Re: Scalia's Originalism

2003-08-01 Thread Jonathan Miller
I have not followed the earlier strand of this discussion, but your
reading of the Supremacy Clause is hardly dictated by its language --
though it has support in obiter dicta in Reid v. Covert.  The clause may
easily be read as placing treaties on the same level as the Constitution
so long as they are enacted using the process that the Constitution
indicates.  While hardly the traditional U.S. approach, it is not clear
from the text that the U.S. cannot ratify a treaty that gives an
international human rights treaty a status equal to the Constitution and
that establishes an international body as the authoritative interpreter of
the international instrument.  Given that public international law was
often viewed in natural law terms in the 18th century, it might even be
possible to argue that the Framers intended the U.S. to be able to enter
into international agreements that would not be limited by the
Constitution.  -- It would be an interesting area for research.

Jonathan Miller
Professor of Law
Southwestern University School of Law


 I know Prof. Martin thinks the Constitution has some status as a
 treaty.  I do not.  Federalist nos. 5 and 75 provide no evidence to the
 contrary.  Nor does Ware v. Hylton bear on the issue he raises; it had to
 do with the supremacy of the Treaty of Paris (1783) over a law of
Virginia.

 Scalia is quite right to disdain rulings of the European Court of Human
 Rights as relevant to American constitutional questions.  Article VI
 identifies three sources of supreme law: the Constitution, acts of
 Congress, and treaties.  No treaty to which the U.S. is a signatory
obliges
 our judges, state or federal, to pay the least bit of attention to the
 rulings of the ECHR (thank goodness).  Nor does customary international
 law have any bearing on the laws by which Americans govern themselves.

 Scalia's federalism--I have in mind those cases where the five
 conservative justices band together to defend sovereign immunity or
 tendentious readings of the Tenth Amendment or limits on the commerce
 power--is lousy originalism precisely because it forgets that the
 Constitution is not a treaty among the states, and because it rests on an
 ahistorical view of the proper reach of judicial review.

 Matt
 ***
 Matthew J. Franck
 Professor and Chairman
 Department of Political Science
 Radford University
 P.O. Box 6945
 Radford, VA  24142-6945
 phone 540-831-5854
 fax 540-831-6075
 e-mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 ***
 At 01:23 PM 8/1/2003 -0400, you wrote:
 Prof. Franck writes in relevant part:
 
 Scalia is a good originalist in Lawrence, and a lousy one when it comes
to
 federalism and other Loch Ness monsters of the Constitution.
 
 Comment:  It is not so clear to me that Scalia is a good originalist
in
 Lawrence.  He fails to recognize that the Eur.Ct.H.R. cases cited in the
 Court's opinion reflect customary international legal obligations with
 which the 14th Amendment's due process clause must be construed because
of
 the Constitution's status as a treaty --something which both Federalist
 and Anti-Federalist recognized.  See Federalist No. 5; Anti-Federalist
No.
 75. Customary international law is evolving -- also something that the
 Founding Fathers recognized. See Ware v. Hylton (1796). Good originalism
 recognize that the Constitution's provisions (viz., due process clause)
 must be construed in conformity with this evolving customary
international
 law.  Scalia misconstrues the constitutiona! l relevance of the
 Eur.Ct.H.R. cases by indicating that they are merely foreign law -- not
 evidence of the U.S.' customary international legal obligations.  This
is
 particularly contrary to originalism because the Founders specifically
saw
 European customary international law as binding on the U.S.
 
 By the way, how is Scalia's federalism lousy?
 
 Francisco Forrest Martin




-
This message was sent using Endymion MailMan.
http://www.endymion.com/products/mailman/


Re: Scalia's Originalism

2003-08-01 Thread Mark Graber
Two sets of thoughts in different directions.

1.  As I have no doubt stated before, I am inclined to think that the
originalist case for Dred Scott is as good as the originalist case
against (see my piece in Con Comm).  Part of the problem is that the
framers were not thinking about the specific issues in 1787.  A greater
part of the problem is that they were not thinking explicitly about
expansion in 1787 (Sandy Levinson is good on this one).  Another part of
the problem, noted in my never finished book project, is that the
framers were not thinking in the legal terms presupposed by originalism.
 Whatever, a lot of good scholarship done by historians, political
scientists and lawyers suggests that the history of due process and
slavery is more complicated then the simple New Deal account that this
was all nonsense.

