Setting aside Smith's exception for Sherbert, and setting aside 
the argument that South Carolina law's protection of Sunday observers 
discriminated against Saturday observers, I would agree with the dissent in 
Sherbert.  That unemployment compensation law has a "good cause" exemption, 
under which some secular causes are treated as sufficient but many as 
insufficient, doesn't mean that religious causes should be treated as well as 
the favored secular causes.

By analogy, as I mentioned, murder law has an exception for "adequate 
provocation" (which reduces the charge to manslaughter).  Copyright law has an 
exception for "fair use."  The duty to testify has an exemption for those 
privileges that courts create in light of experience and reason, as well as the 
Rule 403 free-form admissibility balancing.  Title VII has an exception for 
"bona fide occupational qualifications."  In many states, many criminal laws 
have a free-form "lesser evil" defense.  Trespass law has a "private necessity" 
defense.  Nuisance law in many jurisdictions involves pretty free-form 
balancing, as does negligence law.  It doesn't follow, I think, that claims for 
religious exemptions - entitlement to a manslaughter defense when the 
provocation is blasphemy, entitlement to use others' copyrighted works for any 
religious reasons, the right to refuse to testify when one thinks testimony 
would be religiously wrong, the right not to hire women when one's religion so 
calls, the right to escape criminal liability or trespass tort liability 
because of "religious necessity," the right to interfere with others' enjoyment 
of their property when one has religious justification, or the right to have 
one's actions that injure another's property be declared "reasonable" because 
of one's religious motivations - should be treated as favorably as the most 
favorably treated secular motivations.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Christopher Lund
Sent: Wednesday, February 15, 2012 11:55 AM
To: 'Law & Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as 
failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

Similar question: Eugene, how would you today decide Sherbert v. Verner, with 
its "good cause" requirement?

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Scarberry, Mark
Sent: Wednesday, February 15, 2012 2:32 PM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as 
failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

Eugene,

I will try to respond to your hypos later today, but here is a non-hypothetical 
question: Do you think Fraternal Order of Police v. Newark was correctly 
decided?

Best,
Mark

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Wednesday, February 15, 2012 9:44 AM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as 
failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

                Mark:  A few hypotheticals:  (1)  Say that a state provides 
that adequate provocation makes killing manslaughter rather than murder, and 
that a particular set of behaviors - having sex with the defendant's spouse, 
having just beaten a defendant (but in a situation where the peril is over and 
no self-defense is allowed), and some other things - qualify as adequate 
provocation.  And say that this defense is indeed used in dozens of cases a 
year.  Someone kills someone for what he perceives is blasphemy, and argues 
that his religious sense of provocation should be treated the same as the 
provocation in the adultery, assault, etc. examples, so that he would be guilty 
only of manslaughter rather than murder.  He argues that this presumptively 
entitles him to an exemption, and that it indeed the presumption can't be 
rebutted under strict scrutiny because murder law is underinclusive.

                (2)  Someone feels a religious obligation not to testify 
against his children or parents, or against coreligionists, or in other 
contexts.  He points to all the privileges recognized as defenses to the duty 
to testify, and argues that these exceptions presumptively entitle him to an 
exemption, and that indeed the presumption can't be rebutted under strict 
scrutiny because the duty to testify is underinclusive.

                (3)  Someone feels a religious obligation not to hire women to 
work together with men, or not to hire women with small children at home.  He 
points to the BFOQ exemption and to the exemption for small employers, both of 
which would exclude many more employees from Title VII's protection than would 
his proposed exemption.  He argues that these exceptions presumptively entitle 
him to an exemption, and that indeed the presumption can't be rebutted under 
strict scrutiny because antidiscrimination law is underinclusive.

                (4)  Someone feels a religious obligation to spread the word of 
God for free; that word happens to be in a book whose copyright is owned by 
others.  His claim isn't just to a right to do this in church, but to a right 
to do this everywhere.  He points to the many exceptions from copyright law, 
from 17 USC 107 to 17 USC 122 (each of the sixteen sections contains at least 
one exemption).  He argues that these exceptions presumptively entitle him to 
an exemption, and that indeed the presumption can't be rebutted under strict 
scrutiny because copyright law is underinclusive.

                Is it really the case that all these laws should be subject to 
strict scrutiny - especially given that the underinclusiveness prong of strict 
scrutiny might well make the laws invalid under such a test?

