Hi, Well, I tried your definitions about P and Q, they still difference at only the (co)induction theorems. So if we have:
val (Q_rules, Q_coind, Q_cases) = Hol_coreln `Q (SUC n) ==> Q n` ; (* all numbers *) how can we prove `!n. Q n` ? Regards, Chun > Il giorno 20 gen 2017, alle ore 14:26, Jeremy Dawson > <jeremy.daw...@anu.edu.au> ha scritto: > > Hi Chun, > > I don't think your example captures the distinction, since, as you > prove, AList and BList are the same. > > you're right about > >> 1. [] is List >> and >> 2. If l = h::t and t is List, then l is List. > > In fact the only subset satisfying these (which is therefore both the > least and the greatest) is the set of all lists. > > Think instead about > > Hol_reln `P (SUC n) ==> P n` ; (* no numbers *) > Hol_coreln `Q (SUC n) ==> Q n` ; (* all numbers *) > > Cheers, > > Jeremy > > On 20/01/17 22:07, Chun Tian (binghe) wrote: >> Hi Michael, >> >> It took me some time to think about your words and learn co-induction. >> I'm no expert, but I don't agree with the opinion that "leastness is >> captured by the induction principle". Here is my argument: >> >> 1. Your "AList" definition must come from the following Hol_reln definition: >> >> val (AList_rules, AList_ind, AList_cases) = Hol_reln >> `(!l. (l = []) ==> isAList l) /\ >> (!l h t. (l = h::t) /\ isAList t ==> isAList l)`; >> >> because the generated AList_cases is exactly the same as the one you gave: >> >> val AList_cases = >> |- ∀a0. isAList a0 ⇔ (a0 = []) ∨ ∃h t. (a0 = h::t) ∧ isAList t: >> thm >> >> val AList_ind = >> |- ∀isAList'. >> (∀l. (l = []) ⇒ isAList' l) ∧ >> (∀l h t. (l = h::t) ∧ isAList' t ⇒ isAList' l) ⇒ >> ∀a0. isAList a0 ⇒ isAList' a0: >> thm >> >> val AList_rules = >> |- (∀l. (l = []) ⇒ isAList l) ∧ >> ∀l h t. (l = h::t) ∧ isAList t ⇒ isAList l: >> thm >> >> 2. You're right that, an co-induction of the same relation (or we should >> say, the same rules), would give us the same cases theorem, so let me >> define it with a different name, BList: >> >> val (BList_rules, BList_coind, BList_cases) = Hol_coreln >> `(!l. (l = []) ==> isBList l) /\ >> (!l h t. (l = h::t) /\ isBList t ==> isBList l)`; >> >> it generated the following things: >> >> val BList_cases = >> |- ∀a0. isBList a0 ⇔ (a0 = []) ∨ ∃h t. (a0 = h::t) ∧ isBList t: >> thm >> >> val BList_coind = >> |- ∀isBList'. >> (∀a0. isBList' a0 ⇒ (a0 = []) ∨ ∃h t. (a0 = h::t) ∧ isBList' t) ⇒ >> ∀a0. isBList' a0 ⇒ isBList a0: >> thm >> >> val BList_rules = >> |- (∀l. (l = []) ⇒ isBList l) ∧ >> ∀l h t. (l = h::t) ∧ isBList t ⇒ isBList l: >> thm >> >> 3. Now I can formally prove AList and BList is really the same thing >> (!l. isBList l = isAList l): >> >> val A2B = store_thm ("A2B", ``!l. isAList l ==> isBList l``, >> HO_MATCH_MP_TAC AList_ind >>>> RW_TAC bool_ss [BList_rules]); >> >> val B2A = store_thm ("B2A", ``!l. isBList l ==> isAList l``, >> Induct >>> | [ RW_TAC bool_ss [AList_rules, BList_rules], >> STRIP_TAC >>>> ONCE_REWRITE_TAC [BList_cases] >>>> ONCE_REWRITE_TAC [AList_cases] >>>> REPEAT STRIP_TAC >>> | [ ASM_REWRITE_TAC [], >> SIMP_TAC list_ss [] >>>> `t = l` by PROVE_TAC [CONS_11] >>>> PROVE_TAC [] ] ]); >> >> val AB_same = store_thm ("AB_same", ``!l. isBList l = isAList l``, >> PROVE_TAC [A2B, B2A]); >> >> now I want to say AList_ind and BList_coind are actually derived from >> the same rules for the same relation, they themselves didn't show any >> essential characteristics of the defined object (AList or BList here). >> >> P. S. This sounds like we could have another stronger Hol_reln (or >> Hol_coreln), which could return both induction and coinduction theorems >> at the same time for the same given rules. >> >> 4. So where are the words "least" and "maximal" coming from inductive >> and coinductive definitions? I think for the *same* relation we can >> always define it using either inductive or coinductive ways: >> >> (Inductive) A "List" is defined as the least subset of HOL type "list", >> such that: >> >> 1. [] is List >> and >> 2. If l = h::t and t is List, then l is List. >> >> The defined concept "List" is the interaction of all 1-ary relation >> satisfying above property. Consider the extreme case: List = (\l. T) >> also satisfy above property. >> >> (Co-inductive) A "List" is defined as the maximal (greatest) subset of >> HOL type "list", such that: >> >> If l is List, then >> 1. l is [] >> or >> 2. ?h t. (l = h::t and t is List) >> >> The defined concept "List" is the union of all 1-ary relation satisfying >> above property. Consider the extreme case: List = (\l. F) also satisfy >> above property. >> >> Both Hol_reln and Hol_coreln only accept the inductive approach when >> defining any relation, that is, conjunction clauses having "==> R x y" >> as the conclusion part. Thus, we must *always* understand these rules as >> the *least* relation satisfying the rules. >> >> As for the purpose of induction theorems and co-induction theorems, I >> think they help us to prove different kinds of theorems on relations. >> Watching the position of "P l" in the conclusion part of these >> (co)induction theorems: >> >> val AList_ind = >> |- ∀P. >> (∀l. l = [] ⇒ P l) ∧ >> (∀l. (∀h t. l = h::t ∧ P t) ⇒ P l) ⇒ >> ∀l. isAList l ⇒ P l: >> thm >> >> val BList_coind = >> |- ∀P. >> (∀l. P l ⇒ l = [] ∨ (∃h t. l = h::t ∧ P t)) ⇒ >> ∀l. P l ⇒ isBList l: >> thm >> >> Suppose I have a 1-ary relation (or predicate) about "Man". The >> induction theorem could help us to prove something like: >> >> If x is a Man, then ... (e.g. x is an animal) >> >> (Most of time we want to prove this kind of theorems using the defined >> relation) while the co-induction theorem could help us to prove things like: >> >> If ... (e.g. x is John), then x is a Man. >> >> Also recall in Wikipedia's "Coinduction" page [1], it says "As a >> definition or specification, coinduction describes how an object may be >> "observed", "broken down" or "destructed" into simpler objects. As a >> proof technique, it may be used to show that an equation is satisfied by >> all possible implementations of such a specification." (keyword: >> specification) >> >> [1] https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Coinduction >> >> Comments are welcome ... >> >> Regards, >> >> Chun Tian >> >> >> On 19 January 2017 at 00:23, <michael.norr...@data61.csiro.au >> <mailto:michael.norr...@data61.csiro.au>> wrote: >> >> Note that the cases theorem does not capture “leastness”. A >> coinductive definition of the same relation would give you the same >> cases theorem. The cases theorem is just giving you the fix-point >> property. ____ >> >> __ __ >> >> One easy example for thinking about these sorts of things is lists. >> Imagine you have:____ >> >> __ __ >> >> isAList l ól = [] \/ ?h t. l = h::t /\ isAList t____ >> >> __ __ >> >> (where l ranges over a type large enough to encompass lists and lazy >> lists both, and the isAList predicate is identifying the appropriate >> subsets of that type).____ >> >> __ __ >> >> If the cases theorem is true for algebraic and co-algebraic lists >> then leastness and greatness must be captured elsewhere. In fact, >> leastness is captured by the induction principle which says____ >> >> __ __ >> >> P [] /\ (!h t. P t ==> P(h::t)) ==> !l. isAList l ==> P l____ >> >> __ __ >> >> Michael____ >> >> __ __ >> >> __ __ >> >> *From: *"Chun Tian (binghe)" <binghe.l...@gmail.com >> <mailto:binghe.l...@gmail.com>> >> *Date: *Wednesday, 18 January 2017 at 21:58 >> *To: *hol-info <hol-info@lists.sourceforge.net >> <mailto:hol-info@lists.sourceforge.net>> >> *Subject: *[Hol-info] How to prove this theorem about relations?____ >> >> __ __ >> >> Hi, ____ >> >> __ __ >> >> Sorry for disturbing again, but I met new difficulties when proving >> theorems about relations.____ >> >> __ __ >> >> Suppose I have the following simple recursive datatype and a "sub >> formula" relation about it:____ >> >> __ __ >> >> val _ = Datatype `form = atom 'a | dot form form`;____ >> >> __ __ >> >> val (subF_rules, subF_ind, subF_cases) = Hol_reln____ >> >> `(!(A:'a form). subF A A) /\____ >> >> (!