2.  I think of myself (and friends such as Howard Gillman and Rogers
Smith) as good historians for political scientists.  On the other hand,
I very much doubt my history would meet the highest professional
standards (hope by combining a little history and political science to
say something of value).  So all of us might benefit from a little more
modesty when walking outside of our areas of expertise.  In this vein,
one of the main problems with originalism may be that the persons who do
originalism are amateurs who may simply select the most political
correct historian who shares their viewpoint, rather than engage in
serious historical analysis.

Mark A. Graber

 [EMAIL PROTECTED] 08/01/03 17:27 PM 
Professor Franck wrote:

The trouble with lawyers, I often think, is that they all went to law
school. And the trouble with law schools is that their permanent
population consists of law professors.  He then proceeded to attack the
analysis of Stephen Henderson's article on the Texas case, noting that
he relied on three law professors including me.

Franck wrote:  Henderson relies on the views of three law professors
for this attempt to associate Scalia with Taney's defense of slavery:
Lea Vandervelde of the University of Iowa, Paul Finkelman of the
University of Tulsa, and Kermit Roosevelt of the University of
Pennsylvania. Henderson found only one dissenter from this
characterization, and he wasn't at a law school   Todd Gaziano of the
Heritage Foundation.

Franck then asserts:  Taney's Dred Scott opinion was a mockery of the
text, of the Framers' intent, of the history of American beliefs on
race, and of the relevant precedents. Scalia, by contrast, got them all
right in the recent sodomy case.

Since I am a law professor who went to graduate school (in history),
rather than law school, I might start by suggesting that the trouble
with political science departments is that they are filled with people
who have political science degrees and think they know something about
history.  (However with deference to Mark Graber I will not make such a
point.)

There is a strong argument that the Framers' intent was precisely as
Taney saw it: to protect slavery and preserve it. That is why it is the
only type of private property and the only social institution in the
Constitution that gets special protection and extra political power in
Congress.  Taney's decision is far from being a mockery of the text, at
least on the issue of slavery and its special place in the Constitution.
On the contrary, does Prof. Franck really believe that the framers, like
Charles Pinckney, Charles Coteswoth Pinckney, Pierce Butler, as well as
the ratification conventions in Md., Va., N.C., S.C. and Ga. believed
that they were entering a Union in which they free blacks would be
considered full citizens and in which slavery would be threatened and
hemmed in.  The Northwest Ordinance can be read a limiting slavery, but
it is also plausible to read it as an agreement that slaveowners are
free to enter all other territories; moreover, under the NWO it the So!
 uth would have had the expansion potential as the North; the Missouri
Compromise, at issue in Dred Scott, gave  huge advantage to the North
and virtually ended the potential for southern growth.  It seems
unlikely that anyone of the southern delegates or ratifiers intended
this.

I agree with Prof. Franck that Taney's analysis of the territories
clause of Art. IV was a mockery of the text. I don't see how he can,
with a straight face, make the same argument about Taney's 5th Amendment
analysis or his overarching analysis that slavery was protocted by the
Constitution. It the self-serving spirit of this list serve, I offer my
own book, SLAVERY AND THE FOUNDERS: RACE AND LIBERTY IN THE AGE OF
JEFFERSON (2nd ed., 2001) in support of the proslavery intentions of the
framers and of the text they wrote.


--
Paul Finkelman
Chapman Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Tulsa College of Law
3120 East 4th Place
Tulsa, OK   74104-3189

918-631-3706 (office)
918-631-2194 (fax)

[EMAIL PROTECTED]


Re: Scalia's Originalism

2003-08-01 Thread Robert Justin Lipkin
  As a non-historian and a non-political scientist, let me asks the following questions: (1) Does originalism presuppose the Framers held one determinate view regarding constitutional meaning? Does it permit the Framers' holding several different views? (2) How does one establish such either view? (3) How do historians (and political scientists) deal with the problem of ascertaining "collective intent," a problem that Dworkin and more recently George Fletcher, as well as many others have emphasized? (2) Do those supporting original intent or original understanding appreciate the enormous commitments to differing philosophies of mind involved in either theory? (4) How do we ascertain the intent---subjective or objective---of a particular Framer? (5) How do we ascertain the public meaning of a critical political or legal term even in contemporary society let alone in the past? and (6) To what are we referring when we make claims that the original intent or understanding of a constitutional provision is X? (7) What evidentiary techniques are required to substantiate such claims? Apologies if some of these questions overlap. 

