Re: Hegel Marx

2004-07-16 Thread Ted Winslow
Charles Brown wrote:
Perhaps a scientific worldview enhances achievement of
self-determinaton
through greater mastery of necessity and thereby freedom. Radical
acknowledgement of objective reality implies the existence of
subjective
reality.
 Darwin, Lewontin, Levin and Gould's work concern an area with a lot of
non-human wills  (improper wills ?), animal psychology. A dialectical
materialist approach to biology is not identical with Hegel's.
Whitehead's ontology is a scientific worldview.  It's a sublation of
the scientific materialist form of science that includes, for instance,
a sublation of relativity and quantum theory.
The sublation produces an ontology consistent with the existence of
freedom not only as self-determination, but as self-determination
potentially able, in the case of human being, to take the form of a
will proper and a universal will.  As I've pointed out before,
Whitehead makes science in this enlarged sense the essence of
freedom understood as the practicability of purpose, a conception of
freedom he explicitly associates with the economic interpretation of
history.
Scientific materialism has no logical space for self-determination in
any form let alone this one, i.e. no room for will where we mean by
this some degree of self-determination.  This produces logical
incoherence, as in the claim that science so conceived can enhance
human freedom.
A will proper contrasts with an animal will which has more of less
limitation or a content which is immediately extant through nature.
The Will Proper, or the Higher Appetite, is (a) pure indeterminateness
of the Ego, which as such has no limitation or a content which is
immediately extant through nature but is indifferent towards any and
every determinateness. (b) The Ego can, at the same time, pass over to
a determinateness and make a choice of some one or other and then
actualize it. (Hegel, The Philosophical Propaedeutic p. 2)
In the articles I recently cited, Julie Nelson appropriates an object
relations psychoanalytic interpretation both of the dogmatic
misidentification of science with scientific materialist ontological
premises and of the inability of minds dogmatically attached to these
premises to comprehend alternative premises such as the premise that
relations are internal.  On this basis she makes the following
claims:
This feminist critique of economic methodology, then, springs not from
ad hoc dissatisfaction with various aspects, but from a deep analysis
of the social, historical, and psychosexual meanings the traditional
image of science holds for its participants.  The idea that the
universe may be open, in some ways fundamentally unpredictable, and
intrinsically purposive - in contrast to being a closed system,
ultimately distillable into formulae, controllable, and fundamentally
indifferent - is not simply a reasonable alternative ontology that can
be carefully weighed for its logical implications and neutrally
evaluated for its relative merits.  As Harding writes, 'it requires a
great deal more than just 'clear thinking' to dislodge ... ontologies
from their status as obvious' (1999: 130).  The idea of an open
universe feels fundamentally _scary_ for those who sense that not only
their status as scientists set above the objects they study, but also
their safety vis-a-vis chaos, their 'manhood' (whether actual, or, in
the case of female scientists, symbolic), and their very own distinct
selfhood are threatened unless they can keep the living, novel,
relational aspects of nature safely at bay.
   Feminists who delve into the historical, social, emotional, and
psychosexual dynamics that have kept women suppressed and oppressed
have found a complex of dualistic, hierarchical belief patterns that
manifest themselves not only in the social realm, but also in
intellectual (and religious and artistic) endeavors.  Historically,
well-reasoned criticisms of neoclassical economics - targeting its
unrealistic assumptions, narrow methodology, over-formalism, false
detachment, etc. - have been legion, as any perusal of a bibliographic
database will show.  Also historically, they have generally failed to
alter the mainstream ideas of the discipline.  Yet the present feminist
analysis does not simply add to this legion of critiques; it suggests,
at a basic emotional and motivational level, that such critique is
suppressed because it is _feared_.  It points out how reasonableness is
taking a back seat to emotional reaction, in this drama.  This feminist
analysis takes us back to the territory of critique of Enlightenment
dualisms once more but this time with feeling.  (Once more, with
feeling: Feminist economics and the ontological question, in Feminist
Economics 9(1), 2003, p. 111(
I think Doug once tried to initiate a discussion on this list of an
earlier version of these claims.
Ted


absolute general law of capitalist accumulation/ Hegel/Marx

2004-07-16 Thread Charles Brown
 Hegel  Marx
by Ted Winslow

Whitehead's ontology is a scientific worldview.  It's a sublation of
the scientific materialist form of science that includes, for instance,
a sublation of relativity and quantum theory.

