The New York Review of Books <http://www.nybooks.com/index>  
________________________________

>  

Volume 52, Number 16 · October 20, 2005
<http://www.nybooks.com/contents/20051020> 


email icon <http://www.nybooks.com/images/email-icon.gif> Email to a friend
<javascript:popUp('article-email?article_id=18363')> 


Review


The Wars Over Evolution


By Richard C. Lewontin <http://www.nybooks.com/authors/4463> 


The Evolution–Creation Struggle
<http://service.bfast.com/bfast/click?bfmid=2181&sourceid=41397204&bfpid=067
4016874> 


by Michael Ruse


Harvard University Press, 327 pp., $25.95


Not By Genes Alone: How Culture Transformed Human Evolution
<http://service.bfast.com/bfast/click?bfmid=2181&sourceid=41397204&bfpid=022
6712842> 


by Peter J. Richerson and Robert Boyd


University of Chicago Press, 332 pp. $30.00


1.


The development of evolutionary biology has induced two opposite reactions,
both of which threaten its legitimacy as a natural scientific explana-tion.
One, based on religious convictions, rejects the science of evolution in a
fit of hostility, attempting to destroy it by challenging its sufficiency as
the mechanism that explains the history of life in general and of the
material nature of human beings in particular. One demand of those who hold
such views is that their competing theories be taught in the schools. 

The other reaction, from academics in search of a universal theory of human
society and history, embraces Darwinism in a fit of enthusiasm, threatening
its status as a natural science by forcing its explanatory scheme to account
not simply for the shape of brains but for the shape of ideas. The
Evolution–Creation Struggle is concerned with the first challenge, Not By
Genes Alone with the second. 

It is no surprise that Cardinal Christoph Schönborn has recently chosen the
Op-Ed page of The New York Times to enunciate the doctrine on evolution of
the new Benedictine papacy.[1] <http://www.nybooks.com/articles/18363#fn1>
Political and cultural struggle over the origin of life and of the human
species in particular has been a characteristically American phenomenon for
a century, providing Europeans (the French in particular) with yet another
example of la folie des Anglo-Saxons. In his essay, Cardinal Schönborn
accepts that human and other organisms have a common ancestry and, by
implication, that the species on earth today have evolved over a long period
from other species no longer extant. That is, he accepts the historical fact
that life has evolved. He distinguishes this acceptable fact of evolution
from what he characterizes as the unacceptable "neo-Darwinian" theory that,
in the words of the offi-cial 1992 Catechism of the Catholic Church of which
he was an editor, evolution is "reducible to pure chance and necessity." He
rejects, as he must, the Newtonian notion of first cause, that at the
beginning God only created a material mechanism with a few basic molecular
laws and that the rest of history has simply been the consequence of this
mechanism.

In the evolutionary process, he writes, there must have been "an internal
finality," the Divine plan. He calls attention to the fact that John Paul
II, who endorsed the science of evolution in his 1996 address to the
Pontifical Academy of Sciences, nevertheless insisted in his other writings
that there must also be such a principle of finality and direction built
into the material process. Such internal finality and direction cannot be
omitted from the minimal Christian position. For if evolution is only the
consequence of random mutations, none of which needs to have occurred, and
if the subsequent fate of those mutations is subject only to the relative
ability of their carriers to reproduce and to survive catastrophes of the
environment that eliminate species and make room for new ones, then rational
beings capable of moral choices might never have come into existence. But
without such beings the concept of Redemption is unintelligible.
Christianity demands, at the very least, the inevitable emergence of
creatures capable of sin. Without a history of human sin, there is no
Christ.

Everything else is up for grabs. Neither the Vatican nor much of quite
conventional Protestant theology demands that one take the story in Genesis
1 literally. Even William Jennings Bryan, famous as the prosecutor in the
Scopes trial in 1925, when called as a witness for the defense, confessed
that he did not much care whether God took six days or six hundred million
years to create the world. Moreover, even the minimalist Christian position
does not require the abandonment of the neo-Darwinian view of the mechanism
of evolution. It is quite possible to argue, as some of my believing
religious colleagues do, that God set the stage for evolution by natural
selection of undirected mutations, but that He reserved the ancestral line
destined to become human for special preservation and guidance.