Bobby Lipkin
Widener University School of Law
Delaware


University of Wisconsin / Milwaukee Political Science Department has opening in public law / judicial politics

2003-08-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Title: Message





  
  -Original Message-From: Sara C. Benesh 
  [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] Sent: Thursday, July 31, 2003 12:02 
  PMTo: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  . . .
  
  
  The University of WisconsinMilwaukee 
   
  Assistant Professor: Public Law/Judicial 
  Politics
  
  The Department of Political Science, 
  pending budgetary approval, invites applications for an anticipated tenure 
  track position at the rank of Assistant Professor in public law/judicial 
  politics with a starting 
  date of August 2004. We seek a scholar engaged in 
  significant research in any area of the subfield. Primary teaching 
  responsibilities will be constitutional law and other courses in the law 
  studies option of the political science major, including law and society and 
  judicial process. We are open to a wide range of additional graduate and 
  undergraduate teaching interests within and beyond public law including 
  methodology. The teaching load is two courses per semester and the salary is 
  competitive with peer institutions and commensurate with experience. A Ph.D. 
  in political science and evidence of excellence in research and teaching is 
  required. 
  
  The application deadline is October 20, 
  2003. Please send your 
  application, including a vita, three letters of reference, a brief writing 
  sample, and summary evidence of teaching competence (by U.S. mail) to 
  Professor Howard Handelman, Chair, Department of Political Science, P.O. Box 
  413, University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee, Milwaukee, WI 53201. UWMilwaukee is 
  an affirmative action, equal employment opportunity employer.
  
  Sara C. Benesh
  Assistant Professor  Director of 
  Undergraduate Studies
  Department of Political Science
  P.O. Box 413
  Milwaukee, WI 53201
  414.229.6720 voice
  414.229.5021 fax
  [EMAIL PROTECTED] email
  http://www.uwm.edu/~sbenesh 
  web
  


Dred Scott (was Scalia's Originalism)

