Dear Gary, Douglas, lists,

Thanks to Gary for the reference to the Harvard lecture draft. I went back and 
reread that (pretty fantastic btw) piece of prose. Gary's right about P's 
"waverings" (as he calls it) regarding the relation between the categories and 
the three argument types, ab-, in- and deduction (which is the 1-2-3 sequence 
followed in this text). In the deleted part added as s footnote in Turrisi's 
edition to which  Gary also refers, P. leaves "the question undecided".
I think there is no doubt in the overall perspective that Peirce stuck, despite 
these waverings, to the ab-, de-, in-sequence in the larger perspective of the 
mature version of his logic - this is supported by his stable dichotomy of 
deductions (corollarial vs. theorematic, to which I return in a later chapter) 
and his (a bit less) stable trichotomy of inductions (pooh-pooh, quantitative, 
and qualitative, respectively) - given P's argument that Secondnesses give rise 
to dichotomies, Thirdnesses to trichotomies.
But despte this fact there is indeed good reason to investigate the arguments 
for the two different versions - the ab-in-de sequence dominated P's earlier 
years so it is really a case with much wavering on his part. The argument for 
the ab-in-de sequence in the deleted part of the Harvard lecture draft go as 
follows: ab-in-de function by means of icons, indices, and symbols, 
respectively - and induction has two subtypes (here, quantitative and 
qualitative) while deduction has three (here, three of the normal four types of 
syllogisms of which the fourth is claimed reductible).
In addition to the dichotomy-trichotomy argument, the corresponding arguments 
for the ab-de-in sequence often relies upon taking that sequence as a typical 
procedural sequence in the logic of discovery: abduction first proposes a 
hypothesis on the basis of some facts; deduction then takes this hypothesis as 
an ideal model and infers some necessary consequences from it; induction 
finally tests those deductive results by comparing them to empircal samples. 
(But is there necessarily any strong link between the 1-2-3 classification and 
the sequence of procedure?)
I think, however, that the decisive argument for finally settling on the 
ab-de-in sequence was Peirces double identification of deduction with 
diagrammatical reasoning and with mathematics (diagrams being seconds in the 
image-diagram-metaphor trichotomy) - instead of the identification of deduction 
with symbol-supported reasoning in the 5th Harvard lecture.
A third sequence which P often gives in the 1900s is de-in-ab which does not 
seem to refer to categories nor to procedure, but rather to the falling order 
of degree of validity (from necessary over probable to possible) - probably 
also an order of importance, deduction often (also in Gary's Harvard lecture) 
being described as the overall argument type which the other two somehow feed 
into.

All this said, I think a commentary on a meta-level should be added. I am not 
certain that 1-2-3 sequenceing in terms of the categories should always have 
first priority when discussing Peircean triadic distinctions. Of course, it is 
easy to get this idea from the classification of sciences where categories 
belong to Phenomenology, being second only to Mathematics in the hierarchy. But 
P's own practice counts against taking this Comtean hiearchy itself as a 
sequence of inference from top to bottom so that lower sciences should receive 
dictates by higher ones. There's a traffic also in the bottom-up direction - 
the lower sciences receive principles from the higher ones, alright, but the 
higher ones articulate those principles by abstracting from the matter of the 
lower ones. This latter is especially the case regarding the relation between 
logic and categories where P follows Kant's idea that the categories should be 
abstracted from logic. This implies that logic is actually the source of the 
categories (which is also evident from many P claims already in the 1860s). So 
even if, in the hierarchy of the ideal, static end point of inquiry, categories 
give principles to logic, in the ongoing process of discovery it is rather the 
categories which are abstracted out of logic. So before the final doctrine of 
categories is consummated, we should not be able to expect them to be able to 
legislate over logic - also because of the simple fact that Peirce discovered a 
whole lot more of logic than about category phenomenology which remained 
ambiguous (cf. the enormous amount of very different descriptions of the 
categories - as compared to the far larger stability of the description of 
ab-de-in, irrespectively of their sequence). This is why I generally hesitate 
to call in the categories as final arbiters of trichotomy issues lower in the 
system.