________________________________

What, then, is the source of the repeated episodes of active political and
social agitation against the assertions of evolutionary science? One
apparent answer is that it is the expected product of fundamentalist belief,
which rejects the easy compromises of liberal exegesis and insists that
every word in Genesis means exactly what it says. Days are days, not eons.
But there's the rub. A literal reading of Genesis tells us that it took God
only three days to make the physical universe as it now exists, yet nuclear
physics and astrophysics claim a very old stellar system and provide the
instruments for the dating of bits and pieces of the earth and of fossils
spanning hundreds of millions of years. So why aren't Kansas schools under
extreme pressure to change the curriculum in physical science courses? Why
should physicists be allowed to propagate, unopposed, their godless accounts
of the evolution of the physical universe? Something more is at stake than a
disagreement over the literal truth of biblical metaphors. 

One way to understand the particular vulnerability of the science of
biological evolution to religious attack is to blame it on the biologists.
That is the message of Michael Ruse's The Evolution–Creation Struggle. Ruse,
a well-known philosopher of science, is not a creationist and is careful to
align himself with the Darwinian explanation of the origin and evolution of
species. He identifies his position on the existence of a higher power as
"somewhere between deist...and agnosticism." That is, he is committed to
giving natural explanations of natural phenomena as a methodological
principle, but he is not absolutely sure that every aspect of the world is,
in fact, nothing but the interactions of matter according to natural laws. 

His chief quarrel is not with evolutionary biology as a technical scientific
discipline, or even with its claim that the evolution of species has been a
purely material process, but rather with what he calls "evolutionism," a
commitment to a principle of universal long-term progress in the biological,
social, cultural, and political worlds. He identifies evolutionism as a form
of religion and portrays the conflict between creationism and evolutionism
as a fight between two religious doctrines, a struggle between
premillenialism, the doctrine that earthly perfection will only be achieved
after, and as a consequence, of the Second Coming, and postmillenialism, the
view that Christ will return, if at all, only after earthly paradise has
been achieved. Ruse sees evolutionary biology as having been permeated by
the idea of pro-gress and so, as a rhetorical device, iden-tifies it as
"postmillenial," but without any commitment to the Second Coming.

Ruse is certainly correct that notions of progress have recurred repeatedly
in evolutionary biology, especially in the nineteenth century. However, it
is not the ideology of progress that has characterized evolutionary theory,
not even at its nineteenth-century origins. Rather it was change, ceaseless
change, that was the ideological leitmotif of a revolutionary era. Ninety
years before Darwin's On the Origin of Species, Denis Diderot had his
dreaming philosopher d'Alembert ask,

        Who knows what races of animals preceded ours? Who knows what races
of animals will succeed ours? Everything changes, everything passes, only
the totality remains.[2] <http://www.nybooks.com/articles/18363#fn2>  

Nine years before the appearance of the Origin, Tennyson's In Memoriam
echoed Diderot. Is nature, while making individual death inevitable, at
least careful of the type?

        So careful of the type? But no.
        From scarped cliff and quarried stone
        She cries, "A thousand types are gone:
        I care for nothing, all shall go."

Herbert Spencer in his Progress: Its Law and Cause (1857) argued for change
as a general phenomenon, as a "beneficent necessity," citing historical
transformation in music, poetry, society, government, and language. But even
Spencer defined progress in a way that accorded with contemporary changes in
social and economic relations: 

        Leaving out of sight concomitants and beneficial consequences, let
us ask what progress is in itself.

        From the earliest traceable cosmical changes down to the latest
results of civilization, we shall find that the transformation of the
homogeneous into the heterogeneous is that in which progress consists.

What could have seemed more obvious to the mid-nineteenth-century observer
than the transformation of a relatively "homogeneous" society, characterized
by the "simple" agrarian life with the rural village its center, into one
marked by the booming, buzzing "heterogeneous" confusion of life in
industrial Manchester and London?

