Jeff, List,

Those are important questions:

JBD:  How important is it to consider the things Peirce is reading for the sake 
of understanding what he says? Let me start with a simple point. Can we 
understand what Peirce is explicitly saying about another author's views 
without reading the passages in their writings to which Peirce is referring?

Unfortunately, that evidence doesn't exist.   But I certainly agree with the 
following point:

JBD:  I think that (1) reading the texts and (2) reading what he is reading go 
hand in hand. That is, reading what he is reading is essential to understanding 
the texts--at least in those places where he is explicitly or implicitly 
referring to, drawing on, or reacting to the ideas of others.

I would also emphasize Peirce's uncanny ability to anticipate future 
developments, especially in logic..  That is why I would add that a knowledge 
of developments in the century after Peirce is important for evaluating his 
contributions.  Good sources for such evaluations are the talks presented at 
the Peirce Sesquicentennial in 1989 and the Centennial in 2014.  The modern 
experts in fields that Peirce had pioneered emphasized many of his most 
significant insights,   There are also many ongoing publications that address 
his contributions to the future.

In any case, thanks for preparing that list of authors and the number of 
references to each.  That list is worth saving and consulting as a guide to 
research.  To understand what Peirce wrote at any point in time, it's important 
to look both forwards and backwards -- both in his own writings and in the 
writings of his predecessors and successors.

Even authors who never read anything by Peirce were influenced by people who 
had and by people who rediscovered some of his ideas.  Tarski and Gentzen, for 
example, were brilliant logicians, but it's inaccurate to say that Peirce had 
anticipated their work.  In some important respects, he went beyond them.

John

From: "Jeffrey Brian Downard" <jeffrey.down...@nau.edu>

Jon S, List,
How important is it to consider the things Peirce is reading for the sake of 
understanding what he says? Let me start with a simple point. Can we understand 
what Peirce is explicitly saying about another author's views without reading 
the passages in their writings to which Peirce is referring?
For the sake of satisfying my own curiosity, I've made a list of the number of 
pages in the CP that make reference to philosophers, scientists, 
mathematicians, and literary figures. Given the fact that the CP is only a 
small portion of his writings, it isn't comprehensive. What is more, it does 
not count the total number of references made to a given name, which is higher 
in many cases due to multiple references made on a single page. Nor does it 
take into consideration discussions of a view that continue for many pages 
without repetitive references to a specific name.
Let us suppose for the sake of argument that the CP consists of about 10% of 
his writings and that they are a representative sample. Under this supposition 
(which is not accurate), we would need to multiply the numbers below by a 
factor of 10 in order to approximate the number of pages that involve 
references to the writings of others.
Here is the list:
Top 12:
Aristotle  227
Kant  218
Hegel  121
Boole  95
Schröder  76
Scotus  66
Plato  60+
Euclid  58
Royce  57
William James  50
Cantor  50
Berkeley  50

Philosophy
Pythagoras 12
Parmenides 3
Heraclitus 1
Democritus 5
Zeno 12
Plato, Platonic, Platonism  60+
Aristotle, Aristotelian, Aristotelis 227
Diogenes, Cynic  6
Plotinus, neoplatonic 2
Stoic 16
Boethius 25 (6 in text, 19 in fn)
Augustine 11
John of Salisbury 14
Abelard 17
Scotus 66
Ockham 34
Roger Bacon 11
Aquinas 27
Francis Bacon 17
Hobbes 26
Descartes 39
Pascal 5
Spinoza 12
Leibniz 35
Locke 37
Berkeley  50
Hume 40
Reid 19
Kant, Kantian 218
Friedrich Schiller 2
Fichte 6
Schelling 8
Hegel, Hegelian 121
Bentham 13
James Mill 11
Whewell 21
John Stuart Mill 17
William Hamilton 32
Schopenhauer 3
Nietzsche 0
Ferdinand (FCS) Schiller 24
Royce 57
William James 50
Dewey 13
Husserl 3