2003-08-01 Thread Matthew J. Franck

Oh, dear. It seems my playful gibe about law
professors didn't go over so well, at least with Paul Finkelman, though
he seems to lend it credence by noting what I had forgotten when writing
my NRO piece--his historian's credentials--thereby distancing himself
from his law school colleagues, who are, it appears (to paraphrase
Kipling), lesser breeds without the history. But then
he thinks the same of political scientists (about which he is quite right
in most cases). But conlawprof is not the place to engage in a
disciplinary pissing match, so I will forebear to tender my own
credentials. Instead let's cut to the matter at hand, about which
even a cat can look at a king.
I made three claims about Dred Scott that are relevant here. (I'll
leave aside the fourth, regarding Taney's treatment of the Declaration of
Independence, since Prof. Finkelman did not contest it, though I expect
he would.)
First, I said, Taney
was wrong, as a
matter of original understanding, to deny that free blacks could be
considered citizens of the United States. Prof. Finkelman
asks whether I really believe that various southerners at the
time of ratification believed that they were entering a
Union in which the free blacks would be considered full citizens and in
which slavery would be threatened and hemmed in. The question
is not what they believed. The question is what the Constitution
permits and prohibits. If they didn't see that it permits the
treatment of free blacks as citizens, and the hemming in of slavery, they
weren't paying attention. Congress could, for instance--but did
not--permit the naturalization of nonwhite immigrants in its first
naturalization statutes. Free blacks who were not free immigrants
but emancipated or born free in the U.S. were considered citizens by a
number of states, and inasmuch as the Constitution was silent on what did
or did not make someone born here a citizen, but permitted suits between
citizens of different states in Article III, Taney was wrong
to address the irrelevant question of whether free blacks were or could
be citizens of the U.S. (an interesting move toward nationalization by a
supposed states' rights man). It's a familiar judicial gambit: ask
the wrong question and give the answer you like.
My second point was that Taney
was wrong to hold that
Congress lacked power to outlaw slavery in the federal
territories. Prof. Finkelman says he agrees with me (I think)
about the Article IV power over territories, so what has become of his
assertion that various framers could not imagine slavery being hemmed in
by federal power? Whatever compromise anyone imagined
to be embodied in the Northwest Ordinance about taking slaves into other
territories, the Ordinance did not guarantee what treatment Congress
would give to subsequently acquired territories. In fact, it was
the perfect precedent for the Missouri Compromise that Taney
overturned.
My third point was that Taney
was wrong to declare
that such an act of Congress [banning slavery in a territory] inhibited a
slaveownerÂ’s liberty without due process of law. Prof.
Finkelman wants to know how I can such an argument with a straight
face. Let's see.
At page 450 of his opinion, Taney offered this and only this as a
due process argument: [A]n act of Congress which deprives a citizen
of the United States of his liberty or property merely because he came
himself or brought his property into a particular Territory of the United
States, and who had committed no offence against the laws, could hardly
be dignified with the name of due process of law.
This is a perfect example of question-begging. The Missouri
Compromise made it an offence against the laws to carry
slaves into certain territories and there hold them as slaves. The
penalty was that they were no longer slaves and the
slaveholder lost his property. Sure looks like due process to
me. Unless one is a fan of substantive due process, that highly
useful judicial fraud. I am not. To borrow a bit from Lincoln
and use it differently: what if the law had plainly said that one shall
not bring hogs into a particular federal territory, and everyone was on
notice that they would be taken away if discovered once one crossed the
border? Does anyone imagine that this would run afoul of due
process? I think that could hardly be dignified with the
name of an argument.
Prof. Finkelman is in accord with Taney's general view of the pro-slavery
character of the Constitution. I am persuaded instead by Lincoln's
Cooper Union speech, among many others. I know Prof. Finkelman's
book to which he draws our attention. I am not persuaded by it, but
by Lincoln, Douglass (not Douglas), Marshall, Story, and the works of
Prof. Finkelman's Tulsa colleague Paul Rahe, Robert Goldwin, Herbert
Storing, Harry Jaffa, and Thomas West. Not to mention the late Don
Fehrenbacher, whose book on Dred Scott I have not opened lately but who I
believe was in accord with every argument I make above.
I thank Mark Graber for defending the 

Treaties (was Scalia's Originalism)

2003-08-01 Thread Matthew J. Franck

Nothing I wrote stated or implied that the U.S. cannot
ratify a treaty that gives an international human rights treaty a status
equal to the Constitution and that establishes an international body as
the authoritative interpreter of the international
instrument. I suppose it could, though I'd like to give it
further thought. This I do know: I'm glad it has never done
so!
Matt
***
Matthew J. Franck
Professor and Chairman
Department of Political Science
Radford University
P.O. Box 6945
Radford, VA 24142-6945
phone 540-831-5854
fax 540-831-6075
e-mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]
***
At 02:30 PM 8/1/2003 -0800, you wrote:
I have not followed the earlier
strand of this discussion, but your
reading of the Supremacy Clause is hardly dictated by its language
--
though it has support in obiter dicta in Reid v. Covert. The clause
may
easily be read as placing treaties on the same level as the
Constitution
so long as they are enacted using the process that the Constitution
indicates. While hardly the traditional U.S. approach, it is not
clear
from the text that the U.S. cannot ratify a treaty that gives an
international human rights treaty a status equal to the Constitution
and
that establishes an international body as the authoritative interpreter
of
the international instrument. Given that public international law
was
often viewed in natural law terms in the 18th century, it might even
be
possible to argue that the Framers intended the U.S. to be able to
enter
into international agreements that would not be limited by the
Constitution. -- It would be an interesting area for
research.
Jonathan Miller
Professor of Law
Southwestern University School of Law

 I know Prof. Martin thinks the Constitution has some status as
a
 treaty. I do not. Federalist nos. 5 and 75 provide
no evidence to the
 contrary. Nor does Ware v. Hylton bear on the issue he raises;
it had to
 do with the supremacy of the Treaty of Paris (1783) over a law
of
Virginia.