^
CB: So what is overcome and what is preserved ?



The sublation produces an ontology consistent with the existence of
freedom not only as self-determination, but as self-determination
potentially able, in the case of human being, to take the form of a
will proper and a universal will.  As I've pointed out before,
Whitehead makes science in this enlarged sense the essence of
freedom understood as the practicability of purpose, a conception of
freedom he explicitly associates with the economic interpretation of
history.


CB: So, is he rediscovering Engels on these issues ?

^^^


Scientific materialism has no logical space for self-determination in
any form let alone this one,

^^

CB: What do you mean by scientific materialism ?

^





 i.e. no room for will where we mean by
this some degree of self-determination.  This produces logical
incoherence, as in the claim that science so conceived can enhance
human freedom.

A will proper contrasts with an animal will which has more of less
limitation or a content which is immediately extant through nature.

^
CB: Human will in contrast with animal will has much more social content,
including especially social connections to life experience and activities of
now dead generations of humans. This is the main difference between human
and animal consciousness/will.

 Referring to your previous post crtiicizing Darwin, Lewontin, et.al, since
Darwin, Lewontin and other biologists are dealing with animals, the will
proper wouldn't play the same role for them as in dealing with human
society, right ?

^^


The Will Proper, or the Higher Appetite, is (a) pure indeterminateness
of the Ego, which as such has no limitation or a content which is
immediately extant through nature but is indifferent towards any and
every determinateness. (b) The Ego can, at the same time, pass over to
a determinateness and make a choice of some one or other and then
actualize it. (Hegel, The Philosophical Propaedeutic p. 2)

In the articles I recently cited, Julie Nelson appropriates an object
relations psychoanalytic interpretation both of the dogmatic
misidentification of science with scientific materialist ontological
premises and of the inability of minds dogmatically attached to these
premises to comprehend alternative premises such as the premise that
relations are internal.


CB: How does the concept of internal relations help explicate the absolute
general law of capitalist accumulation ?

^^^





 On this basis she makes the following
claims:

This feminist critique of economic methodology, then, springs not from
ad hoc dissatisfaction with various aspects, but from a deep analysis
of the social, historical, and psychosexual meanings the traditional
image of science holds for its participants.  The idea that the
universe may be open, in some ways fundamentally unpredictable, and
intrinsically purposive

^^

CB: Unpredictable , yet purposive ?  Doesn't knowing the purpose give a
basis to predict ?

^^



- in contrast to being a closed system,
ultimately distillable into formulae, controllable, and fundamentally
indifferent - is not simply a reasonable alternative ontology that can
be carefully weighed for its logical implications and neutrally
evaluated for its relative merits.  As Harding writes, 'it requires a
great deal more than just 'clear thinking' to dislodge ... ontologies
from their status as obvious' (1999: 130).  The idea of an open
universe feels fundamentally _scary_ for those who sense that not only
their status as scientists set above the objects they study, but also
their safety vis-a-vis chaos, their 'manhood' (whether actual, or, in
the case of female scientists, symbolic), and their very own distinct
selfhood are threatened unless they can keep the living, novel,
relational aspects of nature safely at bay.
   Feminists who delve into the historical, social, emotional, and
psychosexual dynamics that have kept women suppressed and oppressed
have found a complex of dualistic, hierarchical belief patterns that
manifest themselves not only in the social realm, but also in
intellectual (and religious and artistic) endeavors.  Historically,
well-reasoned criticisms of neoclassical economics - targeting its
unrealistic assumptions, narrow methodology, over-formalism, false
detachment, etc. - have been legion, as any perusal of a bibliographic
database will show.  Also historically, they have generally failed to
alter the mainstream ideas of the discipline.  Yet the present feminist
analysis does not simply add to this legion of critiques; it suggests,
at a basic emotional and motivational level, that such critique is
suppressed because it is _feared_.  It points out how reasonableness is
taking

