N.T. Wright

Jesus’ Resurrection and Christian Origins

Originally published in Gregorianum, 2002, 83/4, 615–635.  Reproduced by 
permission of the author.



Introduction


The question of Jesus’ resurrection continues to haunt the thinking and writing 
of many scholars.  I shall not debate in detail with them here; there are other 
places for that.  I want instead to sketch, in broad strokes, a historical 
argument about what happened three days after Jesus’ crucifixion.


The question divides into four.  First, what did people in the first century, 
both pagans and Jews, hope for?  What did they believe about life after death, 
and particularly about resurrection?  Second, what did the early Christians 
believe on the same subjects?  What did they hope for?  Third, what reasons did 
the early Christians give for their hope and belief, and what did they mean by 
the key word ‘resurrection’ which they used of Jesus? Finally, what can the 
historian say by way of comment on this early Christian claim?


Life after Death in the First Century


Paganism

Homer was hugely important in the world of late antiquity; and in Homer life 
after death is pretty bleak.  Odysseus’s journey to the under world (in Books 
10 and 11 of the Odyssey) hardly encourages readers to suppose that death will 
take them into a better world.  Hades, the abode of the dead, is a place of 
shadows and wraiths, who can just about remember what life was like but not 
much more.  This view persists in popular first-century culture, as witnessed 
by thousands of funerary monuments, tailing off into the shoulder-shrugging 
agnosticism of the well- known inscription: ‘Non fui, fui, non sum, non curo – 
I wasn’t, I was, I am not, I don’t care.’  Within the more serious philosophies 
of the first century, this view, suitably refined, would have been shared by 
many Epicureans at least.1


Plato held out a different possibility, the chance of a blissful after-life at 
least for some.  He even speculated about reincarnation, though this is not 
central to his thought, nor is it stressed in later Platonism.  His ideas come 
through into popular first-century culture not least in the mystery religions.  
Once philosophical speculation began devising alternatives to the Homeric 
viewpoint, other positions emerged; for instance, that of Stoicism, that the 
entire world would be destroyed by fire and be reborn, phoenix-like, only for 
everything to happen again in exactly the same way as before.


There are numerous sub-topics within ancient pagan views of life after death.  
Of particular interest is Euripides’s play Alcestis, where Hercules does battle 
with the god Thanatos and rescues Alcestis from his clutches, bringing her back 
to her sorrowing husband.  The representation of the scene in ancient art may 
have influenced the Christian iconography in which Jesus leads Adam and Eve out 
of Hades.  But the flagrantly mythological character of the whole drama does 
not encourage us to think that either philosophers or ordinary folk really 
believed that Hercules or anyone else could or would rescue people from actual 
death.

Indeed, whenever the question of bodily resurrection is raised in the ancient 
world the answer is negative.  Homer does not imagine that there is a way back; 
Plato does not suppose anyone in their right mind would want one.


There may or may not be various forms of life after death, but the one thing 
there isn’t is resurrection: the word anastasis refers to something that 
everybody knows doesn’t happen.  The classic statement is in Aeschylus’s play 
Eumenides (647-8), in which, during the founding of the Court of the Areopagus, 
Apollo himself declares that when a man has died, and his blood is spilt on the 
ground, there is no resurrection.  The language of resurrection, or something 
like it, was used in Egypt in connection with the very full and developed view 
of the world beyond death.  But this new life was something that had, it was 
believed, already begun, and it did not involve actual bodily return to the 
present world.  Nor was everybody fooled by the idea that the dead were already 
enjoying a full life beyond the grave.  When the eager Egyptians tried to show 
their new ruler Augustus their hoard of wonderful mummies, he replied that he 
wanted to see kings, not corpses.2


What then did people mean when they spoke of ‘hope’, and indeed built temples 
to the goddess Spes, including some in Rome itself?  Very much this-worldly 
futures: peace and security, social stability, crops and harvests, large 
families and good fortune.  The best future, indeed for some the only future, 
was a lasting name and reputation.  Though the importance of the individual is 
hardly a modem invention, as is sometimes supposed, there was in the classical 
world considerable fluidity between one’s own fate and that of one’s family, 
one’s city, and one’s culture.


Some within the ancient pagan world believed in the apotheosis of heroes and 
kings.  The mythological Hercules began as a mortal and was exalted to 
quasi-divinity.  Kings and emperors, from Alexander to the Julio-Claudians and 
beyond, were regularly deified, using various legitimating devices, mostly to 
do with witnessing the departed person’s soul ascending to heaven, perhaps in 
the form of a comet, as with Julius Caesar, or an eagle, as depicted on Titus’s 
Arch.  Ordinary mortals did not expect this treatment, of course.  And Seneca’s 
merry parody of the apotheosis of Claudius, though itself of course written to 
highlight Rome’s good fortune in having Nero as his successor, makes us 
question how many Romans believed that emperors, or at least good ones, were 
now alive and well alongside Jupiter, Apollo and the rest.3  The language 
inquestion did, however, relate to the hope of the ancient world: many 
believed, despite evidence to the contrary, that a strong central ruler would 
guarantee freedom, peace, and future security.