Darwin himself avoided implications of general progress or of
directionality. It should be noted that his great work is unideologically
titled On the Origin of Species, not On Evolution, and the word "evolution"
nowhere appears in the first edition of that work, which thus neatly avoids,
by intent or not, any implication of an unfolding of a progressive program.
Equally revealing is the title of his work on human evolution, a field in
which its more recent practitioners find notions of progress and
directionality all too tempting. Darwin's title is The Descent of Man.[3]
<http://www.nybooks.com/articles/18363#fn3>  The theory of evolution was not
a product of a commitment to progress but a reaction to a consciousness of
the instability of the social structures that characterized the bourgeois
revolutions and the radical changes in them. The Founding Fathers did not
promise us all eventual happiness, but only the freedom to run in pursuit of
it.

________________________________

Despite Darwin's caution, notions of progress and directionality have indeed
reappeared from time to time in evolutionary theory, especially in
discussions of human physical and cultural change. However, the modern
empirical science of evolutionary biology and the mathematical apparatus
that has been developed to make a coherent account of changes that result
from the underlying biological processes of inheritance and natural
selection do not make use of a priori ideas of progress. It is true, as Ruse
points out, that two of the originators of the mathematical formulation of
evolutionary dynamics were ideologically committed to some form of
meliorism, if not perfection. Ronald Fisher in England was an advocate of
eugenics, and both he and Sewall Wright in America formulated the principle
of natural selection as a process of increasing, from generation to
generation, the average fitness of members of a breeding population. Yet
these formulations make no predictions about a general progress of species. 

This may seem odd, since the process of natural selection is supposed to
make organisms more fit for their environment. So why does evolution not
result in a general increase of the fitness of life to the external world?
Wouldn't that be progress? The reason that there is no general progress is
that the environments in which particular species live are themselves
changing and, relative to the organisms, are usually getting worse. So most
of natural selection is concerned with keeping up. Certainly quite new kinds
of making a living have been occasionally exploited in evolution, but every
species eventually becomes extinct (99.9 percent already have) and no way of
making a living will be around forever.[4]
<http://www.nybooks.com/articles/18363#fn4>  Judging from the fossil record
a typical mammalian species lasts roughly ten million years, so we might
expect to last another nine million unless, as a consequence of our immense
ability to manipulate the physical world, we either extinguish ourselves a
good deal sooner or invent some extraordinary way to significantly postpone
the inevitable.

One of the most-cited results in evolutionary biology is the study by the
University of Chicago biologist Leigh Van Valen of the longevity of
Tennyson's "types." Van Valen reasoned that if there is a general increase
in the fitness of organisms then the length of time between the first
appearance of a kind of organism in the fossil record and its eventual
extinction should increase over the long run of geological time. But that is
not what has happened. He found that the average length of time from origin
to extinction of an invertebrate, as measured in the fossil record, has not
changed over evolutionary time. We have no evidence that this is not true
for species in general. So despite natural selection, things are not getting
any better over the long run. Van Valen called this phenomenon the
evolutionary "Red Queen," after the character in Through the Looking Glass
who found it necessary to run constantly just to keep up with a world that
was constantly moving beneath her. Unfortunately, in real life, the Queen
inevitably will tire, stumble, and be swept away.

________________________________

If we accept that evolutionary biology is not, in fact, committed to
progress, then we cannot accept Ruse's central contention that

        in both evolution and creation we have rival religious responses to
a crisis of faith—rival stories of origins, rival judgements about the
meaning of human life, rival sets of moral dictates and, above all, rival
eschatologies [i.e., premillenarian vs. postmillenarian].