Hegel Marx

2004-07-15 Thread Charles Brown
by Ted Winslow

This misinterprets Whitehead. Like Marx's, his ontology is alternative to
and radically inconsistent with the materialist ontology that has
dominated science since the 17th century. In elaborating it, he provides a
systematic critique of this scientific materialism in all its forms
(including the Darwinian form embraced by Lewontin, Levins and Gould).
Scientific materialism is anti-humanist and anti-subjective where we mean
by an ontology that is humanist and subjective one having logical space
for the conception of human being as a being capable of the kind of
self-determination expressible by Hegel's ideas of a will proper and a
universal will.

^
CB: Perhaps a scientific worldview enhances achievement of self-determinaton
through greater mastery of necessity and thereby freedom. Radical
acknowledgement of objective reality implies the existence of subjective
reality.

 Darwin, Lewontin, Levin and Gould's work concern an area with a lot of
non-human wills  (improper wills ?), animal psychology. A dialectical
materialist approach to biology is not identical with Hegel's.

^^

Specifically Whitehead is, as I've many times indicated, an adherent of the
doctrine of relations as internal. Among other things he points to the
implications of this doctrine for logic and language mentioned in my
previous e-mail.

In all this his ontological beliefs contrast sharply with Russell's (as
Russell himself indicates). Here are some passages from the two of them
which include consideration of the implications of the doctrine for
language, logic, arithmetic and counting.

So far, this lecture has proceeded in the form of dogmatic statement. What
is the evidence to which it appeals?
The only answer is the reaction of our own nature to the general aspect of
life in the Universe.
This answer involves complete disagreement with a widespread tradition of
philosophic thought. This erroneous tradition presupposes independent
existences; and this presupposition involves the possibility of an adequate
description of finite fact. The result is the presupposition of adequate
separate premises from which argument can proceed.
For example, much philosophic thought is based upon the faked adequacy of
some account of various modes of human experience. Thence we reach some
simple conclusion as to the essential character of human knowledge, and of
its essential limitation. Namely, we know what we cannot know.
Understand that I am not denying the importance of the analysis of
experience: far from it. The progress of human thought is derived from the
progressive enlightenment produced thereby. What I am objecting to is the
absurd trust in the adequacy of our knowledge. The self-confidence of
learned people is the comic tragedy of civilization.
There is not a sentence which adequately states its own meaning. There is
always a background of presupposition which defies analysis by reason of its
infinitude.
Let us take the simplest case; for example, the sentence, 'One and one
makes two.'
Obviously this sentence omits a necessary limitation. For one thing and
itself make one thing. So we ought to say, 'One thing and another thing make
two things.' This must mean the togetherness of one thing with another thing
issues in a group of two things.
At this stage all sorts of difficulties arise. There must be the proper
sort of things in the proper sort of togetherness. The togetherness of a
spark and gunpowder produces an explosion, which is very unlike two things.
Thus we should say, 'The proper sort of togetherness of one thing and
another thing produces the sort of group which we call two things.' Common
sense at once tells you what is meant. But unfortunately there is no
adequate analysis of common sense, because it involves our relation to the
infinity of the Universe.


CB: This one plus one equal two story reminds of the undergraduates who had
a math class in which Whitehead and Russell's _Principia Mathematica_ was
mentioned and something about their really proving that one plus one equals
two.  Yea the joke went  we really weren't sure that one plus one
equalled two. I'm glad they proved it.

Fungibility, the individual, the specific and the general.


Hegel Marx

2004-07-14 Thread Devine, James
Shane M. writes:
In the depths of WW One Lenin felt called upon to study the Science
of Logic.  He found it revelatory, and in his Philosophical Notebooks
he wrote (I quote from memory, perhaps inexactly):

It is impossible to understand Das Kapital without a thorough
comprehension of Hegel's Science of Logic.  That is why, after
fifty years, none of the Marxists has understood Marx.