Judaism

When we turn to ancient Judaism the picture is both very similar and very 
different.  The Hebrew Sheol, the place of the dead, is not very different from 
Homer’s Hades.  People are asleep there; they can sometimes be woken up, as 
with Saul and Samuel, but to do so is dangerous, and forbidden.4  That is the 
picture we get from most of the Old Testament.


The Psalms begin to explore ways in which YHWH’s love will be known after 
death.  It is notoriously difficult to date these passages, and they remain 
controversial.  Psalm 73 is perhaps the clearest statement of a post-mortem 
hope.  Unlike Plato, the biblical mentions of a hope beyond the grave are not 
predicated on the existence of an immortal soul which will automatically have a 
future life, but on the love and faithfulness of YHWH in the present, which 
must, the poets suppose, continue into the future.


The Jewish hope burst the bounds of ancient paganism altogether by speaking of 
resurrection.  The supposed Zoroastrian origin of this belief is still argued 
by some but strenuously denied by others, who see the metaphors of Isaiah 26 
and Ezekiel 37, and the earlier hints in Hosea 6, as opening the way for a new 
view, generated by Israel’s own basic beliefs and contingent circumstances, 
which comes to full expression in Daniel chapter 12.  Despite what is often 
supposed, this belief, when it arises, is in paradoxical continuity with the 
ancient Hebrew belief in Sheol.  Unlike Platonists, who preferred a disembodied 
immortality, those who believed in resurrection agreed with the ancient 
Israelites that real life meant embodied life.


The difference is that in the earlier view those in Sheol cannot have it again 
(as in the book of Job, apart from the controversial passage in chapter 19), 
whereas in the resurrection passages they can and will.  It is therefore 
misleading to suggest a steady development through the Old Testament, from ‘no 
future hope’ to ‘a disembodied future hope’ to ‘a fully-blown resurrection 
hope’.  The first and the third stages have more in common with each other — a 
strong belief in the goodness of the present created order and of human life 
within it— than either has with the second.


Post-biblical Judaism offers a range of beliefs about life after death.  
Resurrection is by no means the only option; and, when it is specified, it is 
not a general word for life after death, but a term for one particular belief. 
In fact, resurrection is not simply a form of ‘life after death’; resurrection 
hasn’t happened yet.  People do not pass directly from death to resurrection, 
but go through an interim period, after which the death of the body will be 
reversed in resurrection.  Resurrection does not, then, mean ‘survival’; it is 
not a way of describing the kind of life one might have immediately following 
physical death.  It is not a redescription of death and/or the state which 
results from death. In both paganism and Judaism it refers to the reversal, the 
undoing, the conquest of death and its effects.  That is its whole point.  That 
is what Homer, Plato, Aeschylus and the others denied; and it is what some 
Jews, and all early Christians, affirmed.


Resurrection, in other words, means being given back one’s body, or perhaps God 
creating a new similar body, some time after death.  It is, in fact, life after 
‘life after death’; because where you find a belief in resurrection you also 
find, unsurprisingly, a belief in some kind of intermediate state in between 
death and resurrection.  Various ways of describing this were developed: the 
souls of the righteous, said Wisdom (3.1), were in God’s hand.  Others spoke of 
a quasi-angelic intermediate existence, or of spirits that lived on prior to 
the resurrection. The patriarchs were ‘alive to God’.  The Persian term 
‘Paradise’ was employed, not necessarily for the final destination of 
resurrection, but, sometimes at least (e.g. 1 Enoch 37-70), for the peaceful 
garden where people rested before their new bodily life began.


There is no space here to itemize individual sources, themselves often matters 
of dispute.  I merely sketch the overall shape of Jewish belief.  The spectrum 
runs from those who deny the resurrection to those who insist upon it.  The 
Sadducees deny the world to come altogether, reminding us that resurrection was 
and remained an explicitly political doctrine, about God turning the present 
world and its power structures upside down.  Thus the Pharisees’ belief in the 
resurrection was part of their generally revolutionary ideology: as in Daniel 
and Maccabees, resurrection was an incentive to martyrdom.  I am not convinced 
that the Essenes believed in resurrection; but I do hold that Wisdom of Solomon 
3.7-8 teaches resurrection, a re-embodiment for the righteous whose souls are 
presently in the hand of God, who will be given a new life in which, to the 
consternation of their former persecutors, they will return and rule over 
nations and kingdoms.  Finally, a much more Platonic picture is held by Philo 
of Alexandria, who believed in disembodied bliss for the immortal soul.  This 
belief is shared by Jubilees.


Resurrection is thus one point on the spectrum of Jewish beliefs about life 
after death.  If Christianity had been simply a sect of miscellaneous Jews who 
had followed Jesus or approved his teaching, we might have expected a similar 
spread of views, and the fact that we do not is a major part of our question 
about Christian origins; but that is to run ahead of my story.  The second 
point to note about Jewish belief in resurrection is that, where it did occur, 
it was never a detached belief.  It was always part of a larger picture of what 
God was going to do for the nation and indeed the world.