Finally, Doug asked about Bellucci's claim about an internal ab-de-in sequence 
within deduction. I perfectly agree with that suggestion - I think I also 
address it a bit later in the book because it becomes evident in theorematic 
deduction. In mathematical proofs, the case in general is that there is no 
given algorithm to follow, and from one proposition many different other 
propositions may be inferred. This immediately implies a trial-and-error 
procedure - which is by nature abductive. You have to check which direction of 
the proof proves fertile. In the other end, there undoubtedly is a phase 
resembling induction, namely the investigation of coherence of the result with 
established results of other branches of mathematics. So I am certainly with 
Bellucci here.

Best
F

Den 17/12/2014 kl. 02.41 skrev Gary Richmond 
<gary.richm...@gmail.com<mailto:gary.richm...@gmail.com>>:

Douglas, lists,

You wrote: "I learned at the Centennial Conference that Professor Stjernfelt 
associates the two forms of deduction with secondness, and the three forms of 
induction with thirdness.

In the 1903 Harvard lectures draft I pointed to, Peirce seems instead to have 
settled (albeit tentatively) on deduction as associated with 3ns (necessary 
reasoning) and induction with 2ns.

I would encourage anyone interested in this categorial issue (how the 
categories are associated with the three inference patterns) to read that 
draft. It shows how Peirce assiduously applies the principle of fallibility to 
his own research, and just how self-critical he can be.

Best,

Gary R


[Gary Richmond]

Gary Richmond
Philosophy and Critical Thinking
Communication Studies
LaGuardia College of the City University of New York
C 745
718 482-5690

On Tue, Dec 16, 2014 at 8:08 PM, Douglas Hare 
<ddh...@mail.harvard.edu<mailto:ddh...@mail.harvard.edu>> wrote:
Gary R.,

Thanks for the reply. I don't have any brilliant answers at this point, but 
there seems to be an immense amount of confusion surrounding Peirce's theory of 
the modes of inference and the order of inquiry. I learned at the Centennial 
Conference that Professor Stjernfelt associates the two forms of deduction with 
secondness, and the three forms of induction with thirdness. For now, I will 
await his reply before offering any of my half-baked ideas on the relationship 
between these irreducible types of reasoning/stages of inquiry.

List,
Please note that among other typos in my last posting, I misspelled the name of 
Irving Anellis, and I meant to say that the model-theoretic tradition's 
approach to language does *not* run up against prison-house of language 
problems (ineffability claims) given the possibilities of meta-languages.

Yours,
DH

On Tue, Dec 16, 2014 at 7:19 PM, Gary Richmond 
<gary.richm...@gmail.com<mailto:gary.richm...@gmail.com>> wrote:
Douglas, lists,

Thank you for this insightful post--you've clearly given considerable thought 
to these matters. Because of time constraints, for now I'd like only to respond 
to your question to Frederik at the conclusion of your post.

DH: I would like to close by asking Professor Stjernfelt if he agrees with 
Francesco Bellucci that the late Peirce saw diagrammatic reasoning containing 
its own abductive and inductive phases. I look forward to any questions or 
comments before we begin Chapter 8.

I too would be interested in Frederik's answer to this question. Meanwhile, 
your question did make me think of a comment Peirce made in one of the drafts 
of the 1903 Harvard Lectures on Pragmatism which may have some, even if small, 
bearing on the answer to your question.