Daniel D: was he right?

I'd say so (though there may have been Marxists before Lenin who studied
the SCIENCE OF LOGIC and Lenin never heard about it). I think reading
Hegel helps one understand Marx, but that it's too bad that one has to
read Hegel to do so. 

Charles B: I'm quite open to Hegel in relatively simple language
compared to the
original.  From my experience, the translation to  simpler language
would be
a complicated project itself though.  Are you saying someone has put
Hegel (or dialectics) 
into simpler language ?

Levins  Lewontin's DIALECTICAL BIOLOGIST presents a good effort to
present dialectical method (epistemology) in the language of science. 

They summarize it as describing the totality (whole) that we have to
understand in which parts make whole (the various individuals and
internal structures of a totality create the totality itself) and whole
makes part (the nature of these individuals and structures is
profoundly shaped by the totality in which they operate). This
back-and-forth doesn't settle down into any kind of equilibrium.
Instead, the totality is always changing. 

(an example: under capitalism, our actions create history, though not
exactly as we please, since we are constrained by various institutional
structures (such as corporations or political parties). The nature of
our consciousness and thus our actions is in turn shaped and largely
determined by our positions within capitalism, while the institutional
structures are also shaped and largely determined by capitalism's laws
of motion.) 

To LL, the dialectical method does not produce answers to our questions
as much as questions to ask of the real (empirical) world. 


Jim Devine [EMAIL PROTECTED]   http://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevine



Re: Hegel Marx

2004-07-14 Thread Louis Proyect
When Marxists heap adulation on a reactionary, racist, anti-humanist
metaphysician and Prussian propagandist, then perhaps we have a slight
problem.
Sure, some of Hegel's ideas are built into Marx's thinking and later
Marxism. So are Aristotle's, Leibniz's, etc. Sure, Marx matured in an
atmosphere of Hegelianism and could not have avoided being influenced
byt it (even if the influence was filtered through radical Hegelians).
But if we leap backward over Marx to Hegel and start to proclaim that
Hegelian ontology has any value and validity today, we really come close
to betraying the spirit of Marx.
Some Marxists have claimed to find that just about every non-Marxist
philosopher was advancing materialism. It isn't true of Hegel.
Hegel and Kant represent the two important streams of idealist thinking
that have come down to us. We can give those guys credit for their place
in the history of ideas, but we have to recognize that historical and
dialectical materialism denies the validity of most of their doctrines.
*Except* in the context of the history of ideas, they have no relevance.
What really pisses me off is reading Marxists proclaiming the importance
of old idealist philosophers -- and new idealist philosophers -- and
totally neglecting the naturalist, realist, philosophers. We have to
overcome the tendency to heap invective on thinkers whose ideas are
close enough to Marxism to pose a real threat of presenting an
alternative to Marxism and of seducing people away from Marxism. That
was the case with Lenin vis-a-vis Mach -- no radical, but yet a
philosopher of science, unlike Hegel. Think of the way we vilify or
ignore Dewey. Russell. Whitehead. Mead. The positivists. Etc. These
folks represent the main line of thinking in philosophies that are
friendly to science and are to one degree or another materialist
(although the word of course scared them). Nor are these philosophers
somehow anti-humanist and anti-subjective. There is, IMHO, more humanism
in John Dewey than there is in the entire Hot Dog school. Dewey, after
all, pioneered the most humanistic form of education that we have. And,
for goodness sake, Mead practically invented social psychology.
Enough said. I don't plan to respond to other postings on this thread
unless it becomes unavoidable (personal).
En lucha
Jim Blaut
--
The Marxism list: www.marxmail.org


Re: Hegel Marx

2004-07-14 Thread Devine, James
Think of the way we vilify or
ignore Dewey. Russell. Whitehead. Mead.

who is this we?
jd 



Re: Hegel Marx

2004-07-14 Thread s.artesian
Long version:

Last time I looked, we weren't heaping praise on Hegel, nor has anyone denied Hegel's 
racism.  But denying the importance of both the substance and method of Hegel to 
Marx's of work because Hegel wasn't a humanist, was an idealist, and was ignorant, 
in every sense of the word, concerning Africa is substituting moral repugnance and 
outrage for historical analysis, something which is anti-Marxist to the core.