This is where Isaiah 26 and Ezekiel 37 come into their own.  Though already by 
the first century, perhaps already in Daniel, some were reading them as 
prophecies of a literal resurrection, their context insists that God intends to 
restore Israel as a reaction is not an isolated hope for the individual, as so 
often in the modern west.  It is part of the hope for the nation.  And, as 
often as not, it is part of the hope that God will put the whole world to 
rights, bringing judgment upon the powerful and arrogant, and mercy to the poor 
and downtrodden.  And when resurrection happened, it would therefore happen to 
all God’s people at the same moment.


Resurrection is one point on a larger spectrum; it will happen all at once as 
part of God’s future for Israel and the world; and, third, it was fairly 
unspecific in detail.  The rabbis debate whether God will start with the soul 
and gradually build up to the solid body, or whether, as in Ezekiel, God will 
begin with the bones and add flesh and sinews, finally adding breath as in 
Genesis 2.  In each case, of course, what you end up with is what we would call 
a physical body; but there was no agreement as to whether this body would be 
exactly like the one you had before, or significantly different in some way.  
The Maccabean martyrs taunt their torturers with the promise that God will give 
them back their hands, tongues and so forth, which are presently being 
mutilated.  This is consistent with, and probably indicates, a belief that 
resurrection means a return to a form of life very similar to the present one.  
But there is no unanimity on this; other texts, such as Daniel 12, can be 
interpreted in terms of an astral resurrection, shining like stars.5   The 
belief remains vague and unfocused.


Finally, some at least of those who believed in the resurrection also believed 
in the coming of the Messiah, though the relation between Messiah and 
resurrection is not usually clear.  The Messiah would defeat YHWH’s enemies, 
rebuild or cleanse the Temple, and establish YHWH’s rule in the world.  Belief 
in the coming of a Messiah was obviously political as well as theological, as 
the messianic movements in the period bear witness.  Resurrection and Messiah 
together speak of the time when God will be king and the present rulers 
(Caesar, Herod, the Sadducees) will be deposed.  Together they speak of the 
coming Reign of God.


It was from within one such prophetic and messianic renewal movement that the 
early Christians emerged, saying two things in particular: Jesus was and is the 
Messiah, and this is proved because he has been raised from the dead. But 
before we can look at these claims we must set the early Christian views about 
future hope, including life after death, resurrection, and some wider issues 
like Messiahship, in parallel with Judaism and paganism.


The Early Christian Hope: Modified and Realised

Early Christian views about life after death, clearly belonged within the 
Jewish spectrum, not the pagan one, but were also clearly different.  This 
gives us a fresh purchase on the question, why did they reshape the hope in 
that way?


Almost all early Christians known to us believed that their ultimate hope was 
the resurrection of the body.  There is no spectrum such as in Judaism.  Some 
in Corinth denied the future resurrection (1 Corinthians 15.12), but Paul put 
them straight; they were most likely reverting to pagan views, not opting for 
an over-realized Jewish eschatology.  Two named individuals in 2 Timothy 2.18 
say the resurrection has already happened, but they stand out by their oddity, 
and they too bear witness to the fact that mainstream early Christianity did 
indeed hope for resurrection, even if by the end of the first generation some 
were using that language in a new way, to refer simply to a new present 
identity or spiritual experience — marking the road to the gnostic views of, 
for instance, the Epistle to Rheginos.


This almost complete absence of a spectrum of belief itself demands 
explanation, but before we can offer one we must add two further points.  
First, the early Christian belief in resurrection had a much more precise shape 
and content than anything we find in Judaism.  In early Christianity, obviously 
in Paul but not only there, resurrection will be an act of new creation, 
accomplished by the Holy Spirit, and the body which is to be is already planned 
by God.  This will not be a simple return to the same sort of body as before; 
nor will it be an abandonment of embodiedness in order to enjoy a disembodied 
bliss.  It will involve transformation, the gift of a new body with different 
properties.  This is so engrained in earliest Christianity that it already 
affects teaching on other subjects, such as baptism (Romans 6) and ethics 
(Colossians 3)

.

Where did that idea come from?  Not from any ancient paganism known to us; and 
not, or not straightforwardly, from any ancient Judaism.  The best-known 
feature of resurrection in Daniel 12 is that the righteous will shine like 
stars; that, interestingly, is one thing the early Christians do not say about 
the hope of resurrection, except in one gospel passage (Matthew 13.43) not 
echoed elsewhere.6  The hope of resurrection is thus not only virtually 
universal in early Christianity; it is much more sharply focussed than its 
Jewish equivalent.


What then do the New Testament writers mean when they speak of an inheritance 
waiting for us in heaven?  This has been much misunderstood, with awesome 
results in traditions of thought, prayer, life and art.  The point of such 
passages, as in 1 Peter 1.4, 2 Corinthians 5.1, Philippians 3.20, and so forth, 
is not that one must ‘go to heaven’, as in much-popular imagination, in order 
to enjoy the inheritance there. It is rather that ‘heaven’ is the place where 
God stores up his plans and purposes for the future.  If I tell a friend that 
there is beer in the fridge, that doesn’t mean he has to get into the fridge in 
order to enjoy the beer.  When the early Christians speak of a new body in 
heaven, or an inheritance in heaven, they mean what St John the Divine means in 
Revelation 21: the new identity which at present is kept safe in heaven will be 
brought from heaven to earth at the great moment of renewal.  Yes: the great 
majority of Christian expressions of hope through the middle ages, the 
reformation, and the counter-reformation periods have been misleading. ‘Heaven’ 
is not the Christian’s ultimate destination.  For renewed bodies we need a 
renewed cosmos, including a renewed earth. That is what the New Testament 
promises.