Flowing from his view that scientific evolutionary biology can be turned
into a kind of religion, Ruse is worried that the commitment to using only
natural phenomena in the attempt to explain the history and variety of
organisms is a "slippery slope" down which evolutionists may glide from the
firm surface of hard-minded methodology, of which Ruse approves, into the
slough of unreflective metaphysical naturalism. We demand that our
scientific work be framed with reference only to material mechanisms that
can, at least in principle, be observed in nature because any other method
would lead us into a hopeless morass of uncheckable speculation that would
be the end of science. But we should not, in Ruse's view, confuse that rule
of conduct with a revelation of how the world really works. Maybe God is
lurking out there somewhere but He doesn't leave any residue in our test
tube, so we will be tempted to assume He doesn't exist. 

This is a philosopher's worry that does not, as far as I can tell,
correspond to the way people really acquire their views of reality. Some may
have had mountaintop conversions at some point in their lives, while others
experience a crisis of faith as they mature. Theodosius Dobzhansky, the
leading empirical evolutionary geneticist of the twentieth century, who
spent most of his life staring down a microscope at chromosomes, vacillated
between deism, gnosticism, and membership in the Russian Orthodox Church. He
could not understand how anyone on his or her deathbed could remain an
unrepentant materialist. I, his student and scientific epigone, ingested my
unwavering atheism and a priori materialism along with the spinach at the
parental dinner table. 


2.


The present struggle over evolution is often seen by defenders of Darwinism
as a culture war in which creationism is a part of a general right-wing
ideology that justifies an authoritarian, traditionalist society, protecting
"traditional values" against assaults from social revolutionaries intent on
overturning long-held moral values. It is certainly true that creationism is
far more popular in the rural South, the Midwest, and the Southwest among
supporters of the present Republican administration than among urban
Northern Democrats. But the evolution/creation struggle has a complex
history. Before World War II the science of evolution was virtually absent
from school curricula everywhere in America, although explicit creationism
was characteristic largely of the rural South and West. Then the atomic bomb
and, later, an immense increase in the public funding of science as a
response to the alarm raised by Sputnik resulted in a revolution in teaching
science. With support from the National Science Foundation, evolution became
a regular part of biology textbooks and science instruction in the public
schools and remains so in most places.

In response, among those who had never lost their traditional
fundamentalism, an active creationist reaction began, slowly accelerating to
its present prominence. According to a series of polls taken over the last
twenty-five years, about 50 percent of Americans believe that "God created
man pretty much in his present form at one time within the last 10,000
years."[5] <http://www.nybooks.com/articles/18363#fn5>  There have been
repeated recent attempts in Minnesota, New Mexico, Ohio, Pennsylvania,
Arkansas, and Kansas to make the study of challenges to evolutionary biology
part of the mandated public school science curriculum. These have so far not
succeeded, but Kansas seems on the verge of passing a statewide requirement
that a new variant of the Creation myth, "intelligent design," be part of
the discussion of evolution in public secondary schools. Intelligent design
(ID) has itself been intelligently designed to circumvent legal challenges
to the teaching of biblical creationism, challenges based on the
constitutional requirement of a separation of church and state. 

God, the Bible, and religion in general are not mentioned in the doctrine of
ID. Rather, it is claimed that an objective examination of the facts of life
makes it clear that organisms are too complex to have arisen by a process of
the accumulation of naturally selected chance mutations and so must have
been purposefully created by an unspecified intelligent designer. An alien
from outer space? But the theory of ID is a transparent subterfuge. The
problem is that if the living world is too complex to have arisen without an
intelligent designer, then where did the intelligent designer come from?
After all, she must have been as complex as the things she designed. If not,
then we have evolution! Otherwise we must postulate an intelligent designer
who designed the intelligent designer who..., back to the original one who
must have been around forever. And who might that be? Like the ancient
Hebrews the ID designers fear to pronounce Her name lest they be destroyed,
but Her initials are clearly YWH.

________________________________

The political identification of creationism with conservative politics is
recent. Before World War II, rural populism in the Southwest and Midwest,
motivated by resentment against politically and socially powerful Northern
urban elites, included both creationism and socialism. In the election of
1912, the poorest rural counties of Texas and Oklahoma and Arkansas gave
more votes to Eugene Debs than did the urban populations of Chicago and New
York. At the same time the best-selling weekly in America was the Appeal to
Reason, a socialist periodical published in Girard, Kansas. So, what's the
matter with Kansas these days? The shift of American populism from the left
to the right is part of the history of the disappearance of the American
left as a serious political force.

