Medical reasons for action vs. religious reasons for action

2012-07-05 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Here's an analogy from another area in which the normal rule - 
one person may not alter or injure another's body without permission - is 
relaxed: self-defense.

Say Vic is doing something that Don perceives as blasphemous, 
but that might also be dangerous to Don or Don's property.  (E.g., say Vic is 
burning a Koran and saying things that might reasonably lead Don - a Muslim - 
to think that Vic will imminently injure Don, or that the fire will spread to 
Don's property.)  Vic attacks Don using nondeadly force and injures him.

If Don reasonably believed that Vic was about to injure Don, 
and hit Don to prevent that, Don is not guilty of any crime, by reason of 
self-defense.  But say that the objective circumstances are the same, so that 
Don could have reasonably believed that Vic was about to injure him, but Don 
did not actually sincerely believe this.  Instead, he says that he attacked Vic 
because he thought God wanted him to attack Vic.  Then Don is guilty of 
assault; no self-defense defense is available (and I take it that we'd agree 
that no other defense should be available to him).  This rule does not treat 
religious reasons for hitting Vic worse than secular reasons generally.  But it 
does treat all reasons for hitting Vic worse than one favored secular reason - 
the perception that Vic poses an imminent danger to Don's person or property.

If I'm right on this, then I all think that there's no 
violation of the norm of equal treatment when we add another reason for 
allowing one person to alter or injure another's body: that the actor is the 
subject's parent and has a medical reason for ordering a surgery to the 
underage child.  That the parent has a right to alter the child's body for 
medical reasons doesn't mean he has a right to alter the child's body - even 
when the objective circumstances seem the same - for nonmedical reasons, 
including religious ones.

Eugene


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Vance R. Koven
Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 7:09 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: German circumcision decision

OK, let's turn this around again. I don't follow Eugene's reasoning here. If I 
do for religious reasons what anyone else could do for secular reasons, why 
should this be penalized? Seems like a fundamental equal-treatment issue.

On the second paragraph, Eugene is correct that my point went to institutional 
competence and legitimacy. I have little faith in courts to divine a social or 
moral consensus that isn't heavily biased in favor of whatever the upper middle 
class (the category into which most judges fall) thinks it knows. In the 
absence of an affirmative policy decision by elected representatives, 
therefore, the rule of decision that imposes the least harm to the polity ought 
to be that tradition carries prima facie probative weight. This is especially 
true in criminal cases, where the standard of statutory interpretation requires 
that crimes be clearly specified--none of this do no harm generalizing!
On Wed, Jul 4, 2012 at 4:24 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
Sorry for the delay responding - I was traveling Monday and 
Tuesday - but I'm not sure I grasp the argument in the first paragraph.  My 
view is generally this:

(1)  People should generally have the power to make medical 
decisions for themselves.
(2)  Infants and children can't make such decisions.
(3)  Yet some such medical decisions must be made quickly, 
before the child becomes mature enough to decide.
(4)  We therefore delegate this power to make medical decisions 
to the parents.

But this argument hinges on there being medical reasons for the 
decision - I don't see any reason for parents to have this power when they 
exercise it for nonmedical reasons.  We may defer to a parent's decision, even 
one we doubt, when it involves a tradeoff of one medical risk for another 
medical risk.  But I don't see why we should defer to such a decision when the 
parent doesn't even purport to be making a medical judgment, but is just 
deciding based on the judgment that God wants me to do this or I don't want 
to give more profits to Big Pharma.  That's not weighing religious motivation 
negatively because it's religious - that's weighing a nonmedical motivation 
negatively compared to a medical motivation because the only justification for 
letting me order someone to alter not my body but my son's body is the need for 
medical judgment.