Science
Copernicus 9
Galileo 21
Tycho Brahe 4
Kepler 20
Newton 34
Faraday 5
Clausius 11
Thomson 10
Maxwell 10
Ricardo 4
Adam Smith 1
Comte 22
Spencer, Spencerian 27
Darwin 34
Agassiz 6
Oliver Wendell Holmes 2

Mathematics
Pappus 1
Eudoxus 0
Euclid, Euclidean 58
Archimedes 7
Fermat 28
Desargues 1
Bernoulli 9
Playfair, 7
Euler, Euler’s, Eulerian 31
Projective geometry 11
William Rowan Hamilton 38
Gauss 11
Riemann 6
Boole, Boole’s, Boolean 95
DeMorgan 4
Jevons 33
Peano 4
Dedekind 17
Cantor, Cantorian, 50
Kempe 14
Listing 13
Schröder  76
Whitehead 3
Bertrand Russell 2

Literature
Homer 1
Aeschylus 0
Sophocles 0
Lucretius 4
Dante 4
Shakespeare 9
Milton 4
Henry James 5
Sherlock Holmes 1
Emerson 6

Religious
Jesus 11
Buddha 5
Mohammed 1
Holy Ghost 1
Moses 0
Confuscius 0
Brahma 1
It is remarkable, I think, that Peirce makes so many references to Aristotle 
and Kant. As far as I can see, this is some evidence that he is grappling with 
their methods, inquiries, arguments and ideas in a more sustained fashion than 
any of the other philosophers on the list.
So, for the sake of spelling out my own approach to interpreting Peirce's 
writings, I think that (1) reading the texts and (2) reading what he is reading 
go hand in hand. That is, reading what he is reading is essential to 
understanding the texts--at least in those places where he is explicitly or 
implicitly referring to, drawing on, or reacting to the ideas of others.
Yours,
Jeff
Jeffrey Downard
Associate Professor
Department of Philosophy
Northern Arizona University
(o) 928 523-8354

----------------------------------------
From: Jon Alan Schmidt <jonalanschm...@gmail.com>
Sent: Saturday, August 8, 2020 1:35 PM

Jeff, List:

JD:  Jon S asked for references to texts where Peirce employs the distinction 
between principles and laws.

I specifically asked for references where Peirce supposedly endorses your claim 
that "a law of logic governs the relations between the facts expressed in the 
premisses and conclusion of an argument. A principle, on the other hand, is our 
representation of such a law."

JD:  Peirce's definition in the Century Dictionary of the term "principle" is 
instructive on this point.

Quoting those definitions would have been appreciated, rather than expecting 
everyone on the List to look them up for ourselves, although Ben Udell kindly 
provided a link to the ones for "principle" (another is below).

JD:  See the 4th and 5th senses and the examples of uses by Aristotle, 
Hamilton, etc.

CSP:  4. A truth which is evident and general; a truth comprehending many 
subordinate truths; a law on which others are founded, or from which others are 
derived: as, the principles of morality, of equity, of government, etc. In 
mathematical physics a principle commonly means a very widely useful theorem. 
...

5. That which is professed or accepted as a law of action or a rule of conduct; 
one of the fundamental doctrines or tenets of a system: as, the principles of 
the Stoics or the Epicureans; hence, a right rule of conduct; in general, 
equity; uprightness: as, a man of principle. 
(http://triggs.djvu.org/century-dictionary.com/djvu2jpgframes.php?volno=06&page=294&query=principle)

There are no accompanying examples of uses by Aristotle, and the only one from 
Hamilton--which mentions Aristotle--is for the 2nd sense, not the 4th or 5th.

CSP:  2. Cause, in the widest sense; that by which anything is in any way 
ultimately determined or regulated. ...