(A:'a form) B C. subF A B ==> subF A (dot B C)) `;____ >> >> __ __ >> >> Now I need to prove this goal: `!A a. subF A (atom a) ==> (A = atom >> a)`.____ >> >> __ __ >> >> I have successfully proved some theorems about relations defined by >> Hol_reln, but this one brings some difficulties that I never met >> before.____ >> >> __ __ >> >> The main problem is, "atom" never appears in the definition of >> Hol_reln, thus I don't have any theorem talking about it.____ >> >> __ __ >> >> But I recall the fact that, an inductive relation defines the >> *least* relation satisfying the rules, thus anything undefined is by >> default false. I believe this fact has been correctly captured by >> (and only by) subF_cases generated from above Hol_reln definition:____ >> >> __ __ >> >> val subF_cases =____ >> >> |- ∀a0 a1. subF a0 a1 ⇔ (a1 = a0) ∨ ∃B C. (a1 = dot B C) ∧ subF >> a0 B:____ >> >> thm____ >> >> __ __ >> >> If I do cases analysis on `A`, I got a seeming good start point:____ >> >> __ __ >> >>> e (Cases_on `A:'a form`);____ >> >> OK..____ >> >> 2 subgoals:____ >> >> val it =____ >> >> ∀a. subF (dot f f0) (atom a) ⇒ (dot f f0 = atom a)____ >> >> ∀a'. subF (atom a) (atom a') ⇒ (atom a = atom a')____ >> >> 2 subgoals____ >> >> : proof____ >> >> __ __ >> >> But I still don't know how to prove any of these sub-goals. I have >> no useful theorems for rewrite or anything else. The relation rules >> only tells me that, forall A, (subFor A A) is true, but it didn't >> say anything about the other direction: (subF A B) => A = B (if A >> and B are both shapes like (atom ...)____ >> >> __ __ >> >> Also, I even don't know how to prove this fundamental truth about >> datatypes: ``(atom A) = (atom B) ==> A = B``, again, I have no >> theorems to use ... because the Datatype definition didn't return >> anything that I can (directly) use inside a store_thm().____ >> >> __ __ >> >> On the other side, Coq proves the same theorem quite simply:____ >> >> __ __ >> >> Lemma subAt :____ >> >> forall (Atoms : Set) (A : Form Atoms) (at_ : Atoms),____ >> >> subFormula A (At at_) -> A = At at_.____ >> >> intros Atoms A at_ H.____ >> >> inversion H.____ >> >> reflexivity.____ >> >> Qed.____ >> >> __ __ >> >> Need help ...____ >> >> __ __ >> >> Regards,____ >> >> __ __ >> >> Chun Tian (binghe)____ >> >> University of Bologna (Italy)____ >> >> __ __ >> >> >> >> ------------------------------------------------------------------------------ >> Check out the vibrant tech community on one of the world's most >> engaging tech sites, SlashDot.org! http://sdm.link/slashdot >> _______________________________________________ >> hol-info mailing list >> hol-info@lists.sourceforge.net <mailto:hol-info@lists.sourceforge.net> >> https://lists.sourceforge.net/lists/listinfo/hol-info >> <https://lists.sourceforge.net/lists/listinfo/hol-info> >> >> >> >> >> -- >> --- >> >> Chun Tian (binghe) >> University of Bologna (Italy) >> >> >> >> ------------------------------------------------------------------------------ >> Check out the vibrant tech community on one of the world's most >> engaging tech sites, SlashDot.org! http://sdm.link/slashdot >> >> >> >> _______________________________________________ >> hol-info mailing list >> hol-info@lists.sourceforge.net >> https://lists.sourceforge.net/lists/listinfo/hol-info >> > > ------------------------------------------------------------------------------ > Check out the vibrant tech community on one of the world's most > engaging tech sites, SlashDot.org! http://sdm.link/slashdot > _______________________________________________ > hol-info mailing list > hol-info@lists.sourceforge.net > https://lists.sourceforge.net/lists/listinfo/hol-info
signature.asc
Description: Message signed with OpenPGP using GPGMail
------------------------------------------------------------------------------ Check out the vibrant tech community on one of the world's most engaging tech sites, SlashDot.org! http://sdm.link/slashdot
_______________________________________________ hol-info mailing list hol-info@lists.sourceforge.net https://lists.sourceforge.net/lists/listinfo/hol-info