Marx never denied the importance of Hegel for the development of his work.  Marx, to 
my knowledge, also never described his work as humanism.  And despite the acrobatics 
of some, Marxism has little enough to do with what passes as humanism.


Short version:  We were discussing Marx's use of Hegelian jargon, whether or not he 
even used it (I still can't find anything that comes close to Hegel's expositions).  
If somebody out there is vilifying Russell, Mead, Dewey, that's a horse on a different 
colored list.


-Original Message-
From: Louis Proyect [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Jul 14, 2004 12:14 PM
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Subject: Re: [PEN-L] Hegel  Marx

When Marxists heap adulation on a reactionary, racist, anti-humanist
metaphysician and Prussian propagandist, then perhaps we have a slight
problem.

Sure, some of Hegel's ideas are built into Marx's thinking and later
Marxism. So are Aristotle's, Leibniz's, etc. Sure, Marx matured in an
atmosphere of Hegelianism and could not have avoided being influenced
byt it (even if the influence was filtered through radical Hegelians).
But if we leap backward over Marx to Hegel and start to proclaim that
Hegelian ontology has any value and validity today, we really come close
to betraying the spirit of Marx.

Some Marxists have claimed to find that just about every non-Marxist
philosopher was advancing materialism. It isn't true of Hegel.

Hegel and Kant represent the two important streams of idealist thinking
that have come down to us. We can give those guys credit for their place
in the history of ideas, but we have to recognize that historical and
dialectical materialism denies the validity of most of their doctrines.
*Except* in the context of the history of ideas, they have no relevance.

What really pisses me off is reading Marxists proclaiming the importance
of old idealist philosophers -- and new idealist philosophers -- and
totally neglecting the naturalist, realist, philosophers. We have to
overcome the tendency to heap invective on thinkers whose ideas are
close enough to Marxism to pose a real threat of presenting an
alternative to Marxism and of seducing people away from Marxism. That
was the case with Lenin vis-a-vis Mach -- no radical, but yet a
philosopher of science, unlike Hegel. Think of the way we vilify or
ignore Dewey. Russell. Whitehead. Mead. The positivists. Etc. These
folks represent the main line of thinking in philosophies that are
friendly to science and are to one degree or another materialist
(although the word of course scared them). Nor are these philosophers
somehow anti-humanist and anti-subjective. There is, IMHO, more humanism
in John Dewey than there is in the entire Hot Dog school. Dewey, after
all, pioneered the most humanistic form of education that we have. And,
for goodness sake, Mead practically invented social psychology.

Enough said. I don't plan to respond to other postings on this thread
unless it becomes unavoidable (personal).

En lucha

Jim Blaut

--

The Marxism list: www.marxmail.org


Re: Hegel Marx

2004-07-14 Thread Carrol Cox
Louis Proyect wrote:


 En lucha

 Jim Blaut

This reminds me of an argument I was never able to have with Jim. In the
context of a different discussion he remarked in a post on the marxism
list that if one knew all the facts involved one would not have to study
the relations among them. As I say, it was a parenthetical remark and it
was not until almost a year later in wandering through some old posts
that I came across it. Hence the lack of any discussion with him on the
point. (I have a hard copy of the post someplace but currently all my
printouts are in one chaotic pile and I wouldn't be able to put my hands
on it. Until I do regard this as a remembered paraphrase, not as Jim's
precise words.)

But he was profoundly wrong on that, though how much it influenced his
thought and practice in general I do not know.