"Without entering into the various meanings of the term Principle, which 
Aristotle defines, in general, that from whence anything exists, is produced, 
or is known, it is sufficient to say that it is always used for that on which 
something else depends; and thus both for an original law and for an original 
element. In the former case it is a regulative, in the latter a constitutive,  
principle." Sir W. Hamilton, Reid, Note A, §5, Supplementary Dissertations

Aristotle and Hamilton evidently define "principle" as "that on which something 
else depends," such as "an original law."  The 4th sense similarly defines it 
as "a law on which others are founded, or from which others are derived."  The 
5th sense seems consistent with my interpretation, rather than yours--excluded 
middle "is professed or accepted as a law" within classical logic, such that it 
is "one of the fundamental doctrines or tenets of [that] system."  In any case, 
Peirce never defines a principle as our representation of a law; on the 
contrary ...

JD:  Compare that the 3rd sense of "law" in his definition of the term.

CSP:  3. A proposition which expresses the constant or regular order of certain 
phenomena, or the constant mode of action of a force; a general formula or rule 
to which all things, or all things or phenomena within the limits of a certain 
class or group, conform, precisely and without exception; a rule to which 
events really tend to conform. 
(http://triggs.djvu.org/century-dictionary.com/djvu2jpgframes.php?volno=04&page=705&query=law)

It is a law, not a principle, that he defines as a proposition--i.e.,. a 
representation.  He goes on to call it "a general formula or rule to which all 
things ... conform, precisely and without exception."  As I said before, 
excluded middle is not a law, because it is not  exceptionless.

JD:  Here is a famous passage [CP 1.405-406, c. 1896] where Peirce explicitly 
employs the Kantian distinction.

Where do you see such a distinction in that passage?  The only mention of the 
word "law" in what you quoted is naming it as something that calls for an 
explanation.  Meanwhile, Peirce straightforwardly equates "a regulative 
principle" with "an intellectual hope," which is perfectly consistent with his 
description of the principle of excluded middle as a hope rather than a law in 
what I quoted previously from NEM 4:xiii.

JD:  At the same time, I'm trying to understand what Peirce is saying by 
reading what he is reading. That, I think, is necessary to understand what he's 
saying.

I have no doubt that it is helpful and insightful, but I disagree that it is 
necessary.  Surely it is not a requirement for anyone who wants to understand 
Peirce's vast corpus of writings to read everything that he was reading at the 
time, which would obviously be another vast corpus of writings.  And would we 
not then also need to read whatever all those other authors were reading when 
they wrote what they wrote, in order to understand what they were saying?  And 
so on, ad infinitum.

On the contrary, I believe that in most cases a good writer is capable of being 
understood on his/her own terms.  As Gary Fuhrman once  summarized, "I assume 
that he [Peirce] means exactly what he says and says exactly what he means, 
until I have sufficient reason to abandon that working assumption."

Regards,

Jon Alan Schmidt - Olathe, Kansas, USA
Structural Engineer, Synechist Philosopher, Lutheran Christian
www.LinkedIn.com/in/JonAlanSchmidt - twitter.com/JonAlanSchmidt

On Fri, Aug 7, 2020 at 5:14 PM Jeffrey Brian Downard <jeffrey.down...@nau.edu> 
wrote:

Jon Schmidt, John Sowa, Gary Fuhrman, Gary Richmond, Robert Marty, List,
Jon S asked for references to texts where Peirce employs the distinction 
between principles and laws. Peirce's definition in the Century Dictionary of 
the term "principle" is instructive on this point. See the 4th and 5th senses 
and the examples of uses by Aristotle, Hamilton, etc. Compare that the 3rd 
sense of "law" in his definition of the term.
Here is a famous passage where Peirce explicitly employs the Kantian 
distinction. It is especially pertinent to the passage you've quoted:

But every fact of a general or orderly nature calls for an explanation; and 
logic forbids us to assume in regard to any given fact of that sort that it is 
of its own nature absolutely inexplicable. This is what Kant calls a regulative 
principle, that is to say, an intellectual hope. The sole immediate purpose of 
thinking is to render things intelligible; and to think and yet in that very 
act to think a thing unintelligible is a self-stultification. ... Among other 
regular facts that have to be explained is law or regularity itself. (1.405-6)