The third way in which early Christian belief about resurrection is 
significantly different from that of second-Temple Judaism is that, 
particularly in Paul, ‘the resurrection’ has split into two. Paul still sees 
‘the resurrection of the dead’ as a single theological event,7 but it takes 
place in two phases: first the Messiah, then at his coming all his people.8  
This too only makes sense within second-Temple Judaism, but it is something no 
second-Temple Jew had said before.  Resurrection had been a single 
all-embracing moment, not a matter of one person being raised ahead of 
everybody else.


These modifications and sharpenings of the Jewish belief demand a historical 
explanation, and we shall come to that presently.  But there were other 
modifications as well.  Those Jews who believed in resurrection developed, as 
we saw, ways of speaking about the interim state of those who had died, ways of 
holding on to the belief that the physically dead had not entirely ceased to 
exist, but that they were still ‘there’ to be raised again on the last day.  
The early Christians, seeking to say the same thing, used some of the same 
language but some different expressions as well.  They spoke of people being 
‘asleep in Christ’.9


Revelation speaks of the souls under the altar who wake up, ask what time it 
is, and are told to go back to sleep again.10  The penitent thief will be with 
Jesus in Paradise — presumably not a final destination, even if we take ‘today’ 
metaphorically.11  Paul speaks of his desire being to ‘depart and be with the 
Messiah, which is far better’.12  The closest the New Testament gets to 
speaking of the dead being in ‘heaven’, even as a temporary resting place, is 
when in Revelation 21 the New Jerusalem, the bride of Christ, comes down to 
earth from heaven, where presumably she has been waiting, in order that the 
wedding can take place.

Finally, the early Christians speak of one major aspect of the Jewish hope as 
already emphatically realised.  Jesus himself was and is the Messiah, and they 
looked for no other.  This deserves much more elaboration than I can give it 
here.13


Jesus had not done what Messiahs were supposed to do.  He had neither won a 
decisive victory over Israel’s political enemies, nor restored the Temple 
(except in the most ambiguous symbolic fashion).  Nor had he brought God’s 
justice and peace to the world; the wolf was not yet lying down with the lamb.  
But the early gospel traditions are already shaped by the belief that Jesus was 
Israel’s Messiah; Paul regularly calls him Christos, and if that term had 
become for him merely a proper name (which I dispute) that only goes to show 
how firmly Jesus’ messianic identity was already established by Paul’s day.  
For Revelation, Jesus is the Lion of the tribe of Judah.  The historian is 
bound to face the question: once Jesus had been crucified, why would anyone say 
that he was Israel’s Messiah?


Nobody said that about Judas the Galilean after his revolt ended in failure in 
AD 6.  Nobody said it of Simon bar-Giora after his death at the end of Titus’s 
triumph in AD 70.  Nobody said it about bar-Kochbar after his defeat and death 
in 135.  On the contrary. Where messianic movements tried to carry on after the 
death of their would-be Messiah, their most important task was to find another 
Messiah.14  The fact that the early Christians did not do that, but continued, 
against all precedent, to regard Jesus himself as Messiah, despite outstanding 
alternative candidates such as the righteous, devout and well-respected James, 
Jesus’ own brother, is evidence that demands an explanation.


As with their beliefs about resurrection, they redefined Messiahship itself, 
and with it their whole view of the problem that Israel and the world faced and 
the solution that they believed God had provided.  They remained at one level a 
classic Jewish messianic movement, owing fierce allegiance to their Messiah and 
claiming Israel and the whole world in his name.  But the mode of that claim, 
and the underlying allegiance itself, were drastically redefined.


The rise of early Christianity, and the shape that it took in two central and 
vital respects, thus presses upon the historian the question for an 
explanation.  The early Christians retained the Jewish belief in resurrection, 
but both modified it and made it more sharp and precise. They retained the 
Jewish belief in a coming Messiah, but redrew it quite drastically around Jesus 
himself.  Why?


Reasons for the Development: From Theology to Story

The answer the early Christians themselves give for these changes, of course, 
is that Jesus of Nazareth was bodily raised from the dead on the third day 
after his crucifixion.  It is Jesus’ own resurrection that has given force and 
new shape to the Christian hope.15  It was, they insist, Jesus’ own 
resurrection which constituted him as Messiah, and, if Messiah, then Lord of 
the world.16  But what exactly did they mean by this, and what brought them to 
such a belief?


We must now come to the third and fourth stages of my argument.  First, we must 
establish, against some rival claims, that they really did intend to say that 
Jesus had been bodily raised; they were not simply using that language to 
describe something else, a different belief about Jesus or a different 
experience they had had.  Second, we must enquire as historians what could have 
caused them to say such a thing.


