With a correction in the formal logical relations table. Sorry about that. - Ben
 
----- Original Message -----
Jim,
 
>[Jim Willgoose] Peirce says,
"Very many writers assert that everything is logically possible which involves no contradiction. Let us call that sort of logical possibility, essential, or formal, logical possibility. It is not the only logical possibility; for in this sense, two propositions contradictory of one another may both be severally possible, although their combination is not possible." (CP3:527)
 
Just as I thought, Peirce does not discuss modal propositions in the passage which you had in mind.
 
>[Jim] Two propositions, "Bs" and "-Bs" may both be possible. ( severally) But, the proposition "pos Bs & poss.-Bs" is not possible. The first two propositions are not contradictory of one another.
 
In the context of oppositions, the contradictory of a proposition is the _negation_ /of that proposition. "Bs" ("This stove is black") and "-Bs" ("This stove is not black") are contradictory of one another. They can't both be true and they can't both be false. Thus they fit the form defined in the logic of oppositions for contradictories.
 
"Bs" and "-Bs" are both internally consistent but are inconsistent with each other. That is all that Peirce is implying, nothing more.
 
You are confusing formal logical properties with logical _expression_ of modality in just such a way that, ironically, you call impossible the same modal statement which can be used in order to express the idea that two propositions are severally possible.
 
Now, there is nothing that constrains modal expressions to be used in order solely to characterize formal logical relationships such as contrarity, subcontrarity, implication, etc. However, they _can_ be used in a context which confines them to that purpose.  Taking 'poss.' as the 1st-order _expression_ corresponding to 2nd-order imputation of possibility or logical internal consistency to a predicate or proposition,
 
"poss. Bs & poss.-Bs" == "'Bs' and '~Bs' are severally possible." == "[Logically,] this stove can be black and this stove can be non-black."
"~ poss.(Bs & ~Bs)" == "'Bs' and '~Bs' are incompossible." == "[Logically,] it can't be both that this stove is black and that this stove is not black."
 
(Note: "this stove", a.k.a. "s", is not, as you called it in an earlier post, an individual variable, but is instead an individual constant. In traditional logic, the subject of propositions in the form "Hs" (e.g. "Socrates is human") is taken as constant across propositions. If "this stove" is not constant across propositions in a given example, then it is really a variable and we're no longer talking about an already singled-out stove as in Peirce's example).
 
>[Jim] The proposition resulting from their combination appears to be [contradictory].
 
It does not appear to be contradictory. The components do not imply each other's negations.
For instance, "poss.Bs" does not imply the negative of "poss.~Bs".
The negation of "poss.~Bs" is "~poss.~Bs".
"~poss.~Bs" is equivalent to "necess.Bs".
Yet "poss.Bs" does not imply "necess.Bs"
Ergo, "poss.Bs" does not imply "~poss.~Bs".
Ergo, "poss.Bs" is consistent with "poss.~Bs".
QED.
 
>[Jim] They are not  Aristotelian (sub) contraries dealing with "some" objects. 
 
I said nothing about some specifically Aristotelian kind of subcontraries that deal only with "some" objects, "all" objects, etc.
 
The oppositional relationships of subcontrarity, contrarity, contradiction, etc., are certainly not confined to pertaining to quantificational propositions about some objects, all objects, etc. The Square of Opposition shows some oppositional relationships arising between quantificational propositions; however, one does not need quantificational forms at all in order to define such oppositional relationships -- indeed, a complete system of such binary formal logical relationships. The forms or schemata of propositional logic are all that's needed.
 
>[Jim] The so called "failure of contradiction" deals usually with general object indefiniteness in the case of the existential quantifier. That is not what is going on here. Vagueness is just as much the result of considering the two propositions severally.
 
In the context of logical oppositions, contradiction is the validity of exclusive alternation, and contradictories are defined as two propositions which can't both be true and can't both be false. Subcontrarity is positive alternation's validity conjoined with negative alternation's nonvalidity, and subcontraries are defined as two propositions which can both be true and can't both be false.
 
(Formal) equivalence.
Validity of the biconditional.
Can't be the 1st one true & the 2nd one false.
Can't be the 1st one false & the 2nd one true.
p.      p. T.      T. F.      F. --
(Formal) strict forward implication*.
Validity of the forward conditional and
nonvalidity of the reverse conditional.
Can't be the 1st one true & the 2nd one false.
Can be the 1st one false & the 2nd one true.
p.      (p v q). p.      T. F.      p. F.      T.
(Formal) strict reverse implication*.
Nonvalidity of the forward conditional and
validity of the reverse conditional.
Can be the 1st one true & the 2nd one false.
Can't be the 1st one false & the 2nd one true.
p.      (p & q). T.      p. p.      F. T.      F.
(Formal) mutual non-implication.
Nonvalidity of the conditional either way.
Can be the 1st one true & the 2nd one false.
Can be the 1st one false & the 2nd one true.
p.      q. p.      (q v ~p). p.      (q & ~p). p.      ~p.
*Trivial in itself is the difference between
strict forward implication and strict reverse implication.
Likewise trivial in itself is the difference between
the forward conditional and the reverse conditional.
Nontrivial in itself is the difference between the correlated kinds of inference:
(a) inference which is
truth-preservative and falsity-nonpreservative ('strict deduction'), and
(b) inference which is
truth-nonpreservative and falsity-preservative (ampliative induction).
Can both be true.
Can both be false.
Can both be true.
Can't both be false.
Can't both be true.
Can both be false.
Can't both be true.
Can't both be false.
Subalternation
(between
'subalterns').
Nonvalidity of
alternation, be it
positive or negative.
Subcontrarity.
Validity of positive
alternation and
nonvalidity of negative
alternation.
Contrarity.
Nonvalidity of positive
alternation and
validity of negative
alternation.
Contradiction.
Validity of exclusive
alternation.
 
