Daniel Dennett: 'You can make Aristotle look like a flaming idiot'

Daniel Dennett, a cheerleader for Darwin and atheism, attracts fierce
criticism for his views on free will. He talks about his new book and
explains why philosophers have to walk a tightrope


  [Daniel Dennett ]

Big thinkers make for big targets and they don't come much bigger,
physically and intellectually, than Daniel Dennett
<http://www.guardian.co.uk/science/dennett> . The tall, 71-year-old
philosopher looks every inch the enthusiastic sailor he is, with his
white beard and broad torso. With his mild-mannered, avuncular
confidence, he comes across a man who could calmly fend off an assault
or two. That's just as well, since as a leading cheerleader for Darwin
and atheism, he is as much a bete noire for their opponents as a hero
for their advocates.


His critics agree, to the extent that they see him as a clever
philosophical trickster. Yet time and again it seems the best way to
understand Dennett is to understand why so many criticisms miss their
targets.Dennett is in London from his native Massachusetts talking to me
about his latest book,Intuition Pumps and Other Tools for Thinking
<http://www.guardian.co.uk/books/2013/may/19/daniel-dennett-intuition-pu\
mps-thinking-extract> . It's a kind of greatest hits collection, pieced
together from mainly previously published work to present both a
summation of his central ideas about meaning, consciousness, evolution
and free will, and to share some of the philosophical tools he has used
to craft them. "After half a century in the field I've got some tricks
of the trade which I'd like to talk about," he says.

Most assaults are variations on the theme that Dennett takes a too
narrowly scientific worldview. The late Stephen Jay Gould
<http://www.guardian.co.uk/education/2002/may/22/medicalscience.internat\
ionaleducationnews> , for instance, coined the "shocking" terms
"ultra-Darwinist" and "Darwinian fundamentalist" to hurl at him. Yet
Dennett has consistently resisted the crude extension of scientific
thinking into areas where it does not belong. Nowhere is this more
evident than in the issue of free will, which he describes in the book
as "the most difficult and the most important philosophical problem
confronting us today".

"It's important because of the longstanding tradition that free will is
a prerequisite for moral responsibility," he says. "Our system of law
and order, of punishment, and praise and blame, promise keeping, promise
making, the law of contracts, criminal law – all of this depends on
one notion or another of free will. And then you have neuroscientists,
physicists and philosophers saying that 'science has shown us that free
will is an illusion' and then not shrinking from the implication that
our systems of law are built on foundations of sand."

Dennett argues: "There is nothing we have learned from neuroscience that
undercuts the foundation for both the law of contract and criminal law."
It is true that we do not have "ultimate responsibility" because our
choices are always in some ways the result of things we didn't choose,
such as our core personalities and the values we have absorbed from our
society and families. But we have enough self-control to make sense of
the difference between the psychopath and the criminal murder, the
person who murders unwittingly in a sleepwalk and the cold-blooded
killer.

That is the kind of free will we need and is worth wanting. Dennett
worries that there is good evidence that promulgating the idea that free
will is an illusion undermines just that sense of responsibility many
scientists and philosophers are worried about losing. Critics maintain
that Dennett's kind of free will, with its modest idea of "enough"
responsibility, autonomy and control, is not really enough after all.

There's a pattern here, "the story of my life", as Dennett puts it.
People assume unrealistic ideals of what free will, selfhood or
rationality are and then get upset when Dennett says: "It's not the
overwhelming supercalifragilisticexpialidocious phenomenon that you
thought it was." But it's still real enough. The problem is simply:
"Both free will and consciousness have been, by my lights, inflated in
the popular imagination and in the philosophical imagination," and so
"anybody who has a view of either one that is chopped down to size" is
accused of "a wretched subterfuge", as Kant memorably put it.

This can't be explained wholly in cold, rational terms. There is also an
"emotional stake that philosophers often have and betray in their
argumentation", which "it's dangerous and also even verges on offensive
to draw attention" to. "I see what I think is white-knuckled fear
driving people to defend views that are not really well-motivated, but
they want to dig the moat a little further out than is defensible
because they're afraid of the thin end of the wedge."

Some, however, accuse the "new atheists" of being motivated by fears and
less than generous prejudices of their own. The most serious charge is
that they attack the most simplistic forms of religious belief and leave
their most intellectually subtle versions untouched. Dennett
acknowledges "there's some smidgen of truth" in that, but insists: "They
bring it on themselves by changing the rules and shifting the goalposts.
You ask them: 'What do you actually mean, what do you actually
believe?'" But "the real claim won't sit down and be examined and so
after a while you get impatient with that. I have made a concerted
effort over the years to understand sophisticated philosophical theology
and have never come up with anything that I thought could sit in the
light of day and be defended."

He also points out: "The spokespeople for religion who chastise the new
atheists for this philistine dismissal of their sophisticated work are
not speaking for your average churchgoer, certainly not in the United
States."

He may not be crudely scientistic, but it is true that these days
Dennett spends more time around scientists than other philosophers. "I
find the discoveries in those fields mind candy, just delicious," he
says. "If I go to a scientific conference I come away with a bunch of
new things to think about. If I go to a philosophy
<http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/philosophy>  conference I may come away
just having learned four more wrinkles in the debate about something
philosophers have been thinking about for all my life."

But Dennett also maintains that we need philosophy to protect us from
scientific overreach. "The history of philosophy is the history of very
tempting mistakes made by very smart people, and if you don't learn that
history you'll make those mistakes again and again and again. One of the
ignoble joys of my life is watching very smart scientists just reinvent
all the second-rate philosophical ideas because they're very tempting
until you pause, take a deep breath and take them apart."

Ridicule and misrepresentation are in some sense an occupational hazard
for the philosopher. "The best philosophers are always walking a
tightrope where one misstep either side is just nonsense," he says.
"That's why caricatures are too easy to be worth doing. You can make any
philosopher – any, Aristotle, Kant, you name it – look like a
complete flaming idiot with just a slightest little tweak."

His courting of a popular audience also unfairly undermines his
credibility in a profession that has little concern or sometimes even
respect for the wider public conversation. His often breezy tone only
makes it worse. "They want you to take it seriously!" he mocks in a
suitably pompous voice. "I do take it very seriously, but not solemnly."

Dennett is also unashamedly expansive in a way that goes against the
academic grain, trying to paint the bigger picture of the biggest issues
of the day. In contrast, he believes: "One of the real problems in
philosophy is that people can be a little bit myopic." The nadir of this
narrow insularity came while Dennett was a graduate student in the 60s.
"It was comically cautious and unambitious. The very idea of trying for
a large view of anything! This was miniature little piecework stuff. I
thought it was dreadful."

Public intellectuals can come in the role of the helpful clarifier or
the challenging provocateur. Dennett sees himself as the former, and is
"sometimes quite taken aback that people are so provoked". His best
explanation for this is that a lot of what he does is about dissolving
the mysteries that surround ideas such as selfhood and consciousness. "I
think the people who don't like magic tricks explained to them are also
the people who don't like free will explained to them, or consciousness.
'How rude! How philistine, to explain, to even try! How dare you!'"

But Dan dares, and, like what he says or not, few do so with such
intelligence, insight and flair.




http://www.guardian.co.uk/science/2013/may/22/daniel-dennett-aristotle-f\
laming-idiot
<http://www.guardian.co.uk/science/2013/may/22/daniel-dennett-aristotle-\
flaming-idiot>

Reply via email to