It is out of the question, for a start, that the disciples were simply 
extrapolating from the teaching of Jesus himself.  One of the many curious 
things about Jesus’ teaching is that though resurrection was a well-known topic 
of debate at the time we only have one short comment of his on the subject, in 
reply to the question from the Sadducees — a comment which is itself 
notoriously cryptic, like some of its companion pieces in the synoptic 
tradition.  Apart from that, there are the short repeated predictions of Jesus’ 
passion and resurrection, which many of course assume are vaticinia ex eventu, 
and two or three other cryptic references.17


These are scarcely enough to suggest that the disciples invented stories of 
Jesus’ resurrection, on the basis of his teaching, after his death.  Other Jews 
had died promising resurrection, the Maccabees being the most obvious example 
(2 Maccabees 7, etc.); their followers regarded them as heroes and martyrs, and 
believed devoutly that they would be raised from the dead; but nobody said they 
had been, for the rather obvious reason that they hadn’t.18  And even if, 
against all probability, we were to suggest that the disciples had indeed 
invented resurrection-stories on the basis of Jesus’ sayings, this would still 
not account for the modifications and new focus they gave to the existing 
Jewish notions of resurrection.


One regular proposal, which has taken various forms, is that though the early 
church used the language of resurrection about Jesus, and eventually wrote down 
stories about how it had happened, this developed originally from something 
else, a different experience or belief. In particular, some have said, Jesus’ 
followers came first to a belief in his exaltation, and they deduced from this, 
either by logic or devotion, that he had been raised from the dead.


This needs a little more unpacking.  Sometimes it has been argued, or more 
often assumed, that the early Christians believed that Jesus had been in some 
sense exalted (though why they believed this remains uncertain) and that they 
either expressed this belief by saying that he had been raised from the dead 
(misleadingly, because there was never what ‘resurrection’ meant in their 
world) or deduced from this that he had in fact been raised from the dead 
(though again why they would make such a deduction, in a world where 
‘resurrection’ was something to do with bodies, and for that matter something 
that would happen to all the righteous at once, is not clear).  At other times 
it has been argued that the disciples came to believe in Jesus’ actual 
divinity, perhaps by experiencing him as a divine presence, and again 
eitherexpressed this by saying he had been raised, or deduced from it the fact 
that he had been raised.  In this case, too, the logic fails at every point 
when we remind ourselves of how these ideas worked within the historical world 
of the first century.19


It is true that Paul can sometimes speak simply of Jesus’ death and exaltation, 
without mentioning the resurrection explicitly, as in the poem of Philippians 
2.6-11 — though it is equally true that in the same letter he can speak 
emphatically of the bodily transformation that Jesus will effect on believers 
still alive at his return.20  And when he sums up the traditional gospel 
announcement in 1 Corinthians 15.21 a summary which must have done justice to 
what Cephas and Apollos said as well, otherwise the Corinthians would have been 
able to challenge him on it, it is clear that the gospel is about an event 
which happened at some interval after Jesus’ death.21


This has not, I think, been sufficiently thought through.  If we assume, as is 
often done, that talking of Jesus’ resurrection is simply a flowery, perhaps 
Jewish, way of talking about him ‘going to heaven when he died’, so that his 
death and his ‘exaltation’ were actually the same thing, and together 
constitute him as divine, where did the notion of an interval come from?


have often heard it said, sometimes by people who should know better, that 
Jesus died and was ‘resurrected to heaven’, but that is precisely not what the 
early Christians said. Raised from the dead, yes; exalted to heaven, yes; but 
resurrection never did mean ‘going to heaven when you die’, and it certainly 
did not mean that when people used it to talk about Jesus.22   No: if the early 
Christians had been merely ‘deducing’ Jesus’ resurrection from some other 
belief about something he had become through dying, the talk of an interval 
between death and resurrection would never have arisen — unless we are to 
postulate yet another cycle of improbable development of tradition, moving from 
exaltation to resurrection to a three-day gap.23  Jews, after all, had 
well-developed ways of talking about martyrs being honoured and respected, and 
they believed that they would be raised in the future.  If the early Christians 
thought Jesus, upon his death, had gone to a special place of honour with God, 
that would have been the obvious language for them to use.


The key questions here are the following: (a) whether Jesus’ death would by 
itself have precipitated the language of exaltation or vindication; (b) if not, 
whether any subsequent experience (other than resurrection itself) would have 
done so; and (c) what reason there is, even if we were to grant that people had 
begun to speak of Jesus being exalted, being glorified, or even perhaps being 
seen as divine, to suppose that they would deduce from that that he had been 
raised from the dead?  The answers are all obviously negative.  One can 
understand why, if they believed that Jesus had indeed been raised from the 
dead, they came to believe, after he had ceased to appear to them, that he had 
now been exalted to heaven.  But when you think about the options open to 
first-century Jews faced with a dead Messiah, there is simply no route in the 
opposite direction.