I have occasionally referred to this draft (see note 3 to Lecture 5, 276-7, in 
Patricia Turrisi's edition of the lectures) to show that Peirce had changed his 
mind (and then changed it back again) as to whether deduction should be 
associated with categorial 2ns or 3ns. Here I would note that at the conclusion 
of this section of the draft lecture that he comments that there were some 
opinions upon which he had never changed his mind:

One of these is that although Abductive and Inductive reasoning are distinctly 
not reducible to Deductive reasoning, nor either to the other, yet the 
rationale of Abduction and of Induction must itself be Deductive. All my 
reflections and self-criticisms have only served to strengthen me in this 
opinion. But if this be so, to state wherein the validity of mathematical 
reasoning consists is to state the ultimate ground on which any reasoning must 
rest (Turrisi, 277).

Best,

Gary R

[Gary Richmond]

Gary Richmond
Philosophy and Critical Thinking
Communication Studies
LaGuardia College of the City University of New York
C 745
718 482-5690<tel:718%20482-5690>

On Tue, Dec 16, 2014 at 4:48 PM, Douglas Hare 
<ddh...@mail.harvard.edu<mailto:ddh...@mail.harvard.edu>> wrote:
7.5 Diagrams in Linguistics

In the final section of Chapter 7, language emerges from the Dicisign doctrine 
as diagrammatical tool combining “loosely coupled parts” in order to serve as a 
representing and reasoning organ with potentially “universal” application. 
Using the premiss that diagrams are responsible for all deductive reasoning, we 
can then produce an account of how ordinary language possesses 
'diagrammaticity' at the very least in its ability to encode logical inferences 
in the form of syllogisms. But if the difference between language and pictorial 
representations is a diagrammatical matter of degree (measure of iconicity), 
not a difference of kind, then the Herculean tasks of reinterpreting the 
“levels” of natural language into their diagrammatic forms and figuring out how 
to measure gradations within natural language as well as with other iconic 
forms of signification appear before us. Later chapters might clarify why 
Peirce's Existential Graphs remain a valuable instrument for both ostensibly 
Sisyphean endeavors. But ignoring the Alpha and Beta Graphs for now, many 
recent cognitive linguists cited by the author seem to agree that the logical 
connectors of propositional logic, the linguistic quantifiers of first order 
predicate logic, and other more basic structures of grammar allow for possible 
topological formalization(s).

Recall that for Peirce, Dicisigns are formed with icon rhemes and their 
saturation by means of index rhemes. The cognitive linguist would agree that 
sentences are formed by predicates and their saturation by means of subjects. 
To wit: “A basic tendency seems to be that the distinction between grammar and 
morphology on the one hand, and lexical semantics on the other roughly 
corresponds to diagrams pertaining to formal and material ontologies, 
respectively” (NP, 196). If iconic structures can be found in the form of 
conjunctions and sentence structures as well as the the multiplicity of 
structures of rhemes/predicates themselves, grammatical transformations contain 
logical content, and more broadly grammar and morphology will generally contain 
discoverable implicit formal-material ontologies while lexical semantics can 
fill in regional ontological information with particulars: adjectives, common 
nouns, verbs and combinations thereof. Based on underlying forms of 
diagrammatic reasoning, ordinary language does not remain committed to any 
particular ontology (because diagrammatic reasoning is not committed to any 
particular topological framework), even if it acquires variable ontological 
commitments to objects and relational properties of the universe of discourse 
in which we engage, which Qualities and Existents we recognize, and how we 
choose to construct our Arguments.