We see then that Christian fundamentalists have been historically inconstant
in their political preferences; and their demand for a public recognition of
the literal truth of Genesis has not, at least so far, included agitation
against the teachings of physical science. So the campaign against
evolutionary biology must be neither an integral part of the politics of the
right nor the consequence of a devotion in principle to a literal reading of
the Bible. How then are we to explain the continued strength of the campaign
against evolution? We can do no better than to listen to the Reverend Ron
Carlson, a popular preacher, lecturer, and author. He presents to his
audience two stories and asks them repeatedly whether it matters which one
is true. In the secular story,

        you are the descendant of a tiny cell of primordial protoplasm
washed up on an empty beach three and a half billion years ago. You are a
mere grab-bag of atomic particles, a conglomeration of genetic substance.
You exist on a tiny planet in a minute solar system... in an empty corner of
a meaningless universe. You came from nothing and are going nowhere.

By contrast, the Christian view is that

        you are the special creation of a good and all-powerful God. You are
the climax of His creation.... Not only is your kind unique, but you are
unique among your kind.... Your Creator loves you so much and so intensely
desires your companionship and affection that...He gave the life of His only
Son that you might spend eternity with Him.[6]
<http://www.nybooks.com/articles/18363#fn6>  

What is at issue here is whether the experience of one's family, social, and
working life, with its share of angst, pain, fatigue, and failure, can
provide meaning in the absence of a belief in an ordained higher purpose.
The continued appeal of a story of a divine creation of human life is that
it provides, for those for whom the ordinary experience of living does not,
a seductive relief from what Eric Fromm called the Anxiety of
Meaninglessness. The rest is commentary.


3.


At the same time that religious forces have been attempting to destroy
evolutionary biology by denying its truth, a movement within academia has
been attempting to make Darwinism a universal model for an understanding of
history and social dynamics. This movement has two roots in the traditions
of intellectual life. In their intellectual formation, natural scientists
have held up before them a model of scientific work that places a powerful
value on general applicability and on inclusiveness. "Great" scientists are
those who, like Newton, make laws that apply universally, while lesser ones
spend their lives dissecting particular phenomena. If Darwinism is to
satisfy the demand for generality then it must explain not only the
evolution of the physical structure of the organism but of its individual
and social behavior. 

At the same time natural science has increasingly provided a source of
academic legitimacy for inquiry that had previously been seen as a merely
impressionistic endeavor. Surely there must be laws of history rather than
just a narrative of one damned thing after another. Of course there is a
long tradition of attempts to find laws of history. In his Muqaddimah, the
fourteenth-century historian Ibn Khaldun formulated quantitative laws of
"universal" (i.e., Arab) history and five hundred years later Hegel lamented
that the problem for the historian was not to write history but to find a
general theoretical frame on which the facts can be hung. More recently the
study of history and social structures has often become "social science,"
with an apparatus of sample surveys and statistics. The searches for the
general in the biological sciences and for legitimacy in explaining human
social phenomena have converged in the creation of Darwinian models of human
nature, of culture, and of history. 

The first attempts at generalization, epitomized by E.O. Wilson's
Sociobiology: the Modern Synthesis, were simple extensions of evolutionary
theory within biology to nonphysical characters. A universal human nature
was described, including such properties as religiosity, aggression,
entrepreneurship, and conformity. Genes for these traits were postulated,
and adaptive stories were invented to explain why they were established by
natural selection. The credibility of these models was eventually undermined
by the lack of evidence of genetic determination of such traits and by the
slipperiness of attempts at trying to define the "universal" characteristics
of human nature. So when I once pointed out to a sociobiologist that sane
and rational human beings were willing to go to prison rather than engage in
armed struggle, he replied that their resistance to the state was a form of
aggression. One need not be an orthodox follower of Karl Popper to see that
a theory that allows things to appear in the form of their apparent
opposites when convenient is not of much value. 