Some theologians have brought together Jesus’ resurrection and the early 
disciples’ recognition of his divinity in a way which seems to me to 
short-circuit any process that we can reasonably suppose to have been 
historical.  Even if Peter and the rest, two or three days after Jesus’ 
crucifixion, had somehow become convinced that he was the second person of the 
Trinity — an idea which takes some imagination — there is no reason to suppose 
that they would have deduced from this that God ‘must have’ raised him from the 
dead.  Apotheosis along the lines of Hercules, Alexander and the Caesars was of 
course unknown in Judaism, but even if that was the route they had gone there 
is no reason to suppose that they would have added resurrection to the mix.  
No: I believe we must firmly uncouple the historical discussion of Jesus’ 
resurrection from the historical discussion of the rise of an early, high 
Christology (in which I also believe); or, at least, we must insist that the 
only credible line of explanation runs from resurrection to Christology (about 
which more anon), rather than in the opposite direction.


In any case, with all of these accounts which suppose that the disciples 
deduced Jesus’ resurrection from something else, or expressed some other belief 
in the (misleading) fashion of ‘he’s been raised from the dead’, we are still 
faced with the major problem: why would ‘resurrection’ itself, and the hope for 
a Messiah, have been so drastically adjusted as we find them to have been in 
early Christianity?


We are forced to conclude that when the early Christians said that Jesus had 
been raised from the dead, and gave that as their reason for reshaping their 
beliefs about resurrection itself on the one hand and Messiahship on the other, 
they were using the language in its normal sense.  That which Aeschylus said 
couldn’t happen to anyone, and Daniel said would, to all God’s people at once, 
had happened to Jesus, all by himself.  That was what they intended to say.  
And this brings us, at last, to the resurrection narratives themselves.


The first point to make here is vital.  I have argued that the early Christians 
looked forward to a resurrection which was not a mere resuscitation, nor yet 
the abandonment of the body and the liberation of the soul, but a 
transformation, a new type of body living within a new type of world.  This 
belief is embroidered with biblical motifs, articulated in rich theology.  Yet 
in the gospel narratives we find a story, told from different angles of course, 
without such embroidering and theology — told indeed in restrained, largely 
unadorned prose.  Yet the story is precisely of a single body neither 
abandoned, nor merely resuscitated, but transformed; and this, though itself 
totally unexpected, could give rise to exactly that developed view of which I 
have spoken.  The Easter narratives, in other words, appear to offer an answer 
to why the early Christian hope and life took the form and shape they did.


Were the four gospels, then, all derived from this developed theology?  Are 
they all later narratival adaptations of a doctrinal and exegetical basis, from 
which of course all traces of dogma and exegesis have, in each case, been 
carefully extracted?  Hardly.  It is far easier to say that the stories, or 
something like them, came first, and that Paul and the other later theologians 
have reflected deeply upon them, have indeed reshaped and rethought one branch 
of mainstream Jewish theology around them, but have not substantially modified 
them.


A few more remarks about the narratives themselves.  Matthew’s story is often 
seen as anti-Jewish apologetic — not surprisingly, because he himself tells us 
that he is countering a story current among non-Christian Jews of his day.  But 
even if Matthew does represent a later polemic, the debate itself — that some 
say Jesus’ body was stolen, and others say it wasn’t — bears witness to my more 
fundamental point, that in the first century ‘resurrection’ wasn’t about 
exaltation, spiritual presence, a sense of forgiveness, or divinization; it was 
about bodies and tombs.  If someone had been able to say ‘oh, don’t you 
understand?  When I say “resurrection”, all I mean is that Jesus is in heaven 
and he is my Lord, that I’ve had a new sense of God’s love and forgiveness,’ 
the dangerous debate about tombs, guards, angels and bodies could have been 
abandoned with a sigh of relief all round.24


Second, a word about Mark.  When Mark says that the women ‘said nothing to 
anyone, because they were afraid,’ he does not mean they never said anything to 
anyone.  I do not think, in any case, that Mark finished his gospel at chapter 
16 verse 8.1 think he wrote more, which is now lost.  But I think his emphatic 
denial that the women said anything to anyone is meant to counter the charge, 
actual or possible, that if the women really had seen something remarkable — an 
empty tomb, a rolled-away stone, an angel — they would have been bound to tell 
everyone they met.  This they had not done; so (the charge would run) maybe 
they had not seen anything much after all?  Certainly not, replies Mark: the 
reason they said nothing to anyone (until, we presume, they got to the 
disciples) is because they were scared stiff.


Third, a word about Luke and John.  They tell, of course, much fuller stories 
than Matthew and Mark, and it is they who are normally accused of having 
developed, or invented, these stories to combat the danger of docetic views 
within the early church, beliefs that Jesus in his risen body wasn’t really a 
physical human being, but only seemed to be.  Leave aside the fact that that is 
not what mainstream docetism wanted to say anyway — it was a belief about 
Jesus’ pre-crucifixion humanity more than about his risen body — and 
concentrate on what Luke and John actually say.  Yes, they have him eating 
food.  Yes, he invites them to touch him, to inspect him, to make sure he is a 
real human being.  But these are the same accounts, in the same passages, which 
have Jesus appearing and disappearing, sometimes through locked doors.


