems to have worked fine for Free Exercise.  
> Students get the difference between them.  We get it.  Courts get it.  I 
> mean, occasionally a plaintiff will cite theLukumi line of cases in support 
> of his RFRA or state RFRA claim, thereby making it seem as if state RFRAs 
> create that sort of ruthless presumption of invalidity.  But I don’t think 
> courts are fooled.  (One great example of a court not being fooled is State 
> v. Hardesty, 214 P.3d 1004, 1008-09 (Ariz. 2009)).  No confusion, as far as I 
> can tell.  So what then is wrong with RFRA’s compelling-interest test, if we 
> agree that “compelling interest” can’t mean here what it might mean in other 
> places?
>  
> Best,
> Chris
>  
> From: Volokh, Eugene 
> Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 10:44 AM
> To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
> Subject: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA
>  
> I disagree on very much with Marci, and I’m not sure that the 
> Sherbert/Yoder test would have been inapplicable to the things that NARAL and 
> CHILD fears. 
>  
> But Marci’s more general point strikes me as quite correct:  At least if read 
> literally, RFRA enacts an across-the-board stri

RE: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA

2012-06-17 Thread Christopher Lund
I wanted to send out a thought relating to earlier posts by Mark Graber and 
Eugene Volokh.  They suggest an intermediate standard of review, somewhere 
between strict scrutiny and Smith.  I think they are right on the key point. 
The usual  “strict scrutiny” standard – i.e., strict in theory, fatal in 
fact – won’t work for free exercise.   It’s too harsh a standard.  I think 
defenders of regulatory exceptions generally believe that.  But we also all 
know that, in the Shebert/Yoder days, the test wasn’t applied like that. 
“Strict in theory, feeble in fact,” as people say.



Justice Scalia says in Smith that this is a problem—that it won’t work to 
have a “compelling interest” test in Free Exercise that is less stringent 
that the “compelling interest” test in Free Speech.  It will either (1) 
water down the test in the Free Speech setting, or (2) improperly heighten 
the test in the Free Exercise setting.  Judges will be confused between the 
two domains, and one domain will screw the other up.  Eugene says something 
similar below.



But I don’t know quite why that is; I haven’t seen any evidence of 
confusion.  It seems to me that we could quite sensibly have a 
compelling-interest test in Free Exercise that is lighter than the 
compelling-interest test in other areas.  The compelling-interest test 
applies differently in different domains: “Context matters in applying the 
compelling interest test.” Gonzales v. O Centro, 546 U.S. 418, 431 (2006). 
Grutter and Lawrence were decided the same term.  Grutter upheld an 
affirmative action program under a deferential version of strict scrutiny; 
Lawrence struck down a sodomy law under an aggressive version of rational 
basis.  That’s confusing, but no judge tasked with actually applying Grutter 
will be confused by Lawrence (or vice versa).



And what could be more confusing than the current situation?  Right now, we 
have two different compelling-interest tests in the area of Free Exercise 
alone.  Gonzales v. UDV applied RFRA’s compelling-interest test and said 
that it required “sensible balances” between religious liberty and 
governmental interests.  (Gonzales repeats “sensible balances” three times.) 
That language has been used in state RFRA cases as well.  That’s light years 
away from Lukumi’s compelling-interest test, which really is 
strict-in-theory-and-fatal-in-fact.  But having two different 
compelling-interest tests seems to have worked fine for Free Exercise. 
Students get the difference between them.  We get it.  Courts get it.  I 
mean, occasionally a plaintiff will cite the Lukumi line of cases in support 
of his RFRA or state RFRA claim, thereby making it seem as if state RFRAs 
create that sort of ruthless presumption of invalidity.  But I don’t think 
courts are fooled.  (One great example of a court not being fooled is State 
v. Hardesty, 214 P.3d 1004, 1008-09 (Ariz. 2009)).  No confusion, as far as 
I can tell.  So what then is wrong with RFRA’s compelling-interest test, if 
we agree that “compelling interest” can’t mean here what it might mean in 
other places?