 Scalia is quite right to disdain rulings of the European Court of
Human
 Rights as relevant to American constitutional questions.
Article VI
 identifies three sources of supreme law: the
Constitution, acts of
 Congress, and treaties. No treaty to which the U.S. is a
signatory
obliges
 our judges, state or federal, to pay the least bit of attention to
the
 rulings of the ECHR (thank goodness). Nor does customary
international
 law have any bearing on the laws by which Americans govern
themselves.

 Scalia's federalism--I have in mind those cases where
the five
 conservative justices band together to defend
sovereign immunity or
 tendentious readings of the Tenth Amendment or limits on the
commerce
 power--is lousy originalism precisely because it forgets that
the
 Constitution is not a treaty among the states, and because it rests
on an
 ahistorical view of the proper reach of judicial review.

 Matt
 ***
 Matthew J. Franck
 Professor and Chairman
 Department of Political Science
 Radford University
 P.O. Box 6945
 Radford, VA 24142-6945
 phone 540-831-5854
 fax 540-831-6075
 e-mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 ***
 At 01:23 PM 8/1/2003 -0400, you wrote:
 Prof. Franck writes in relevant part:
 
 Scalia is a good originalist in Lawrence, and a lousy one when
it comes
to
 federalism and other Loch Ness monsters of the
Constitution.
 
 Comment: It is not so clear to me that Scalia is a
good originalist
in
 Lawrence. He fails to recognize that the Eur.Ct.H.R. cases
cited in the
 Court's opinion reflect customary international legal
obligations with
 which the 14th Amendment's due process clause must be construed
because
of
 the Constitution's status as a treaty --something which both
Federalist
 and Anti-Federalist recognized. See Federalist No. 5;
Anti-Federalist
No.
 75. Customary international law is evolving -- also something
that the
 Founding Fathers recognized. See Ware v. Hylton (1796). Good
originalism
 recognize that the Constitution's provisions (viz., due process
clause)
 must be construed in conformity with this evolving
customary
international
 law. Scalia misconstrues the constitutiona! l relevance of
the
 Eur.Ct.H.R. cases by indicating that they are merely foreign law
-- not
 evidence of the U.S.' customary international legal
obligations. This
is
 particularly contrary to originalism because the Founders
specifically
saw
 European customary international law as binding on the
U.S.
 
 By the way, how is Scalia's federalism lousy?
 
 Francisco Forrest Martin



-
This message was sent using Endymion MailMan.
http://www.endymion.com/products/mailman/



Re: Scalia's Originalism

2003-08-01 Thread Matthew J. Franck

I will have to look for the Barnett article. For my
money, the best defense and explication of originalism is Keith
Whittington's Constitutional Interpretation.
Matt
***
Matthew J. Franck
Professor and Chairman
Department of Political Science
Radford University
P.O. Box 6945
Radford, VA 24142-6945
phone 540-831-5854
fax 540-831-6075
e-mail [EMAIL PROTECTED]
***
At 04:28 PM 8/1/2003 -0700, you wrote:
As
a non-originalist, I suggest that the only coherent originalism theory is
the textually (aka original meaning) theory which is well discussed in
Randy E. Barnett, An Originalism for NonOriginalists, 45 Loyola L Rev.
611 (1999). This version of originalism renders the most perplexing
of Prof. Lipkin's questions irrelevant.
Malla Pollack
Visiting, Univ. of Oregon, Law
541-346-1599
[EMAIL PROTECTED]

- Original Message - 
From: Robert Justin Lipkin 
To:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Friday, August 01, 2003 3:53 PM
Subject: Re: Scalia's Originalism

 As a non-historian and a non-political scientist, let me asks the following questions: (1) Does originalism presuppose the Framers held one determinate view regarding constitutional meaning? Does it permit the Framers' holding several different views? (2) How does one establish such either view? (3) How do historians (and political scientists) deal with the problem of ascertaining collective intent, a problem that Dworkin and more recently George Fletcher, as well as many others have emphasized? (2) Do those supporting original intent or original understanding appreciate the enormous commitments to differing philosophies of mind involved in either theory? (4) How do we ascertain the intent---subjective or objective---of a particular Framer? (5) How do we ascertain the public meaning of a critical political or legal term even in contemporary society let alone in the past? and (6) To what are we referring when we make claims that the original intent or understanding of a constitutional provision is X? (7) What evidentiary techniques are required to substantiate such claims? Apologies if some of these questions overlap. 