This leaves two different arguments.  One is letting people do 
what they have always done, which strikes me as weak for the reasons I gave in 
part of my response to Paul Finkelman's post - especially give the longstanding 
tradition of allowing not 

Re: Medical reasons for action vs. religious reasons for action

2012-07-05 Thread Vance R. Koven
I'm not sure who the we is in Eugene's hypothesis, but nobody is
proposing to add anything to defenses, since it's the existence of the *
offense* that is under discussion. Nobody contests that the crime of
murder, or attempted murder, exists with a rather precise definition. There
is as yet no crime of circumcision. Moreover, in looking at the two
situations, it's obvious that the defense of self-defense (which derives
from the same unalienable right to life to which the crime of murder
speaks) contains a mental state within its definition, as does the crime of
murder. If there were a similar mental state in the crime of circumcision
(e.g. removing someone else's foreskin with the intent to do grievous
bodily harm), then one might say that the normal circumcision would never
violate the law, and if the perpetrator did have the requisite intent,
claiming religious justification might well not suffice as a defense.

Of course, a legislature creating a crime of circumcision could decide to
allow medical exemptions  but not to allow a religious one (RFRA arguments,
anyone? Would *Lukumi* apply?), but I still think that would be merely a
trap for the unwary defendant who fails to allege medical motives.

On Thu, Jul 5, 2012 at 10:46 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 Here’s an analogy from another area in which the normal
 rule – one person may not alter or injure another’s body without permission
 – is relaxed: self-defense.

 ** **

 Say Vic is doing something that Don perceives as
 blasphemous, but that might also be dangerous to Don or Don’s property.
 (E.g., say Vic is burning a Koran and saying things that might reasonably
 lead Don – a Muslim – to think that Vic will imminently injure Don, or that
 the fire will spread to Don’s property.)  Vic attacks Don using nondeadly
 force and injures him.

 ** **

 If Don reasonably believed that Vic was about to injure
 Don, and hit Don to prevent that, Don is not guilty of any crime, by reason
 of self-defense.  But say that the objective circumstances are the same, so
 that Don *could have* reasonably believed that Vic was about to injure
 him, but Don *did not actually sincerely believe this*.  Instead, he says
 that he attacked Vic because he thought God wanted him to attack Vic.  Then
 Don is guilty of assault; no self-defense defense is available (and I take
 it that we’d agree that no other defense should be available to him).  This
 rule does not treat religious reasons for hitting Vic worse than secular
 reasons generally.  But it does treat all reasons for hitting Vic worse
 than one favored secular reason – the perception that Vic poses an imminent
 danger to Don’s person or property.

 ** **

 If I’m right on this, then I all think that there’s no
 violation of the norm of equal treatment when we add another reason for
 allowing one person to alter or injure another’s body: that the actor is
 the subject’s parent and has a medical reason for ordering a surgery to the
 underage child.  That the parent has a right to alter the child’s body for
 medical reasons doesn’t mean he has a right to alter the child’s body –
 even when the objective circumstances seem the same – for nonmedical
 reasons, including religious ones.

 ** **

 Eugene

 ** **

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Vance R. Koven
 *Sent:* Thursday, July 05, 2012 7:09 AM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: German circumcision decision

 ** **

 OK, let's turn this around again. I don't follow Eugene's reasoning here.
 If I do for religious reasons what anyone else could do for secular
 reasons, why should this be penalized? Seems like a fundamental
 equal-treatment issue.

 On the second paragraph, Eugene is correct that my point went to
 institutional competence and legitimacy. I have little faith in courts to
 divine a social or moral consensus that isn't heavily biased in favor of
 whatever the upper middle class (the category into which most judges fall)
 thinks it knows. In the absence of an affirmative policy decision by
 elected representatives, therefore, the rule of decision that imposes the
 least harm *to the polity* ought to be that tradition carries prima facie
 probative weight. This is especially true in criminal cases, where the
 standard of statutory interpretation requires that crimes be clearly
 specified--none of this do no harm generalizing!

 On Wed, Jul 4, 2012 at 4:24 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu
 wrote:

 Sorry for the delay responding – I was traveling Monday
 and Tuesday – but I’m not sure I grasp the argument in the first
 paragraph.  My view is generally this:

  

 (1)  People should generally have the power to make
 medical decisions for themselves.