Naive sociobiology then gave way to evolutionary psychology, which avoids
the danger of making predictions that are too specific and concerns itself
with the evolution of underlying behavioral mechanisms of sexual attraction,
fear of life-threatening circumstances, group cohesiveness, rationality, and
so on. Such explanations, however, do not do the work that historians and
sociologists require. For example, evolutionary psychology explains why
babies emit piercing howls and wails when they are hungry or uncomfortable.
They are helpless, and unless they can distract their parents from other
concerns they will not be sure they will be fed or rescued from pain.
Natural selection will then favor howling babies, since quiet ones may be
malnourished or suffer injuries and so are less likely to survive. 

________________________________

Of course the screams of a baby can be counterproductive since parents have
been known, in their frustration, to take drastic measures to quiet crying
babies, even to the point of killing them. These are to be seen as
pathological exceptions, however, when we take account of natural selection
in favor of maternal love, since parents who injure their children will have
fewer surviving offspring. While entirely plausible, such a theory does
nothing to explain historical and social differences in child-rearing
practices. As recently as the middle of the last century the administration
of a swat on the buttocks or a rather energetic shaking was an entirely
acceptable form of discipline for a recalcitrant child, but such behavior
now is grounds for criminal charges of child abuse. 

Evolutionary psychology also explains why all spoken languages must have
certain phonemic properties in order that hearers can distinguish one word
from another. The ability to distinguish similar spoken sounds is clearly of
survival value. A confusion between "That animal always calls when cornered"
and "That animal always kills when cornered" can lead to injury or death.
What evolutionary psychology does not tell us, however, is why some people
use clicks, some use rising and falling tones, why the kings of England
finally came around to speaking English at home instead of French, or how
the use of the periphrastic "do," as in the replacement of phrases like "I
go not" by "I do not go," grew in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries.
Evolutionary psychology is not a theory applicable to historical change and
cultural variation.

As a result, biological models of cultural change and diversity have been
replaced by pseudobiological models, using the structure of Darwinian
explanation metaphorically rather than literally. Darwinism is a
population-based theory consisting of three claims. First, there is
variation in some characteristics among individuals in a population. Second,
that variation is heritable. That is, offspring tend to resemble their
biological parents more than they do unrelated individuals. In modern
Darwinism the mechanism of that inheritance is information about development
that is contained in the genes that are passed from parent to offspring.
Third, there are different survival and reproduction rates among individuals
carrying different variants of a characteristic, depending on the
environment inhabited by the carriers. That is the principle of natural
selection. The consequence of differential reproduction of individuals with
different inherited variants is that the population becomes richer over
generations in some forms and poorer in others. The population evolves. 

A classic case is the evolution of mimicry in butterflies. Some butterflies
taste bad to their potential bird predators and the birds quickly learn from
a few revolting trials to recognize them by their wing coloration and to
avoid trying to eat them. Other species of butterflies that taste good have
evolved wing patterns that make them look like the nasty-tasting species,
and so are also avoided by their potential predators. This evolution was
possible because butterfly wing patterns are genetically variable from
individual to individual. In the past, an individual butterfly that tasted
good and whose wings somewhat resembled those of the uneatable species would
sometimes fool a bird and be spared from predation. The offspring of this
survivor would on average resemble it. Some would be lucky enough to have
combinations of genes from its two parents that resulted in its looking even
more like the nasty species and their lives would be even more likely to be
spared. The final result of these repeated generations of selection in favor
of the mimics would be the evolution of an essentially perfect mimic. 

Metaphorical Darwinian models of cultural and historical behavior do not
contain genes, but contain cultural variants that arise like gene mutations
and that are somehow differentially propagated over time in human minds and
institutions, resulting in cultural evolution. The first, rather simple
formulation of such a model in 1982 by Richard Dawkins[7]
<http://www.nybooks.com/articles/18363#fn7>  contains elementary particles
of culture, memes, playing the role of genes, which are propagated to
greater or lesser degrees because they are more or less appealing to people.
The memes might be ways of pronouncing the letter r, or whether the color
associated with death is white or black, or whether one prefers Luther to
the Pope. In this model human beings are the carriers of the cultural
particles, the physical propagators of these particles through
communication, and they provide the environment that determines which memes
are successful. 