Best,

Chris



From: Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 10:44 AM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA



I disagree on very much with Marci, and I’m not sure that 
the Sherbert/Yoder test would have been inapplicable to the things that 
NARAL and CHILD fears.



But Marci’s more general point strikes me as quite correct:  At least if 
read literally, RFRA enacts an across-the-board strict scrutiny test, which 
the Court in the Sherbert/Yoder era never did.  For instance, when the 
government was acting as prison administrator or as commander of military 
personnel, the religious exemption test--like the Free Speech Clause 
test--was close to the rational basis framework. Lower courts adopted a 
similarly deferential test for probation conditions that incidentally 
interfered with religious practices.  When the government was acting as 
employer, some lower courts likewise adopted fairly (but not entirely) 
deferential tests borrowed from the Pickering test applied in government 
employee free speech cases. There was no agreed-on test for the government 
acting as educator in kindergarten through high school, but courts at least 
had the option of concluding that the free exercise test--like the free 
speech test--should be relatively deferential in these cases, too.



When the government was acting as sovereign, the test was usually strict 
scrutiny, but not always.  For claimants requesting exemptions from 
generally applicable speech restrictions, the free exercise test was the 
same as the free speech test, which might differ from strict scrutiny. 
Content-neutral restrictions on the time, place, or manner of speech, for 
instance, are only subject to a form of intermediate scrutiny under the Free 
Speech Clause, and Heffron v. ISKCON held that this same quasi-intermed

Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA

2012-06-15 Thread Volokh, Eugene


From: Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 10:44 AM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Strict scrutiny, from Sherbert/Yoder to RFRA

I disagree on very much with Marci, and I’m not sure that the 
Sherbert/Yoder test would have been inapplicable to the things that NARAL and 
CHILD fears.

But Marci’s more general point strikes me as quite correct:  At least if read 
literally, RFRA enacts an across-the-board strict scrutiny test, which the 
Court in the Sherbert/Yoder era never did.  For instance, when the government 
was acting as prison administrator or as commander of military personnel, the 
religious exemption test--like the Free Speech Clause test--was close to the 
rational basis framework. Lower courts adopted a similarly deferential test for 
probation conditions that incidentally interfered with religious practices.  
When the government was acting as employer, some lower courts likewise adopted 
fairly (but not entirely) deferential tests borrowed from the Pickering test 
applied in government employee free speech cases. There was no agreed-on test 
for the government acting as educator in kindergarten through high school, but 
courts at least had the option of concluding that the free exercise test--like 
the free speech test--should be relatively deferential in these cases, too.

When the government was acting as sovereign, the test was usually strict 
scrutiny, but not always.  For claimants requesting exemptions from generally 
applicable speech restrictions, the free exercise test was the same as the free 
speech test, which might differ from strict scrutiny.  Content-neutral 
restrictions on the time, place, or manner of speech, for instance, are only 
subject to a form of intermediate scrutiny under the Free Speech Clause, and 
Heffron v. ISKCON held that this same quasi-intermediate scrutiny was 
applicable to requests for religious exemptions from such restrictions.   
Similarly, some lower court cases suggested that zoning restrictions were 
subject to a lower standard of scrutiny.

Now perhaps the same results could be reached by applying strict scrutiny with 
an eye towards the special circumstances present in those cases – but that, 
even more than the Court’s “feeble in fact” version of strict scrutiny applied 
in cases such as Lee, Bob Jones, and the like, would in practice be a way of 
avoiding strict scrutiny rather than a way of honestly applying it.

Eugene


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 12:09 AM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Religious exemptions in ND

The Sherbert/Yoder test was never treated by the
Supreme Court as a test available across the
board.   So NARAL's concerns and CHILD 's
Issues would not have been controlled by it

The concern is not over enforcement but rather enforcement
Giving religious groups more power to endanger children is
not a good idea.

Marci
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.