                My thinking is that the answer is no.  Most laws involve the 
reconciliation of competing interests, including competing private interests 
that the government is trying to protect; and I don't think that the fact that 
someone has a religious motivation to do something constitutionally entitles 
him to the best treatment available to others.  That my rights as a copyright 
owner are limited in some ways to serve rival concerns doesn't mean that 
there's a constitutional obligation on the government's part to limit them 
further in order to serve some people's view of what God demands - a view that 
is not my view, and to which my rights should not, I think, bend.  But whatever 
one might think of this as a matter of first principles, it seems to me that 
this "most favored nations" approach likely yields results, in cases such as 
the ones I described above, that are rightly seen as improper.

                Eugene



From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu<mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu> 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]<mailto:[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]>
 On Behalf Of Scarberry, Mark
Sent: Wednesday, February 15, 2012 9:16 AM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Laws with exceptions as triggering strict scrutiny -- and as 
failing strict scrutiny because of their underinclusiveness?

Paul rightly asks us to consider more than just formalism. History is 
important, and I think the concern about freedom of the church goes back at 
least to Pope Gregory (?) in the 11th (?) Century. Cf. Antigone.

I've suggested elsewhere that a historical approach to what constitutes free 
exercise might help us understand it. But here is some more somewhat 
formalistic analysis:

I have always understood the general applicability test to involve a kind of 
most favored nations concern. Are other exceptions allowed to undercut the 
basis purpose of a law to roughly the same degree that a religious exception 
would undercut it? If so, the law is not of general applicability. For example, 
if a prohibition law permitted sale and consumption of beer it would need to 
permit sale and consumption of wine for communion or for Shabbat or Passover 
dinners. If there is a copyright law exception for fair use of music in 
schools, then an exception must be made for church services. Justice (then 
Judge) Alito made this point in Fraternal Order of Police v. City of Newark (3d 
Cir. 1989):

"Because the Department makes exemptions from its policy for secular reasons 
and has not offered any substantial justification for refusing to provide 
similar treatment for officers who are required to wear beards for religious 
reasons, we conclude that the Department's policy violates the First Amendment."

I think that this is a kind of mid-level under-inclusiveness requirement, but 
one that is used not in applying a level of scrutiny but in deciding what level 
of scrutiny to apply. From Lukumi Babalu Aye v. City of Hialeah:

"The ordinances are underinclusive for those ends. They fail to prohibit 
nonreligious conduct that endangers these interests in a similar or greater 
degree than Santeria sacrifice does. The underinclusion is substantial, not 
inconsequential."

Thus the prohibition on animal sacrifice was not generally applicable. I 
realize that there is other language in the case that focuses on the targeting 
of religious conduct, on the point that practically the only conduct prohibited 
was religious. Yet I think the quoted principle captures the basic meaning of 
"generally applicable."

Of course all of these concepts are somewhat manipulable. What is the purpose 
of laws against murder? To prevent killing? To prevent unjustified killing? To 
protect the innocent? Under some of these formulations a defense of 
self-defense could make a murder law not generally applicable in a formalistic 
sense. But of course our history will prevent murder laws from being 
invalidated with respect to human sacrifice, even of a volunteer. You might say 
that background legal principles frame the analysis. We value innocent life. 
Thus historically we have permitted private self-defense against attackers, but 
we do not otherwise allow the private intentional killing of a human being 
except where there is not enough time to get the govt involved. If unenumerated 
but firmly historically rooted rights (e.g, some parental rights) are 
constitutionally protected under Due Process, as I think even Justice Scalia 
accepts, then it makes some sense to consult history as we try to understand a 
right specifically enumerated in the First Amendment. Almost all legal concepts 
are manipulable, but that does not mean they are useless. And even laws not of 
general applicability will be enforceable against religious conduct if the govt 
interest is strong enough, which gives us an out from a too-formalistic 
application of the requirement.

I suppose a historical approach might have led to a different result in Lukumi. 
That may cut against it. Animal sacrifice has been seen for quite a long time 
to be foreign (literally) to the exercise of religion in the US. (A cousin told 
me of an animal sacrifice done next to her condo building by some 
middle-eastern immigrants to cleanse the building of the effects of a suicide. 
The immigrants were neither Jewish nor mainstream Muslim, as I understand it.) 
Yet we do eat animals in celebrations that have religious or cultural 
significance (e.g., Thanksgiving turkey). We even grant mercy to such animals 
at times. Consider presidential pardons of Thanksgiving turkeys. And there is a 
need to adjust historical analysis to protect religions that are new to our 
society. Perhaps the general applicability requirement would help us do the 
needed historical adjustment.

Best,
Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
_______________________________________________
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Reply via email to