>[Jim] We started this discussion with a number of examples of "whetherhood" designed to expand and qualify the predicate assertion.  I chose possibility becasue of its generality and largely epistemic flavor. I read Peirce as developing the meaning of possibility with "states of information," knowledge and probability in mind. I also favored in the beginning attaching the modal operator to propositions and treating the proposition as a subject. I did this in order to preserve the copula "is" in the subject assertion without qualification. The various ordinary ways of expressing the proposition can be rephrased. I also pointed out the way that identity becomes problematic.
 
Identity is _always_ "problematic" when one considers logic as signs. There is no index which picks out an object with total precision. Some vagueness is always involved.
 
The idea that a difference in modifications automatically means such a signficant difference in the substantial thing itself as to cause a break-down in identity logic is both unpragmatic and unfounded in deductive logic. It amounts to holding that allowing an element of chance ushers in total chaos. It amounts to saying that one cannot discuss possibilities without severing into multiple objects the object subject to those possibilities. It amounts to saying that one cannot discuss a given total population as subject to alternate events.
 
>[Jim] You say,
 
>>[Ben] "Maybe there's a necessary difference at a simple logical level between epistemic and ontological treatments of possibility, but such difference isn't evident to me."
 
>[Jim] Consider the difference between saying each proposition "Bs' and "-Bs" is indeterminate with respect to truth and saying that it is impossible that both propositions are jointly true. Ontologically, I do not think that the same stove or same women can have contrary qualities. Is this a principle of Being or just an idealization of excluded middle? Further, would you be prepared to say that the truth value of the compound proposition is indeterminate in the sense of "not known to be false?"
 
Peirce says that the same subject can have contrary qualities successively in time. In fact he says something like, that's just what an event is. >From CP 1. 493. "An event always involves a junction of contradictory inherences in the subjects existentially the same, whether there is a simple monadic quality inhering in a single subject, or whether they be inherences of contradictory monadic elements of dyads or polyads, in single sets of subjects." For more, see quotations appended to this post.
 
Of course a sufficiently expressive logical formalism will accommodate that without getting into trouble over it. I would hold that it is false to say that the same stove is both black and non-black in the same place, time, and way. And, for simplicity's sake, we can take "this stove" as "this stove now." Or we can just pretend, for simplicity's sake, that the problem doesn't arise -- just let the logic be the low-pixelage thing which it is, and go with its flow.  But simplicity's sake is what's involved, not an ontological or metaphysical doctrine that the same stove with a different color wouldn't and couldn't be the same stove.
 
Best, Ben Udell
 
Appendix: Quotes from Peirce on contradictory inherences.
 
CP 1. 493. There are other sorts of events, somewhat more complex because the characters concerned are not simple monadic qualities. For example, A may make war upon B, that is, may pass from one sort of relation to B to another sort of relation to B. But they come to much the same thing. There is a repugnance between two monad elements. It is hardly for our present purposes worth while to undertake a long analysis in order to make the very slight correction of our definition of an event called for on this account. An event always involves a junction of contradictory inherences in the subjects existentially the same, whether there is a simple monadic quality inhering in a single subject, or whether they be inherences of contradictory monadic elements of dyads or polyads, in single sets of subjects. But there is a more important possible variation in the nature of events. In the kind of events so far considered, while it is not necessary that the subjects should be existentially of the nature of subjects -- that is, that they should be substantial things -- since it may be a mere wave, or an optical focus, or something else of like nature which is the subject of change, yet it is necessary that these subjects should be in some measure permanent, that is, should be capable of accidental determinations, and therefore should have dyadic existence. But the event may, on the other hand, consist in the coming into existence of something that did not exist, or the reverse. There is still a contradiction here; but instead of consisting in the material, or purely monadic, repugnance of two qualities, it is an incompatibility between two forms of triadic relation, as we shall better understand later. In general, however, we may say that for an event there is requisite: first, a contradiction; second, existential embodiments of these contradictory states; [third,] an immediate existential junction of these two contradictory existential embodiments or facts, so that the subjects are existentially identical; and fourth, in this existential junction a definite one of the two facts must be existentially first in the order of evolution and existentially second in the order of involution. We say the former is earlier, the latter later in time. That is, the past can in some measure work upon and influence (or flow into) the future, but the future cannot in the least work upon the past. On the other hand, the future can remember and know the past, but the past can only know the future so far as it can imagine the process by which the future is to be influenced.
 
Peirce: CP 1.494 Such, then, is the nature of an event. We can now go forward to an analysis of the substance of the law of time. It has three requirements, a monadic, a dyadic, and a triadic. The monadic clause in the law of time is that whatever fact or dyadic dyad exists, exists during a time, and in this time. The event is the existential junction of states (that is, of that which in existence corresponds to a statement about a given subject in representation) whose combination in one subject would violate the logical law of contradiction. The event, therefore, considered as a junction, is not a subject and does not inhere in a subject. What is it, then? Its mode of being is existential quasi-existence, or that approach to existence where contraries can be united in one subject. Time is that diversity of existence whereby that which is existentially a subject is enabled to receive contrary determinations in existence. Phillip is drunk and Phillip is sober would be absurd, did not time make the Phillip of this morning another Phillip than the Phillip of last night. The law is that nothing dyadically exists as a subject without the diversification which permits it to receive contrary accidents. The instantaneous Phillip who can be drunk and sober at once has a potential being which does not quite amount to existence.
---
Message from peirce-l forum to subscriber [EMAIL PROTECTED]
---
Message from peirce-l forum to subscriber archive@mail-archive.com

Reply via email to