If Luke or John wanted to invent anti-docetic, no-nonsense real-body stories, 
they surely could have done better than this.  No: it really does look as if 
they are telling, with continuing bewilderment, stories which, though 
astonishing at the time as they still are, provided the basis we are seeking 
for the transformed belief about resurrection we have outlined earlier: stories 
about Jesus’ body being neither abandoned (as though he had simply ‘gone to 
heaven’ and was now a ‘spiritual’, ‘non-bodily’ presence) nor merely 
resuscitated, like Lazarus, and like (perhaps) the martyrs expected to be, but 
transformed, so that, though in all sorts of ways still ‘bodily’, and certainly 
so as to leave an empty tomb behind him, his body was now significantly 
different, with new properties, in a way that nothing in the Jewish tradition 
had prepared him or his followers for.  Indeed, the one new property which you 
would have expected them to include, had they been making these stories up on 
the basis of scripture, they do not.  In none of the accounts is there the 
slightest suggestion that Jesus’ body was shining like a star.


I suggest, in fact, that the gospel stories themselves, though no doubt written 
down a good deal later than Paul, go back with minimal editorial addition to 
the very early stories told by the first disciples in the earliest days of 
Christianity.  They are not the later narratival adaptation of early Christian 
theology; they are its foundation.


This does not mean, of course, that they are photographic descriptions of ‘what 
happened’.  No historical narrative is ever quite that.  But they challenge 
today’s historian, as they challenged their first hearers, either to accept 
them or to come up with a better explanation for why Christianity began and why 
it took the shape it did.


>From Story to Event

This brings us, finally, to our fourth question.  What can the historian say 
that will account for the early Christians’ claim that Jesus of Nazareth had 
been raised from the dead, the explanation they themselves offer for their 
drastic modification of the Jewish hope?


There has been no shortage of hypotheses designed to explain why the early 
Christians really did believe that Jesus really had been raised from the dead.  
These come in many shapes and sizes, but most of them feature one of three 
types of explanation.  (1) Jesus did not really die; he somehow survived.  (2) 
The tomb was empty, but nothing else happened.  (3) The disciples had visions 
of Jesus, but without there being an empty tomb.


(1) The first can be disposed of swiftly.  Roman soldiers knew how to kill 
people especially rebel kings.  First-century Jews knew the difference between 
a survivor and someone newly alive.


(2) The second is only a little more complicated.  Faced with an empty tomb, 
but with no other evidence, the disciples would have known the answer; the body 
had been stolen by someone.  These things happened.  They were not expecting 
Jesus to rise again; by itself, an empty tomb would prove as little to them as 
it would to us.


(3) Visions were frequent and well known — including visions of someone 
recently dead.  We did not have to wait for modem medicine, psychology and 
pastoral records to tell us that these things happen.  Faced with Peter 
knocking on the door when they thought he was about to be killed, the praying 
church assumed he had died and was paying them a post-mortem visit; ‘it must be 
his angel’, they said.25   Even lifelike visions would not prevent people 
conducting a funeral, continuing to mourn, and venerating the tomb.


To cut a long story very short: to explain why the early Christians really did 
believe that Jesus really had been raised from the dead, we must postulate 
three things: Jesus really had been dead; the tomb really was empty, and it 
really was his tomb; they really did see, meet and talk with a figure who was 
not only demonstrably the crucified Jesus but who seemed to be in some ways 
different — though not in the ways one would have imagined from reading Isaiah, 
Ezekiel or Daniel.


Can we go beyond this?  What then can and must be said?


To move any further back, from the empty tomb and the visions of a previously 
dead Jesus, is notoriously difficult, even when we have become quite clear what 
the early church really meant by those stories.  There are a couple of related 
difficulties which must be cleared out of the way.


First, there is a hare-and-tortoise puzzle currently vexing cautious-minded 
historians.  I propose we take a tough line with it and simply insist on common 
sense.  All writing, all history, all biography, is someone’s ‘construction’ of 
reality.  This leads many to say, again and again, that all we can know is 
‘Matthew’s construction of Christian origins,’ ‘Mark’s view of Easter,’ and so 
on.  There is a grain of truth in this.  But the fact that the historian has a 
point of view does not mean that nothing happened.  History proceeds, not just 
by deduction from each individual piece of evidence, but by abduction, by 
inference to the best explanation.  We must not be browbeaten by an 
over-cautious epistemology.  This is where the hare must stride confidently 
past the tortoise, ignoring the protests which say all he can ever do is halve 
the distance between them.


Second, much more seriously, there is the problem I associate with Hans Frei 
and others.26  If we attempt to argue for the historical truth of the 
resurrection on standard historical grounds, have we not allowed historical 
method, perhaps including its hidden Enlightenment roots, to become lord, to 
set the bounds of what we know, rather than allowing God himself, Jesus 
himself, and indeed the resurrection itself, to establish not only what we know 
but how we can know it?  This is I think a proper question (though it is not 
without echoes, not least in the Yale school of which Frei was a part, of the 
hare-and-tortoise problem itself), and we must face it directly.27


The problem arises, I think, not least from the fact that the events concerning 
Jesus, and particularly his resurrection, have often been seen, not least 
within a systematic theology that has lost contact with historical scholarship, 
as direct evidence about the divinity of Jesus, or, to put it the other way, 
about the incarnation of the second person of the Trinity.  This then poses the 
problem: how can the historian claim to get to that point, the point which 
should only be accessible to Christian faith, by the apparently ‘neutral’, even 
maybe would-be ‘objective’, route of historical enquiry?