Bobby Lipkin
Widener University School of Law
Delaware 




Re: Scalia's Originalism

2003-08-01 Thread Francisco Martin


Prof. Franck writes: "I know Prof. Martin thinks the Constitution has some "status as a treaty." I do not. Federalist nos. 5 and 75 provide no evidence to the contrary."

Comment: John Jay indirectly referred to the Constitution as a treaty in Federalist No. 4 when he favorably compared it to the Treaty of Union (1707) between England and Scotland establishing United Kingdom and recognizing one British nation.Hampden in Anti-Federalist No. 75 also indirectly referred to the Constitution when he stated, "Who is it that does not know, that by treaties in Europe the succession and constitution of many sovereign states, ha[ve] been regulated?"There are numerous other reasons why the Constitution is a federal treaty -- too many to go into here. (If anyone would like a copy of my paper, I would be happy to email it to them.) Indeed, I  cannot find any compelling reason why the Constitution isNOT a treaty. If someone can tell me why the Constitution is not a treaty, I would love to hear the reasons.

Prof. Franck continues: "Nor does Ware v. Hylton bear on the issue he raises; it had to do with the supremacy of the Treaty of Paris (1783) over a law of Virginia."

Comment: Ware v. Hylton distinguished between ancient and modern law of nations. This cannot be controversial. By definition, customary international law is CUSTOMARY, and customs change.

Prof. Franck continues: "Scalia is quite right to disdain rulings of the European Court of Human Rights as relevant to American constitutional questions. Article VI identifies three sources of "supreme law": the Constitution, acts of Congress, and treaties. 

Comment: Treaties (especially multilateral treaties, such as the ECHR) are evidence of customary international law for a number of reasons (depending on the instrument); hence, customary international law is part of the supreme law of the land.

Prof. Franck continues: "No treaty to which the U.S. is a signatory obliges our judges, state or federal, to pay the least bit of attention to the rulings of the ECHR (thank goodness). Nor does "customary international law" have any bearing on the laws by which Americans govern themselves."

Comment: It does not matter whether the U.S. is a party to the ECHR for the ECHR to be evidence of the U.S.' customary international legal obligations. At least one federal court has recognized the ECHR as reflecting customary international legal obligations for the U.S. As for your statement "[n]or does 'customary international law' have any bearing on the laws by which Americans govern themselves," I am dumbfounded. Both the U.S. Supreme Court and state courts repeatedly have recognized that customary international law is binding on the federal government and the states.
Prof. Franck continues: "Scalia's "federalism"--I have in mind those cases where the five "conservative" justices band together to defend "sovereign immunity" or tendentiouus readings of the Tenth Amendment or limits on the commerce power--is lousy originalism precisely because it forgets that the Constitution is not a treaty among the states, and because it rests on an ahistorical view of the proper reach of judicial review."

Comment: Thanks for the clarification. I would just comment that the fact that the Constitution IS a "federal" treaty actually may support yourarguments againstScalia's federalism incommerce clause cases because "federal" treaties(which are similar to foedi) give greater authority to the central government in interstate affairs -- such as commerce.In the case of commerce clause cases, it is important to note that the interstate commerce claause sits right in-between the foreign commerce and Indian commerce clauses -- areasboth governed by international law (at least until 1871 for Indian commerce). It is reasonable to assume that the interstate commerce clause also must be construed in conformity with international law. Indeed, Madison, Randolph, and others argued in the Virginia state convention that the Constitution did not allow the federal government to violate state navigational rights (e.g, on theMississippi)because this would violate the law of nations – even if there was no explicit prohibition in the Constitution. Hence, interstate commerce (at least insofar as navigational rights were concerned) was governed by the law of nations, and the Constitution could not be construed to conflict with this law of nations.
Francisco Forrest Martin


Re: Dred Scott (was Scalia's Originalism)

2003-08-01 Thread Mark Graber
Some thoughts on Dred Scott.  Professor Franck is quite correct that the
conventional view is that originalism can justify Dred Scott.  My view,
I should emphasize, is that originalism provides as much support to
Taney as to Curtis or McLean, not that Taney was right and they were
wrong.  Some specific commentary on points Professor Franck makes.