Stjernfelt relates the blurring of the grammar/semantics distinction to 
Husserl's use of the scholastic distinction between syncategorematica (closed 
classes)and categoramatica (open classes), and makes the observation that, in 
all three accounts, formal ontologies are produced that contain subclasses of 
formal ontologies such as modal logic, temporal logic, higher order logic on 
the one hand and high-level material ontological concepts from epistemic logic, 
deontic logic, speech act logic on the other. The linguist might say that 
high-level material ontologies include modal verbs, tempus morphemes of verbs, 
in propositional stances verbs, in speech act verbs,” (NP, 199) but regardless 
of the terminological variation, the “doubleness of isomorphism and 
independence recognized between logic, language, and ontology” (NP, 202) is a 
common thread whereby a gluing (interdependence) between the global/local 
provided by the Dicisign structure overcomes the structuralist account the 
arbitrarity of language (usually inferred from the relationship between sounds 
and words), because “conceived from a diagrammatical point of view, language 
has two levels, one general, formal, vague, formalized in grammar and 
closed-class categorematica—and another in lexical semantics and open-class 
syncategorematic,” (NP, 199) which are open to further investigation. Ordinary 
language remains 'secular'—not committed to any topological or metaphysical 
viewpoint ahead of time because the genuine interaction between (what I am 
calling) the relatively autonomous global/local levels allows for language to 
remain an ecumenical, indefinitely-extended, self-critical means of information 
processing.

The author closes the chapter with a discussion of Hintikka's identification of 
two strands of 20th century philosophy, one which views language as universal 
representation and one which sees it as a calculus. According to the Hintikkan 
geneaology, Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein, Quine, and even Heidegger and Derrida 
seem to favor the former approach (language as one reference domain to all 
reality with privileged semiotic access to the world) while Boole, Peirce 
Schroder, Hilbert, Husserl, and the late Carnap understand that multiple 
representational systems with differing degrees of generality, granularity, are 
quite possible if not necessary to productive inquiry as an open-system which 
does run up against, in Hintikka's words, “prisonhouse of language hypotheses.” 
I do not disagree with Stjernfelt's claim that for the model-theoretic 
tradition considers language as closer to a calculus ratiocinator than a 
mathesis univseralis but I would contend that Irving Annelis's 
paper<http://arxiv.org/pdf/1201.0353.pdf> ( c.f. pp. 25-28) offers a more 
nuanced assessment how these Leibnizian themes are re-appropriated by the late 
Peirce than that of Hintikka, in my humble opinion.

For Peirce, representational pluralism does not conflict with a robust realism 
given his idea of inquiry as a distinctly communal activity, one in which 
natural language is able to engage by means of presenting various 
formalizations which “semiotically triangulate the object,” (NP, 200) and one 
in which individual inquiry itself engages in a sort of game-theoretic 
semantics. Given one representational system's ability to assess another, we 
are not left with the ineffability claims but a science of semantics. Indeed, a 
careful reading of Chapter 7 offers the reader a deeper understanding of how 
language remains capable of entertaining universes of discourse which lack 
logical consistency or logical commitment so we have at our disposal a tool 
capable of examining and experimenting with the ontologically inconsistent, the 
vague, the general, and the imaginary. Peirce's 'fallibilistic apriorism' 
(opposed to Kantian apriorism) is better able to account for the various a 
priori structures of different material ontologies. Language from the 
diagrammatic perspective thus resembles a versatile collaboration between 
different topological considerations found inside, outside, and between 
conjunctions, grammar, semantics, and their various instantiations. Along with 
recent developments in Existential Graphs, the trajectory cognitive semantics 
exposited by Stjernfelt makes a strong case for CSP's continued relevance to 
diagrammatological linguistics.

I would like to close by asking Professor Stjernfelt if he agrees with 
Francesco Bellucci that the late Peirce saw diagrammatic reasoning containing 
its own abductive and inductive phases. I look forward to any questions or 
comments before we begin Chapter 8.

Thankfully,

Doug


-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to 
peirce-L@list.iupui.edu<mailto:peirce-L@list.iupui.edu> . To UNSUBSCRIBE, send 
a message not to PEIRCE-L but to 
l...@list.iupui.edu<mailto:l...@list.iupui.edu> with the line "UNSubscribe 
PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .







-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to 
peirce-L@list.iupui.edu<mailto:peirce-L@list.iupui.edu> . To UNSUBSCRIBE, send 
a message not to PEIRCE-L but to 
l...@list.iupui.edu<mailto:l...@list.iupui.edu> with the line "UNSubscribe 
PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .






-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to