The answer is that both halves of the equation are misconceived.  On the one 
hand, the resurrection did not for the first Christians, and does not today, 
‘prove’ that Jesus was and/or is ‘divine’.  If one of the brigands crucified 
alongside Jesus had been found to be alive again three days later, people would 
have said the world was a very odd place, but nobody would have said he was the 
second person of the Trinity.  If one of the Maccabean martyrs, who died 
believing that God would raise them from the dead, had been found to be alive 
again a few days later, everyone would have been shocked, including the 
resurrected persons themselves; this was supposed to be something that happened 
to all the righteous together, not to one person ahead of the rest.  But nobody 
would have imagined that this meant he or she was in any sense divine.  And, 
supposing such a thing could have happened, it would in principle be open to 
historical investigation just like any other reported event.


On the other hand, the Frei school have overstated their case about the nature 
of historical investigation.  By no means all historians today believe that 
they are ‘objective’ or ‘neutral’, attaining fixed and unalterable results by 
supposedly scientific means.  On the contrary,  I myself stand in a line of 
historians who have explicitly renounced that pseudo-objectivity and have 
instead argued for a form of ‘critical realism’ in which the interaction 
between the historian and the subject matter is fully allowed for.28


In fact, in this case, the evidence presents us with exactly the sort of result 
that Christian theologians ought to be happy with.  I would not pretend to have 
found an argument that would force a sceptic to admit that Jesus ‘must have’ 
been raised from the dead.  It is always open to anyone to say, at least, ‘I 
can’t think of a better explanation, but I know there must be one, because I 
intend to hold to my presupposition that dead people don’t rise.’  Cautious 
agnosticism is always an option.  What historical investigation can do, and in 
this case I believe must do, is to clear away the overgrown thickets of 
misunderstanding, misreading, sheer bad history, and sometimes willful 
obfuscation, in order that the main texts can be allowed to say what they are 
saying and the main questions may stand out in their stark simplicity.


Historical investigation, I propose, brings us to the point where we must say 
that the tomb previously housing a thoroughly dead Jesus was empty, and that 
his followers saw and met someone they were convinced was this same Jesus, 
bodily alive though in a new, transformed fashion.  The empty tomb on the one 
hand and the convincing appearances of Jesus on the other are the two 
conclusions the historian must draw.  I do not think that history can force us 
to draw any particular further deductions beyond these two phenomena; the 
conclusion the disciples drew is there for the taking, but it is open to us, as 
it was to them, to remain cautious.  Thomas waited a week before believing what 
he had been told. On Matthew’s mountain, some had their doubts.


However, the elegance and simplicity of explaining the two outstanding 
phenomena, the empty tomb and the visions, by means of one another, ought to be 
obvious.  Were it not for the astounding, and world-view-challenging, claim 
that is thereby made, I think everyone would long since have concluded that 
this was the correct historical result.  If some other account explained the 
rise of Christianity as naturally, completely and satisfyingly as does the 
early Christians’ belief, while leaving normal worldviews intact, it would be 
accepted without demur.


That, I believe, is the result of the investigation I have conducted.  There 
are many other things to say about Jesus’ resurrection.  But, as far as I am 
concerned, the historian may and must say that all other explanations for why 
Christianity arose, and why it took the shape it did, are far less convincing 
as historical explanations than the one the early Christians themselves offer: 
that Jesus really did rise from the dead on Easter morning, leaving an empty 
tomb behind him.  The origins of Christianity, the reason why this new movement 
came into being and took the unexpected form it did, and particularly the 
strange mutations it produced within the Jewish hope for resurrection and the 
Jewish hope for a Messiah, are best explained by saying that something 
happened, two or three days after Jesus’ death, for which the accounts in the 
four gospels are the least inadequate expression we have.


Of course, there are several reasons why people may not want, and often refuse, 
to believe this.  But the historian must weigh, as well, the alternative 
accounts they themselves offer.  And, to date, none of them have anything like 
the explanatory power of the simple, but utterly challenging, Christian one.  
The historian’s task is not to force people to believe.  It is to make it clear 
that the sort of reasoning historians characteristically employ — inference to 
the best explanation, tested rigorously in terms of the explanatory power of 
the hypothesis thus generated — points strongly towards the bodily resurrection 
of Jesus; and to make clear, too, that from that point on the historian alone 
cannot help.  When you’re dealing with worldviews, every community and every 
person must make their choices in the dark, even if there is a persistent 
rumour of light around the next corner.

-----------------------------------------------

* This is the McCarthy lecture 2002, delivered on March 13,2002, in the Faculty 
of theology of the Gregorian University.

-- 
-- 
Centroids: The Center of the Radical Centrist Community 
<RadicalCentrism@googlegroups.com>
Google Group: http://groups.google.com/group/RadicalCentrism
Radical Centrism website and blog: http://RadicalCentrism.org

--- 
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
"Centroids: The Center of the Radical Centrist Community" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email 
to radicalcentrism+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
For more options, visit https://groups.google.com/d/optout.

Reply via email to