Professor Franck declares:

First, I said, Taney was wrong, as a matter of original understanding,
to
deny that free blacks could be considered citizens of the United
States.  Prof. Finkelman asks whether I really believe that various
southerners at the time of ratification believed that they were
entering a
Union in which the free blacks would be considered full citizens and in
which slavery would be threatened and hemmed in.  The question is not
what
they believed.  The question is what the Constitution permits and
prohibits.  If they didn't see that it permits the treatment of free
blacks
as citizens, and the hemming in of slavery, they weren't paying
attention.  Congress could, for instance--but did not--permit the
naturalization of nonwhite immigrants in its first naturalization
statutes.  Free blacks who were not free immigrants but emancipated or
born
free in the U.S. were considered citizens by a number of states, and
inasmuch as the Constitution was silent on what did or did not make
someone
born here a citizen, but permitted suits between citizens of different
states in Article III, Taney was wrong to address the irrelevant
question
of whether free blacks were or could be citizens of the U.S. (an
interesting move toward nationalization by a supposed states' rights
man).  It's a familiar judicial gambit: ask the wrong question and give
the
answer you like.

Two thoughts (and I do not have the opinion close at hand).  Taney
actually only discusses whether former slaves can become citizens by
virtue of emancipation.  His opinion actually leaves open whether
Congress can naturalize immigrants of color.  Second, some free blacks
were citizens in 1787, but I see little evidence that most southerners
were aware of this.  So suppose most southerners are under the
impression that only whites are citizens and most northerners under the
impression that persons of color can become citizens.  No meeting of
minds.  Both Curtis and Taney have to strain history to conclude
otherwise.

Back to Professor Franck:


My second point was that Taney was wrong to hold that Congress lacked
power to outlaw slavery in the federal territories.  Prof. Finkelman
says
he agrees with me (I think) about the Article IV power over territories,
so
what has become of his assertion that various framers could not imagine
slavery being hemmed in by federal power?  Whatever compromise anyone
imagined to be embodied in the Northwest Ordinance about taking slaves
into
other territories, the Ordinance did not guarantee what treatment
Congress
would give to subsequently acquired territories.  In fact, it was the
perfect precedent for the Missouri Compromise that Taney overturned.

A note: interestingly, about 75-80 of the slave state representatives
who spoke during the Missouri Compromise debates either explicitly
declared that Congress could not ban slavery in the territories or made
arguments to that effect.  I have have only one non-border south
representative explicitly asserting a congressional right.
Nevertheless, believing the morthern territories to be a vast wasteland
they accepted to ban to get Missouri in.  So it is a bit more
complicated than traditionally thought to treat the Missouri Compromise
as recognition of congressional power.  Maybe it was a constitutional
compromise as well.

My third point was that Taney was wrong to declare that such an act of
Congress [banning slavery in a territory] inhibited a slaveowner's
liberty
without due process of law.  Prof. Finkelman wants to know how I can
such
an argument with a straight face.  Let's see.

At page 450 of his opinion, Taney offered this and only this as a due
process argument: [A]n act of Congress which deprives a citizen of the
United States of his liberty or property merely because he came himself
or
brought his property into a particular Territory of the United States,
and
who had committed no offence against the laws, could hardly be dignified
with the name of due process of law.

This is a perfect example of question-begging.  The Missouri Compromise
made it an offence against the laws to carry slaves into certain
territories and there hold them as slaves.  The penalty was that they
were no longer slaves and the slaveholder lost his property.  Sure looks
like due process to me.  Unless one is a fan of substantive due process,
that highly useful judicial fraud.  I am not.  To borrow a bit from
Lincoln
and use it differently: what if the law had plainly said that one shall
not
bring hogs into a particular federal territory, and everyone was on
notice
that they would be taken away if discovered once one crossed the
border?  