________________________________

There have been a number of more or less complex variants on this original
elementary metaphor for genetic evolution and it is generally agreed that
the most nuanced and sophisticated version is contained in the work of
Robert Boyd and Peter Richerson, and laid out in considerable detail in Not
By Genes Alone. The title is meant to suggest that cultural evolution is not
simply like, but is part of, the entirety of human evolutionary change. The
authors begin by asserting, quite correctly, that culture is part of human
biology partly because evolved neural structures that underlie psychological
states must have some influence on what people believe and perceive and
partly because the culture creates an environment in which future physical
evolution by natural selection takes place. We could not have our present
automotive culture without a certain minimum of depth perception. Moreover,
since automobile accidents are the leading peacetime cause of death, by far,
among people of reproductive age in technologically advanced countries
(about one death per one hundred persons in this age group per generation in
the United States), genes that favor short reaction time to perceived danger
must be increasing in our population, slowly but inexorably. 

Richerson and Boyd reject the simplistic model of gene-like "memes," but
they are rather vague, as they must be, on how to recognize culture or its
structure. They are aware that one aspect of culture will change in reaction
to and in concert with other aspects of culture, that there is a complex
network of causal dependency among parts of culture. Changes in technology,
occupation, education, political attitudes, division of household labor and
parental responsibility, leisure activities, and styles of speech and dress
are connected as both causes and effects within and between generations.

The invention and spread of computers are the direct cause of major changes
in patterns of education and leisure as books are replaced by on-line
databases and computer games. They are the agents of the creation of new
occupations and new methods of work, of changes in vocabulary and in volume
and speed of interchange between individuals as well as the possibility that
one person can communicate with large populations without the intervention
and control of public media. They create the ability to purchase immediately
a vast array of goods and services and to have access to a vast quantity of
stored information. 

All of these changes in turn feed back onto the development of further
computer hardware and software, developments that amplify the effects
already seen and create new forms of production, commerce, communication,
and education. The difficulty that this complexity presents for making
models of cultural change and diversification is that it has no clear
structure. That structure has to be invented. 

________________________________

In Richerson and Boyd's formulation, cultural elements, ideas, tastes,
languages, and attitudes are properties of individual human carriers who
acquire them by a great variety of processes including conscious and
unconscious imitation of others, direct teaching by parents, learning in
formal educational settings, or by exposure to various forms of
communication. Changes in frequency of cultural variants among specific
populations occur by two basic mechanisms. First, there are biases in the
transmission of cultural elements, some elements being more popular or
easier to learn or simply more frequent among those from whom we acquire our
culture. That might explain the spread of, for example, hard rock. Second,
in a purely Darwinian mode, the carriers of some cultural variants may
survive better or have more children. All other things being equal, the
religious beliefs of those who oppose contraception on principle ought to be
spreading like wildfire. The differential rate of reproduction and the
biases in transmission are, of course, dependent on environment, but Boyd
and Richerson recognize that the human environment is itself largely a
consequence of culture so that cultural change is both the cause and effect
of further evolution.

This model has some shortcomings. One is that much of one's culture is not
acquired from other persons. When I walk down the street in Florence I do
not have to hear anyone speak or read any sign to know that I am not
anywhere in America. Buildings look strange, streets look strange, things
have a strange smell, people carry their bodies in an unfamiliar way. I
become conscious of a culture different from my own, a culture that I
acquired throughout my development simply by walking down the street and
being bombarded by sense impressions. Another is that no model of cultural
evolution of which I am aware takes account of power. The people of Bavaria
are predominantly Catholic while Westphalians are Protestant, not because
somehow Lutheranism was more appealing to northerners but because at
Augsburg in 1555 the warring German princes and the Holy Roman Emperor made
peace using the rule of cuius regio, eius religio, which allowed rulers to
enforce their own religion in their own dominions and to expel those who
were recalcitrant.