 (2)  Infants 

Medical reasons for action vs. religious reasons for action

2012-07-05 Thread Volokh, Eugene
The question, I think, isn't whether there should be a crime of 
circumcision as such.  Rather, the question is whether the normal crime of 
mayhem, assault, battery, or child abuse - whatever label a particular 
jurisdiction would use for cutting off a part of an infant's body - should have 
as a defense (1) categorical parental prerogative, at least when it comes to 
circumcision (I'm the parent and I can cut off certain parts of the child's 
body for any reason I choose), (2) religious parental prerogative (I'm the 
parent and I can cut off certain parts of the child's body if I think God wants 
me to), or (3) medical parental decision (I'm the parent and I can make 
medical decisions for the child, within broad parameters, even if that includes 
cutting off certain parts of the child's body, based on my good-faith estimate 
of the costs and benefits of a procedure).

I'm inclined to think that defense 2 is improper (for some of the reasons Chip 
gives), that defense 1 is proper only for actions that are highly unlikely to 
affect future bodily function (which male circumcision might or might not 
qualify, and which ear piercing does qualify as), and defense 3 is proper for 
actions that are fairly likely to affect future bodily function.  And the 
analogy to self-defense helps explain why defense 3 is proper even though it 
treats medical reasons as better than all other reasons, including religious 
ones.

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Vance R. Koven
Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 11:05 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Medical reasons for action vs. religious reasons for action

I'm not sure who the we is in Eugene's hypothesis, but nobody is proposing to 
add anything to defenses, since it's the existence of the offense that is under 
discussion. Nobody contests that the crime of murder, or attempted murder, 
exists with a rather precise definition. There is as yet no crime of 
circumcision. Moreover, in looking at the two situations, it's obvious that the 
defense of self-defense (which derives from the same unalienable right to 
life to which the crime of murder speaks) contains a mental state within its 
definition, as does the crime of murder. If there were a similar mental state 
in the crime of circumcision (e.g. removing someone else's foreskin with the 
intent to do grievous bodily harm), then one might say that the normal 
circumcision would never violate the law, and if the perpetrator did have the 
requisite intent, claiming religious justification might well not suffice as a 
defense.

Of course, a legislature creating a crime of circumcision could decide to allow 
medical exemptions  but not to allow a religious one (RFRA arguments, anyone? 
Would Lukumi apply?), but I still think that would be merely a trap for the 
unwary defendant who fails to allege medical motives.
On Thu, Jul 5, 2012 at 10:46 AM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
Here's an analogy from another area in which the normal rule - 
one person may not alter or injure another's body without permission - is 
relaxed: self-defense.

Say Vic is doing something that Don perceives as blasphemous, 
but that might also be dangerous to Don or Don's property.  (E.g., say Vic is 
burning a Koran and saying things that might reasonably lead Don - a Muslim - 
to think that Vic will imminently injure Don, or that the fire will spread to 
Don's property.)  Vic attacks Don using nondeadly force and injures him.

If Don reasonably believed that Vic was about to injure Don, 
and hit Don to prevent that, Don is not guilty of any crime, by reason of 
self-defense.  But say that the objective circumstances are the same, so that 
Don could have reasonably believed that Vic was about to injure him, but Don 
did not actually sincerely believe this.  Instead, he says that he attacked Vic 
because he thought God wanted him to attack Vic.  Then Don is guilty of 
assault; no self-defense defense is available (and I take it that we'd agree 
that no other defense should be available to him).  This rule does not treat 
religious reasons for hitting Vic worse than secular reasons generally.  But it 
does treat all reasons for hitting Vic worse than one favored secular reason - 
the perception that Vic poses an imminent danger to Don's person or property.

If I'm right on this, then I all think that there's no 
violation of the norm of equal treatment when we add another reason for 
allowing one person to alter or injure another's body: that the actor is the 
subject's parent and has a medical reason for ordering a surgery to the 
underage child.  That the parent has a right to alter the child's body for 
medical reasons doesn't mean he has a right to alter the child's body - even