Re: Dred Scott (was Scalia's Originalism)

2003-08-01 Thread Ilya Somin
IF I recall correctly, free blacks were citizens in at least one southern
state (North Carolina) in 1787. It is possible that ordinary southern
whites weren't aware of this fact, but such an assumption is less
plausible in the case of southern political elites and southern delegates
to the state ratifying conventions. It is also, I think, implausible to
assume that southern white elites were unaware that free blacks were
citizens in several northern states. As to why southern whites  might have
been willing to accept the presence of free black citizens, it is
important to realize that such citizens were few in 1787, and the
Constitution left the definition of citizenship largely in the hands of
the states. Thus, southern whites, if they considered this issue at all,
may not have seen much of a threat here.

Regarding the DoI, I don't have much to add to the vast literature on the
subject. However, Thomas Jefferson and many other framers were lifelong
opponents of slavery so it is perfectly plausible that they meant to
include blacks in it. Jefferson was one of the main supporters of the
Northwest Ordinance and attempted to pass emancipation legislation in
Virginia. Obviously, neither Jefferson nor the others expected immediate
emancipation as a result of the Declaration, and many were personally
hypocritical in  so far as they continued to own slaves themselves.
However, it is not true that they didn't realize that the wording of the
DoI applied to blacks too, at least to the extent of condemning their
enslavement.

Ilya Somin

On Fri, 1 Aug 2003, Paul Finkelman wrote:

 I agree with Franck that it was reasonable to argue that free blacks
 were citizens of hte US if you lived in some parts of the north; one
 assumes the Mass. framers believed this, from their experience.  but the
 va, sc and ga framers would never have understood this is what they were
 doing.  Can you imagine SC ratifiying if it pinckney had come back and
 said you will have to deal with black us citizens?   there wre multiple
 intentions, as mark graber pointed out.The problem with
 originalism and intentions is that we cannot know what it means; we
 can look at text (is Franck now a strict constructionist/textualist?);
 but the text says slavery is protected in many ways; intentions go
 beyond text to the debates (where they can help us, but of course mostly
 they can't).  But on slavery it is quite clear the southern framers
 *intended* to support slavery and ratified with that intention.  See
 Pinckney's speeches in SC or even Madison's and Randolph's in VA.  Thus,
 on this point, it seems to be, as Mark Graber said earlier, that Taney's
 orginalism is as plausible as anyone else's; I would argue more so,
 given the proslavery nature of the constitution.

 I did not get into teh Dec of I, but the only reference to slavery there
 is at the end, when the Dec complains about the king freeing slaves to
 fight against the patriots  (He has incited domestic insurrections.)  If
 something in the Dec. of I. was supposed to apply to slaves -- if that
 ws the *intent* of the DofI, I am sure the 40% of Virginia that was held
 in slavery would have been happy to know about it.  But, neither the
 primary author (the Master of Monticello) nor very many other southern
 leaders, seemed to think that it applied.  Now, that leaves Prof. Franck
 two alternatives.  Either he can concede that the Dec. of I's authors
 did not intend it to apply to slavery or he can concend the founders,
 starting with TJ, of being dishonest, hypocritcal, etc.

 we agree on the territories clause; but I think Taney's 5th Amendment
 argument is powerful and goes to the heart of what slaveholders intended
 when the wrote and ratified that amendment. surely they did not intend
 it to be an abolitionist amendment; they intended it to protect their
 property.

 Lincoln's Cooper Union speech -- as well as his House Divided Speech and
 his debates with Douglas speeches are fine political rhetoric; I would
 have voted for him; but it is not great history.  It is important for
 those of us who admire Lincoln, but who are modern scholars, to
 understand the difference between a great speech that fits and era, and
 serious historical analaysis.  Lincoln was able to persuade the north
 that his view of history was how it ought to be, but that does not mean
 he was right about how it was.  fortunately, Lincoln was neither an
 orginalist nor a text bound literalist.


 (ps, please excuse typoes, i am working with one hand, the other is
 taped up.)

 --
 Paul Finkelman
 Chapman Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Tulsa College of Law
 3120 East 4th Place
 Tulsa, OK   74104-3189

 918-631-3706 (office)
 918-631-2194 (fax)

 [EMAIL PROTECTED]