Angela:
>'repressed memories', which is to say that term that comes into being
>as a juridical proof of a crime, is of course, rubbish, and for many
>of the reasons that freud pointed out: namely, that rememberances are
>always fantastic rememberances, or at the very least tainted, and
>would hardly consitute proof in the juridical sense. 

The Observer 

June 8, 1997, Sunday 

THE WEEK IN REVIEWS: BOOKS: CALL IN THE FREUD SQUAD 

By  Anthony Clare 

There is no more bitter dispute in the field of mental health than that
about 'false' memories. What intensifies the bitterness is that at its core
is the stomach-churning issue of child sexual abuse. Those whose memories
are challenged include many patients alleging serious sexual abuse at the
hands of parents, siblings and guardians. Those challenging retrieved
memories of abuse include parents and relatives accused of CSA, some
innocent, some almost certainly guilty. There are those who insist that
some traumatic experiences are so psychologically destructive that the
sufferer, consciously or not, 'represses' them and lives a life seemingly
indifferent to them unless, usually with the help of a sympathetic
therapist, the memories are unearthed. Others argue with equal vehemence
that there is no such thing as 'repressed' memory, that it is yet another
spurious Freudian dogma, and that therapists use questionable methods of
interrogation to suggest and insert false memories that are the allegedly
buried ones. At the heart of the controversy is a scientific question can
the mind completely and involuntarily pack in the unconscious memories of
repeated traumatic events and recover them with accuracy and in detail many
years later? A formidable protagonist in this battle is Frederick Crews, an
emeritus professor not of psychology or psychiatry, but of English. In
common with many literary academics in the postwar years, Crews was, as he
describes himself, 'a one-time Freudian' who has since seen the light. In
1993, he published an article, 'The Unknown Freud', in the New York Review
of Books, in which he argued that the founder of psychoanalysis was 'a
saturnine self-dramatiser' who showed a cavalier disdain for facts,
invariably preferred an arcane explanation to an obvious one, brazenly
interfered with the marriage of a patient in order to get his hands on an
heiress's money, doctored his data and manipulated his clients, and who, in
the words of an American psychoanalyst trained by Freud, 'would wait until
he found an association that would fit his scheme of interpretation and
pick it up like a detective at a line-up who waits until he sees his man'.
In that same article, Crews studied several Freudian case histories, and
concluded that Freud did not elicit repressed memories from his patients,
but constructed them and proceeded to create a therapeutic arrangement in
which these 'repressed' memories were uncovered. 

As Allen Esterson reminds us, in his powerful book Seductive Mirage, the
controversy over Freud's seduction theory has tended to focus on whether
the accusatory tales of childhood sexual abuse recounted by his patients
were believable. Jeffrey Masson held that the stories were true and that
Freud showed a failure of nerve in renouncing them. Peter Gay asserts that
the stories were false and that Freud had been taken in by his own
patients. But, argued Crews, drawing heavily on Esterson, both parties have
missed the point. The question is not whether the stories are true but,
rather, what stories. 

Freud asserted that 'almost all my women patients told me they had been
seduced by their father'. He later decided such revelations were fantasies.
His papers, however, revealed that before they came to analysis, these
women knew nothing about such events until he suggested them. Freud
described how he did it: 'Only the strongest compulsion of the treatment
can induce them to embark on a reproduction of them.' Then, as Esterson
describes it: 'Having decided that his own constructions (about childhood
sexual abuse) are untrue, he concludes that they are not genuine
occurrences, but fantasies of his patients.' Crews concludes that the
coercive tactics by which Freud tried to win his patients' agreement to his
own theory-driven surmises about their histories 'rendered him chief
begetter of contemporary 'false memory syndrome'.' The essay, 'The Unknown
Freud', together with the follow-up 'The Revenge of the Repressed', which
also appeared in the New York Review of Books, are both contained in this
book, and alone would make it worth a read. But what makes the book
mandatory for anyone interested not just in the brutal skirmish over
repressed memory but in the wider war over the status of psychoanalysis is
that Crews has included substantial excerpts from one of the largest
postbags of correspondence that any article in that literary journal has
provoked. His assaults on psychoanalysis and its founder stirred passionate
controversy. Here, luminaries of the psychoanalytic world lock horns with
Crews, challenging his dismissal of the therapeutic bankruptcy of
psychoanalysis and contesting his allegations of dishonesty against Freud. 

Several years ago, the British Psychological Society produced its Report on
Recovered Memories, summarising the views of the society's 810 members who
had responded to a questionnaire on the subject. The report came down on
the side of recovered memories, concluding that complete or partial memory
loss is an oft-reported consequence of experiencing certain kinds of
psychological trauma, including childhood sexual abuse, and that such
memories may be recovered within or independently of therapy. 'Memory
recovery,' the report added, 'is reported by highly experienced and
well-qualified therapists well aware of the dangers of inappropriate
suggestion and interpretation.' The report did admit that therapists could
create in their clients false memories of childhood sexual abuse, but felt
there was no reliable evidence that this was a widespread phenomenon in the
UK. 

Crews, however, challenges the wisdom of relying on what therapists believe
derives from 'clinical experience' to sustain the view that 'the mind can
shield itself from ugly experiences, thoughts or feelings by relegating
them to a special 'timeless' region where they indefinitely retain a
symptom-producing virulence'. He insists that only properly conducted
scientific research can clarify the picture. His pugnacious and sturdy
views have led critics to accuse him of arguing that there is no such thing
as childhood sexual abuse. He rebuts the charge, but admits he is highly
dubious of the notion of repressed memory. Memories can disappear because
of factors other than repression. Memories can fade with time and, more
problematically, the mind can readily incorporate post-event information.
To forget is not the same as to repress. 

But the most difficult problem relates to the power of suggestion. Crews
notes with despair the advice given, to a woman led to suspect early
molestation, by the author of an influential and best-selling book in this
area, Repressed Memories: A Journey to Recovery from Sexual Abuse: 'You may
be convinced that your disbelief is a rational questioning of the reality
versus the unreality of your memories, but it is partially a misguided
attempt to repress the memories again.' Given such an approach, how can one
put much faith in the independence and objectivity of therapists asked to
give an opinion on whether repressed memories exist? 

Crews argues that the whole repressed memory controversy is the logical
consequence of the inability of therapists, mainly of a psychoanalytic
persuasion, to accept that the theory of repression is just that, a theory,
still awaiting scientific corroboration. He is no doubt correct, but that
is not the whole story. Many clinicians, including myself, remain sceptical
concerning repressed memories but are only too conscious of our history and
the distasteful fact that, until recently, we paid little attention to the
possibilities of childhood sexual abuse and remained relatively indifferent
to its prevalence, presentation and consequences. While most of us accept
that survivors of CSA recall their trauma with little difficulty, we cannot
completely dismiss the possibility that, for some, the catastrophic nature
of the event is so appalling that they shut out all recollections and in
that sense repress. 

But there is some common ground in the debate. There is, for example,
agreement that false memories can occur, that most people can remember
their abuse and that the only reliable way to distinguish between true and
false memories is by independent external corroboration. Otherwise, the
battle continues. This book is a stylishly written and persuasive summary
of the state of the argument. 

© 1999, LEXIS®-NEXIS®, a division of Reed Elsevier Inc. All Rights Reserved. 


Louis Proyect

(http://www.panix.com/~lnp3/marxism.html)



Reply via email to