“Who will decide there is a need, that climate engineering is an “appropriate 
medicine”? The conditions for making such a technological wager legitimate, 
democratic, and equitable must be explicit. For we are naive to assume the 
decision to administer a medicine by a physician is based on efficacy and 
safety alone. And we will pay the price if we fail to acknowledge that there 
are limits to knowledge and ignore the lessons of history.”

Most scientific bodies (“doctors”) have decided the earth is sick and needs 
“medicine”.
Conventional remedies aren’t working.
A variety of potential technological solutions (“medicines”) have been proposed 
and need to be tested to determine risk/benefit.
Yes, even the best governed scientific endeavors will not be able to identify 
all risks, any better than we can imperfectly predict risk/benefit in medicine.
So given that we will never have perfect knowledge, shall we just let the 
patient die for fear that science cannot provide a better outcome?
If not, what are we waiting for?
-G


Legitimate Conditions for Climate Engineering
Richard Owen
University of Exeter, U.K.
Environ. Sci. Technol., 2011, 45 (21), pp 9116–9117
DOI: 10.1021/es2033185
Publication Date (Web): October 10, 2011
Copyright © 2011 American Chemical Society
On September 13th scientists announced preparations were underway for the first 
UK field trial of climate engineering feasibility.(1) <JavaScript:void(0);>  
The proposed trial will be modest: it will pump water through a 1 km high 
balloon-tethered hose, to assess the feasibility of reflective particle 
injection high into the atmosphere, mimicking the temperature-reducing effects 
of volcanic eruptions. But it has stimulated considerable debate about whether 
research in this controversial field should be undertaken at all, and if so the 
conditions under which it is acceptable to proceed. Responding, the President 
of the UK’s Royal Society, Paul Nurse, replied that there should be research on 
both the efficacy and safety of geoengineering:(2) <JavaScript:void(0);>
“One would not take a medicine that had not been rigorously tested to make sure 
that it worked and was safe. But, if there was a risk of disease, one would 
research possible treatments and, once the effects were established, one would 
take the medicine if needed and appropriate. Similarly we need controlled 
testing of any technologies that might be used in the future”.
His comments, and specifically this analogy to pharmaceuticals, raise important 
questions concerning the conditions under which we decide to deploy 
controversial technologies such as solar radiation management.
Pharmaceuticals indeed go through a rigorous testing process before they are 
authorized for use (“data before market”), but this is because we know the 
harmful effects to look for and there are well-established test methods to 
quantify these, built up over decades of knowledge and incorporated into trials 
of efficacy and safety. We do not have this for the emerging science of climate 
engineering and are therefore compelled to proceed under conditions of 
ignorance.
The response is that we should establish strong research governance processes, 
developing and then employing tests of efficacy and safety before any decision 
to deploy (i.e., proceed with caution) in the same way we have built up 
understanding of pharmaceutical efficacy and safety over time and incorporated 
this into the tests required of medicines before use. This is to be recommended.
The Limits of Knowledge

________________________________

There is however an important caveat to this approach. Despite our best 
intentions, it may only be once deployment has actually occurred that any nasty 
surprises surface. The history of nasty surprises is long, from CFCs to 
asbestos.(3) <JavaScript:void(0);>  Indeed surprises such as thalidomide were a 
major driver of regulation for pharmaceuticals, which in turn strives to ensure 
these effects do not occur again.
But this happens after the fact. Regulation is often blind to that which it has 
not encountered before. Such unanticipated effects might not emerge for solar 
radiation management, but this will always be a gamble for which the 
probabilities can never be known, a point acknowledged by the Royal Society in 
2009. The unintended side effects of many well-intentioned innovations have not 
been predicted. Here there is an analogy with pharmaceuticals: despite tests, 
who could have predicted that the birth control pill would cause environmental 
endocrine disruption?(4) <JavaScript:void(0);>
The argument is that research can help us rule out the technology, on the basis 
of efficacy, safety or both. But what happens if it is not ruled out? What if, 
after careful consideration of risks and feasibility, solar radiation 
management becomes a serious option? Who then would be prepared to place a bet 
for which the stakes can never be fully known? Perhaps the seriousness of 
climate change would make deployment a gamble worth taking. But who would make 
that decision? Who would have the authority to make a (possibly 
intergenerational) commitment to solar radiation management? Who would decide 
that conventional attempts at carbon management and climate change mitigation 
had proved insufficient or unsuccessful? Who would negotiate the distribution 
of impacts across the globe (beneficial or otherwise, known or unknown) that 
might result? Who would compensate those who suffer for the collective good? 
What are the conditions for such planetary technological gambles?
In his essay on the Imperative of Responsibility(5) <JavaScript:void(0);>  
Jonas wrote “One would not deny the statesman the right to risk his nation’s 
existence for its future if really ultimate issues are at stake. It is in this 
manner that awesome but morally defensible decisions about war and peace come 
about when, for future’s sake, the stake is the future itself’. He added that 
‘this should never happen because of the enticement of a wonderful future but 
only under the threat of a terrible future”. The supreme “malum” justifies a 
collective wager. This has been the catalyst for many technological wagers in 
the past, of which the push for mass production of penicillin in World War Two 
is arguably one.
Would the prevention of a terrible future (a “climate change tipping point” for 
example) be a legitimate condition for a collective gamble on a geoengineering 
solution? Perhaps, but this presupposes that this condition has been 
collectively arrived at, and that there is a mechanism for this to be achieved. 
This does not currently exist. It is particularly important for approaches such 
as solar radiation management which may have impacts that may be trans-national 
and unequally distributed in nature. It is here that Nurse’s statement “one 
would take the medicine if needed and appropriate” becomes critical. Who will 
decide there is a need, that climate engineering is an “appropriate medicine”? 
The conditions for making such a technological wager legitimate, democratic, 
and equitable must be explicit. For we are naive to assume the decision to 
administer a medicine by a physician is based on efficacy and safety alone. And 
we will pay the price if we fail to acknowledge that there are limits to 
knowledge and ignore the lessons of history.
References

________________________________

This article references 5 other publications.

 1.  1.

http://www.nerc.ac.uk/press/releases/2011/22-spice.asp (accessed June 10, 2011).

 1.  2.

http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/2011/sep/08/geoengineering-research-royal-society
 (accessed June 10, 2011).

 1.  3.

http://www.eea.europa.eu/publications/environmental_issue_report_2001_22 
(accessed June 10, 2011).

 1.  4.

Jobling, S. and Owen, R.Ethinyl oestradiol: Bitter pill for the precautionary 
principle. In: Late Lessons from Early Warnings II; European Environment 
Agency, (in press).

 1.  5.

Jonas, H. The Imperative of Responsibility; University of Chicago Press, 
Chicago, 1984.


-- 
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
"geoengineering" group.
To post to this group, send email to geoengineering@googlegroups.com.
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
geoengineering+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/geoengineering?hl=en.

Reply via email to