Carrol


Re: Hegel Marx

2004-07-14 Thread Ted Winslow
Jim Blaut wrote:
Think of the way we vilify or
ignore Dewey. Russell. Whitehead. Mead. The positivists. Etc. These
folks represent the main line of thinking in philosophies that are
friendly to science and are to one degree or another materialist
(although the word of course scared them). Nor are these philosophers
somehow anti-humanist and anti-subjective.
This misinterprets Whitehead.  Like Marx's, his ontology is alternative 
to and radically inconsistent with the materialist ontology that has 
dominated science since the 17th century.  In elaborating it, he 
provides a systematic critique of this scientific materialism in all 
its forms (including the Darwinian form embraced by Lewontin, Levins 
and Gould).  Scientific materialism is anti-humanist and 
anti-subjective where we mean by an ontology that is humanist and 
subjective one having logical space for the conception of human being 
as a being capable of the kind of self-determination expressible by 
Hegel's ideas of a will proper and a universal will.

Specifically Whitehead is, as I've many times indicated, an adherent of 
the doctrine of relations as internal.  Among other things he points 
to the implications of this doctrine for logic and language 
mentioned in my previous e-mail.

In all this his ontological beliefs contrast sharply with Russell's (as 
Russell himself indicates).  Here are some passages from the two of 
them which include consideration of the implications of the doctrine 
for language, logic, arithmetic and counting.

So far, this lecture has proceeded in the form of dogmatic 
statement.  What is the evidence to which it appeals?
The only answer is the reaction of our own nature to the 
general aspect of life in the Universe.
This answer involves complete disagreement with a widespread 
tradition of philosophic thought.  This erroneous tradition presupposes 
independent existences; and this presupposition involves the 
possibility of an adequate description of finite fact.  The result is 
the presupposition of adequate separate premises from which argument 
can proceed.
For example, much philosophic thought is based upon the faked 
adequacy of some account of various modes of human experience.  Thence 
we reach some simple conclusion as to the essential character of human 
knowledge, and of its essential limitation.  Namely, we know what we 
cannot know.
Understand that I am not denying the importance of the 
analysis of experience: far from it.  The progress of human thought is 
derived from the progressive enlightenment produced thereby.  What I am 
objecting to is the absurd trust in the adequacy of our knowledge.  The 
self-confidence of learned people is the comic tragedy of civilization.
There is not a sentence which adequately states its own 
meaning.  There is always a background of presupposition which defies 
analysis by reason of its infinitude.
Let us take the simplest case; for example, the sentence, 'One 
and one makes two.'
Obviously this sentence omits a necessary limitation.  For one 
thing and itself make one thing.  So we ought to say, 'One thing and 
another thing make two things.'  This must mean the togetherness of one 
thing with another thing issues in a group of two things.
At this stage all sorts of difficulties arise.  There must be 
the proper sort of things in the proper sort of togetherness.  The 
togetherness of a spark and gunpowder produces an explosion, which is 
very unlike two things.  Thus we should say, 'The proper sort of 
togetherness of one thing and another thing produces the sort of group 
which we call two things.'  Common sense at once tells you what is 
meant.  But unfortunately there is no adequate analysis of common 
sense, because it involves our relation to the infinity of the 
Universe.
Also there is another difficulty.  When anything is placed in 
another situation, it changes.  Every hostess takes account of this 
truth when she invites suitable guests to a dinner party; and every 
cook presupposes it as she proceeds to cook the dinner.  Of course, the 
statement, 'One and one make two' assumes that the changes in the shift 
of circumstances are unimportant.  But it is impossible for us to 
analyse this notion of 'unimportant change.'  We have to rely upon 
common sense.
In fact, there is not a sentence, or a word, with a meaning 
which is independent of the circumstances under which it is uttered.  
The essence of unscholarly thought consists in a neglect of this truth. 
 Also it is equally the essence of common sense to neglect these 
differences of background when they are irrelevant to the immediate 
purpose.  My point is that we cannot rely upon any adequate explicit 
analysis.
The conclusion is that Logic, conceived as an adequate 
analysis of the advance of thought, is a fake.  It is a superb 
instrument, but it requires a background of common sense. ...
My point 

Re: Hegel-Marx on colonialism

1997-10-28 Thread Ricardo Duchesne

 Date sent:  Sat, 25 Oct 1997 18:47:57 -0400 (EDT)
 Send reply to:  [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 From:   Louis N Proyect [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 To: [EMAIL PROTECTED],
 [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Subject:David Harvey on the Communist Manifesto



That Hegel and Marx's views on colonialism were quite similar has 
already been shown by Avineri in his essay "Marx on Colonialism and 
Modernization". Marx's views on the political cultures of non-European 
societes were quite negative - just see his writings on India, 
Mexico, or even Eastern Europe. It is important, however, to be clear 
about what he was critical before we adopt a retrograde nationalist 
position, as dependency theory was to do later. 