I am confident that each of us is capable of looking up and analyzing other 
passages that use the terms "law", "principle" and "logic" in the CP. As such, 
I won't offer a laundry list of such passages.
For my part, I don't think the distinction is new with Kant. In fact it is 
quite old. Kant simply tried to clarify well-established use of the 
conceptions. Notice how easily we slide from talking about the principles 
expressed in a theory, such as the principles of mechanics in Newton's theory 
of physics, to talk about the laws. Doing so is often elliptical. We are often 
saying on the supposition that this theory is true then the principles express 
the real laws in nature. It is not odd to say that the principles in a given 
theory turned out to be false. It is odd, however, to say the laws turned out 
to be false. Rather, we say our supposition that the laws taken to be real in 
given theory turned out to be false.
One reason there the meaning of these two terms appears to have changed over 
time is that an original use of the term "law" is its juridical use. It appears 
that the English term of a legal requirement was later applied to the real 
regularities in nature. The order of Peirce's definitions suggests that he 
understands the history of this term.
Notice the apparent differences in our respective approaches to reading these 
texts. In my post, I was drawing on a secondary reference that I hold in high 
esteem. Let me state the reference now, which is Richard Smyth's Reading Peirce 
Reading. In his interpretation of the early essays, he interprets key arguments 
in  Peirce's justification of the validity of the laws of logic drawing on 
Kantian ideas. This is not surprising given the weight Peirce places on his 
reading of Kant's Critiques at this stage in the development of the theory of 
critical logic.
When I'm trying to make sense of Peirce's writings, I find it is essential to 
draw on the secondary literature and to sort out what seems more and less 
helpful. At the same time, I'm trying to understand what Peirce is saying by 
reading what he is reading. That, I think, is necessary to understand what he's 
saying.
John Sowa suggests that a richer understanding of Peirce's inquiries can be 
gained by seeing where they have taken later reachers who have followed in his 
wake. As such, there are five sources that seem important to reading Peirce:

- the texts themselves;
- the secondary literature on Peirce;
- the inquiries of philosophers, scientists, mathematicians (etc.) Peirce was 
reading--especially those he was drawing on in a sustained manner;
- the inquiries of those following in Peirce's wake (self-consciously or not).

In addition to asking how Peirce used this or that term in a given text (as in 
1, above), I think that it is essential that we (5) try to reconstruct his 
arguments and, at the same time, engage in the inquiries ourselves. After all, 
Peirce's writings were not written for armchair philosophers. Rather, they were 
written for inquirers willing to engage in philosophy as an experimental 
science.

Are there other resources not on this list that should be considered when 
interpreting Peirce's arguments and inquiries? If so, then I think it is worth 
saying so. That way, we can talk about the relative importance of these 
different resources in our respective approaches. My hope is that we can 
compare notes, acknowledge our differences, and learn from one another.

Doing so will put us all in a better position to engage with philosophers and 
other inquirers who are not following in Peirce's wake--and who insist that 
they have  more fruitful assumptions and better methods than the pragmatic 
methods we are looking to Peirce for guidance in putting to better use.

Hope that helps.

--Jeff
Jeffrey Downard
Associate Professor
Department of Philosophy
Northern Arizona University
(o) 928 523-8354
_ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _
ARISBE: THE PEIRCE GATEWAY is now at 
https://cspeirce.com  and, just as well, at 
https://www.cspeirce.com .  It'll take a while to repair / update all the links!
► PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON 
PEIRCE-L to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . 
► To UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message NOT to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu 
with UNSUBSCRIBE PEIRCE-L in the SUBJECT LINE of the message and nothing in the 
body.  More at https://list.iupui.edu/sympa/help/user-signoff.html .
► PEIRCE-L is owned by THE PEIRCE GROUP;  moderated by Gary Richmond;  and 
co-managed by him and Ben Udell.

Reply via email to