I appreciate Chip’s concerns, but I wonder how far they can go.  
A cafeteria at a government-run institution decides to offer kosher options, 
because there happen to be quite a few observant Jewish patrons or employees 
who eat there.  The decision is a local one, made by the local manager, without 
any overarching government policy.  Should that be rejected because we can’t 
have complete confidence that the government would likewise offer halal meals 
if at some point some similar institution ends up having quite a few observant 
Muslim patrons or employees?

               Or say that a school in a heavily Jewish area closes for Rosh 
Hashanah and Yom Kippur.  Should that be found unconstitutional because we 
can’t have complete confidence that a different school in the same district (or 
for that matter, a whole different school district) would do the same for 
Muslim holidays in heavily Muslim areas?

               Or say that a government employer accommodates an employee’s 
religious concerns, even beyond what is required by Title VII.  Say, for 
instance, that there is a more de minimis burden for the employer in exempting 
an employee from, say, handling alcohol, or in allowing the employee three 
weeks off to go on a pilgrimage to Mecca.  Should that be found 
unconstitutional because we can’t have complete confidence that the government 
employer would similarly accommodate other religious objectors who have 
similarly burdensome accommodation requests?

               I would think the answer to all these questions is “no,” 
especially when the accommodation don’t require the government to decide who 
belongs to a particular religion and who doesn’t.  (The Mecca pilgrimage / 
alcohol handling example may actually be harder in this respect, but the first 
two, and the single-sex hours example, don’t pose this problem.)  Requiring 
executive agencies that deal with customer and employee needs to accommodate 
through general rule, or not at all, would lead to many fewer accommodations.   
And I don’t think the single-sex swimming hours situation is any different.

And the concern about discrimination, I take it, would usually be dealt with by 
offering later applicants an opportunity to demand equal treatment with the 
applicants whose objections were granted (enforceable with a lawsuit and an 
injunction if necessary), assuming that the accommodation is indeed comparably 
inexpensive.  In Kiryas Joel, which involved a special statute, such a claim 
might not have been easily available.  But when it comes to executive action, 
the notion that courts can compel the government to treat employees and patrons 
equally, and to give benefits to similarly situated people without regard to 
religion, seems pretty familiar.

               Eugene

Chip Lupu writes:

2.  The Kiryas Joel problem is not about third party harms; it's about 
sectarian discrimination.  Would any other religious minority in NYC (Muslims, 
for example) be able to get women only pool hours in their neighborhood?  I 
understand there may be problems of proof if they have never tried, and the 
case may turn on the role of the City in tolerating a sex-based policy, in this 
neighborhood, that the City would not tolerate elsewhere.  But there are 
questions here, to which Alan Brownstein alluded when he asked if this were 
Lukumi reversed -- an intentionally sect-based benefit, not available to others.

_______________________________________________
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Reply via email to