Dear Felix, Ted, Bryan, and Dymitri,

I have some differences of opinion about the nature of money, its meaning 
today, and what it says about digital art, etc. 

First, money is primarily a social construct, resting on a whole host of 
institutions and arrangements. These inevitably change depending on time and 
circumstance. The Austrian school is certainly over-simple in its notion that 
money rests on something unchangeable with definite use, such as gold. So is 
the  simple Marxian view  that the value of money is somehow conferred by the 
socially necessary labor time to produce it. (Marx introduced the concept of 
labor time to argue that workers under capitalism were being systematically 
robbed, not as some sort of essential fact.) 

After all, though it takes more than a penny’s worth of effort to make a penny, 
it takes about the same amount effort to make a thousand-dollar bill as a 
ten-dollar bill. The effort it can take to have x million dollars in stocks or 
in a bank account may not be appreciably different from having 2x million or 
.5x million. There’s a lot of looseness.

If, as I have argued elsewhere, we increasingly live in an economy based on the 
scarcity and desirability of (human) attention, then one of the values of 
having a lot of money and somehow making the fact known is that our learned 
fascination with money itself leads the flaunters of it to get additional 
attention, which sometimes can be further monetized. On the other hand, at 
times, having very little money can also be a way to get attention, which can 
sometimes  also be monetized. 

On to art. Art can get attention for its maker or possessor in a variety of 
ways: being beautiful, being novel, being revelatory, etc. The difference 
between a famous Picasso painting and a very good copy of it lies ultimately in 
the fact that Picasso actually worked on one but not the other. Picasso’s 
paintings made him Picasso, but being Picasso, anything he worked on took on 
his aura. Of course, now that he’s dead, authenticating which is which is a 
complicated social process, with margins of error. Only when the art world—or 
the relevant part of it—is more or less in agreement can we tell real from 
fake, and thus help determine the apparent worth to collectors. The fact that 
the catalogue raisonnée for Picasso has only a limited number of works, while 
the number potential collectors keeps climbing, tends to increase the value of 
the authenticated ones. If you have the money you might buy it just to bask in 
his aura, or to admire it, or to get attention for yourself, or—or perhaps 
also—as an investment more likely to go up in value than down. It can be 
somewhat like buying a house that you expect to relish living in as well as 
having as a good investment. 

In recent decades, digital art has opened up new possibilities for artists, but 
there is no sense of the artist’s actually having bodily touched any particular 
avatar. There are still possibilities of making money, somewhat similar to 
portions of Christo’s various gates or curtains being cut into small fabric 
pieces and then sold. Which in turn is not that different from the added value 
Abraham Lincoln’s actual pocket watch would have over another 
identical-appearing watch made by the same maker. A slightly older era of 
digital art might make something like the original CD-Rom available for 
collectors. But obviously something completely digital that nonetheless could 
carry the aura of the artist somehow would be very appealing to the community 
of such artists and their admirers and would-be collectors. Hence NFT’s. 

Just as the very first significant Italian Renaissance oil painting  might 
carry special meaning and hence value by being first, it should not be too 
surprising that the first significant piece of digital art ever sold as an NFT 
would carry special value. So the price may not be outrageous. 

However, even though it can be authenticated as long as the computer train used 
to record the unique attribution survives, the value of the authentication is 
seemingly less than say  the signature on the painting or the individuality of 
the particular painter’s brushstroke. For the ten-thousandth digital art work 
the specialness of being a true NFT most surely will have diminished. The aura 
is just too faint. 

One can surely argue that there are far too many artists, entertainers and what 
are now simply called “creators,” and that most of their work adds too little 
to our lives or culture beyond banality. Digital art mostly adds to that 
oversupply, I’d suppose. But how can greatness emerge except from a sea of 
mediocrity? We may not want the sea but we should want the greatness. In fact 
we very much need it. 

We should wish for other ways to support great and potentially great art than 
sales to collectors who may or may not have any feeling for what they are 
buying. We perhaps should also want a way to preserve the aura, the sense of 
connection in witnessing art that connects us to the actual artist. 

Or is that a silly wish? A poem read on a computer screen can bring the poet to 
life in one’s own mind. We don’t need to see the handwriting and feel the 
original paper. A Bach suite does not need Bach’s notation either; one can just 
listen—again and again. Visual artists have traditionally prospered by selling 
individual works or small editions. Perhaps digital visual artists are 
following the wrong tradition; perhaps they are authors more than painters.

Best,
Michael

> On Mar 13, 2021, at 4:07 PM, Felix Stalder <fe...@openflows.com> wrote:
> 
> 

#  distributed via <nettime>: no commercial use without permission
#  <nettime>  is a moderated mailing list for net criticism,
#  collaborative text filtering and cultural politics of the nets
#  more info: http://mx.kein.org/mailman/listinfo/nettime-l
#  archive: http://www.nettime.org contact: nett...@kein.org
#  @nettime_bot tweets mail w/ sender unless #ANON is in Subject:

Reply via email to