The most important question is why we should use a Darwinian model at all
for history and culture. The population model of variation, inheritance, and
different rates of reproduction has been specifically designed to explain a
particular set of natural phenomena that have a well-known empirical and
mechanistic base. Even Darwin, who had no idea of genes or of the rules of
inheritance, knew that organisms were reproduced only by other organisms,
that offspring resembled their parents more in concrete physical
characteristics than they resembled individuals not related to them, and
that more organisms were reproduced than could survive to reproductive age.
That was no guarantee that his model for evolution would have to be entirely
correct because it might have turned out that there was significant
inheritance of acquired characters. 

Cultural evolutionists have no set of phenomena of comparable concreteness.
They can't even reach an agreement on how to define and describe their
objects of interest. The arguments offered by Boyd and Richerson for
adopting a Darwinian model of cultural change are all epistemological: they
serve an intellectual interest but cannot be said to accord better with the
phenomena that they are meant to explain. They say of their arguments, for
example, that "they provide islands of conceptual clarity in the midst of
otherwise mind-numbing complexity and diversity"; that "they are productive
of further work"; that they are "economical" of human intellectual labor;
and that they will "increase the chance that we will detect useful
generalizations in spite of the complexity and diversity of human behavior."


That a theoretical formulation is desirable because it makes it easier and
more efficient to write more articles and books giving simple explanations
for phenomena that are complex and diverse seems a strange justification for
work that claims to be scientific. It confuses "understanding" in the weak
sense of making coherent and comprehensible statements about the real world
with "understanding" that means making correct statements about nature. It
makes the investigation of material nature into an intellectual game,
disarming us in our struggle to maintain science against mysticism. We would
be much more likely to reach a correct theory of cultural change if the
attempt to understand the history of human institutions on the cheap, by
making analogies with organic evolution, were abandoned. What we need
instead is the much more difficult effort to construct a theory of
historical causation that flows directly from the phenomena to be explained.
That the grand historical theorists of the past tried and failed to do this
does not foreclose further efforts. After all, Darwin was preceded by
eminent failures and even he did not get it all right.


Notes


[1] <http://www.nybooks.com/articles/18363#fnr1>  "Finding Design in
Nature," The New York Times, July 7, 2005.

[2] <http://www.nybooks.com/articles/18363#fnr2>  "Qui sçait les races
d'animaux qui nous ont précédé? Qui sçait les races d'animaux qui
succèderont aux nôtres? Tout change, tout passe, il n'y a que le tout qui
reste." Le Rêve de d'Alembert.

[3] <http://www.nybooks.com/articles/18363#fnr3>  As compared to the book of
an eminent anthropologist of the last generation, Earnest A. Hooten, Up from
the Ape (Macmillan, 1946).

[4] <http://www.nybooks.com/articles/18363#fnr4>  Indeed, life on earth is
about half over. It has been around for about two billion years and from our
knowledge of the changes that occur in stars, the sun will become a "red
giant" destroying the earth and other planets in another two billion years
or so.

[5] <http://www.nybooks.com/articles/18363#fnr5>  Otis Dudley Duncan and
Claudia Geist, "The Creationists: How Many, Who, and Where?" Reports of the
National Center for Science Education, Vol. 24, No. 5 (September–October
2004), pp. 26–33.

[6] <http://www.nybooks.com/articles/18363#fnr6>  Ron Carlson and Ed Decker,
Fast Facts on False Teachings (Harvest House, 2003).

[7] <http://www.nybooks.com/articles/18363#fnr7>  Richard Dawkins, The
Extended Phenotype: The Gene as the Unit of Selection (Freeman, 1982).



_______________________________________________
Marxism-Thaxis mailing list
Marxism-Thaxis@lists.econ.utah.edu
To change your options or unsubscribe go to:
http://lists.econ.utah.edu/mailman/listinfo/marxism-thaxis

Reply via email to