 David Harvey spoke on the Communist Manifesto last night at NYC's Brecht
 Forum as part of a year-long celebration of its 150th anniversary. Harvey
 has some of the most interesting insights into the Marxist classics today,
 especially involving questions of their "spatial" dimension. Since he a
 geography professor, this is not surprising.
 
 Harvey spent much of his talks discussing shortcomings or omissions in the
 Communist Manifesto. For example, the question of how the state comes into
 existence is only dealt with in a sketchy manner. Also, there is little
 discussion of how the world is "territorialized." Marx and Engels accepted
 the division of the world as it stood in 1848 pretty much on its own
 terms.
 
 There is also very little consideration of the power of financial
 institutions, which Harvey found puzzling given the major role that the
 Rothschild and Baring banks were playing in Europe in those days. This
 oversight has been corrected by Doug Henwood, needless to say.
 
 One of the presuppositions of the Communist Manifesto is that local
 struggles meld into national struggles, which culminate in proletarian
 revolution. Harvey wondered if this was a simplistic view in light of the
 tendencies to retain a stubbornly local character with their own dynamic.
 He also questioned whether the socialist movement has failed to develop a
 geographical strategy that is anywhere as comprehensive as the
 bourgeoisie's. The bosses have learned to divide up workers in such a
 manner that trade union and political struggles are weakened. They, for
 example, have calculated that 50 workers per plant in distances of 200
 miles from each other has a powerful dampening effect on the ability to
 form unions. Workers need a geographical strategy of their own.
 
 Another problem is the tendency of the Communist Manifesto to depict the
 working-class in much more homogenous terms than it has developed
 historically. This means that the problem of conceptualizing socialism is
 much more difficult than originally anticipated. Perhaps the key is to
 conceive of a form of socialism that embraces heterogeneity rather than
 struggling against it.
 
 In almost a sidebar, Harvey developed some very interesting insights on
 the importance Marx and Engels attached to the question of colonialism.
 One of the goals of the Communist Manifesto was to develop a strategy for
 internationalism. The bourgeoisie had spread its tentacles world-wide and
 it was incumbent on the workers to forge ties across national boundaries.
 
 Harvey pointed out that colonialism was embraced by Hegel in "The
 Philosophy of Right" in 1821. This work was of enormous significance to
 Marx and he felt the need to confront and overcome Hegel's imperialist
 world-view, as reflected in the following passage from Hegel's work:
 
 "The principle of family life is dependence on the soil, on land, *terra
 firma*. Similarly, the natural element for industry, animating its outward
 movement, is the sea. Since the passion for gain involves risk, industry
 though bent on gain yet lifts itself above it; instead of remaining rooted
 to the soil and the limited circle of civil life with its pleasures and
 desires, it embraces the element of flux, danger and destruction.
 Furthermore, the sea is the greatest means of communication, and trade by
 sea creates commercial connections between distant countries and so
 relations involving contractual rights. At the same time, commerce of this
 kind is the most potent instrument of culture, and through it trade
 acquires its significance in the history of the world...
 
 "To realize what an instrument of culture lies in the link with the sea,
 consider countries where industry flourishes and contrast their relation
 to the sea with that of countries which have eschewed sea-faring and
 which, like Egypt and India, have become stagnant and sunk in the most
 frightful and scandalous superstition. Notice also how all great
 progressive peoples press onward to the sea."
 
 Marx was attempting to put these questions on the terrain of capital
 accumulation rather than philosophy when he wrote chapter 33 of volume one
 of Capital, titled "The Modern Theory of Colonization." He says:
 
 "In