I tried to answer a few of the remaining category theory questions as best
I could. This thread is a week old, but I've been away and I saw some
unanswered questions. I tried looking online for good resources to help
explain precisely what a category is but most of what I found was either
vague or assumed significant knowledge of pure math.

On Tue, Apr 3, 2012 at 4:17 PM, Raul Miller <rauldmil...@gmail.com> wrote:

> On Tue, Apr 3, 2012 at 3:55 PM, Marshall Lochbaum <mwlochb...@gmail.com>
> wrote:
> > "The category of sets" is defined to be the category of sets and the
> > functions between them. It is an unambiguous term. If there is another
> > category whose elements are sets (i.e. the category of sets containing a
> > "base" element and the functions between them fixing that element), it
> will
> > be properly delineated.
>
> Then this category must contain all possible arrows?
>


"The category of sets" is a common shorthand for "the category whose
objects are ALL sets and whose morphisms are ALL functions between sets".

I think this should answer your question. Yes, we've included all arrows
that are functions between our objects (as sets).

Arrows don't have to be functions in general though. So we can throw in
additional arrows and create a larger category on the same objects (if we
define composition appropriately), but in this new category we would no
longer have arrows that represent actual functions.



>  > An arrow is only associated with one source and one destination. Thus
> there
> > is no arrow which leads from 0 to 0 and from 1 to 1. If we are in the
> > category of sets, this means each function has precisely one domain and
> > codomain.
>
> I think you are telling me that an arrow cannot represent
> an arbitrary function.
>
>   Consider the function F(x) = x+1
>
>   F(1) = 2
>   F(2) = 3
>
>   There can be no arrow that leads from 1 to 2 which also
>   leads from 2 to 3.
>
>   We can have an arrow which leads from the set of all
>   integers to the set of all integers, but that arrow
>   cannot distinguish between the above function and any
>   other function on integers.
>
> But this does not match what I read when I read about arrows/morphisms.



Let me give two different ways of formalizing natural numbers with
categories that I think help clarify precisely what categories are.

Let N1 be a category with only one object (ie a monoid), which is the set
N={0,1,2,3,...}, and arrows which are given by all functions from this set
to itself (composition is normal function composition). Your function f(x)
= x + 1 is a valid arrow in this category, we would write f: N -> N to
specify its domain and codomain. It composes nicely with itself and with
any other arrows (composition of arrows in our category is given to us by
composition of functions in our set-theory interpretation).

The key observation here is that the categorical structure is the abstract
structure of objects, arrows, and composition (N, functions on N, and their
composition). It doesn't capture "our objects are sets" or "our arrows are
functions". In the strictly categorical structure of N1, "0" and "1" are
nothing; they are neither objects nor arrows, we only use them to define it.

Let N2 be a category whose objects are the numbers 0,1,2,3,... themselves,
so we now have infinitely many objects (I'm not specifying what arrows are
in this category yet). It seems like the earlier confusion arose from the
desire to have a single arrow in a category like this which represents f(x)
= x + 1. But we also must define its domain and codomain, so some f0: 0 ->
1 would be distinct from some f1: 1 -> 2. The function f(x) = x + 1 can't
be represented by a single arrow in this category because its domain and
codomain are not individual numbers, which are our objects. We might be
able to get a functor out of it, but this depends on our choice of arrows.

Actually, let's go ahead and define our arrows in N2 by saying that there
is a unique arrow f: x -> y if x < y or x = y (in the latter case this
would be the identity arrow). This gives us a structure of arrows that are
not representative of functions functions but instead describes the linear
ordering of the natural numbers. You can confirm that this indeed satisfies
the properties of a category, where composition is defined by the only
possibility (ie if x<=y and y<=z then x<=z and each of these corresponds to
a unique arrow by definition, so there is only one way to compose them).
Now, we can define F: N2 -> N2 to be a functor, defined by F(x) = x + 1 on
the objects {0,1,...} and F( f: x -> y ) = (f+1): (x+1) -> (y+1) on the
arrows. This should satisfy the definition of a functor.

A function, like any mathematical thing, can be represented in terms of
category theory in many different ways and you have to be careful when
doing so.
----------------------------------------------------------------------
For information about J forums see http://www.jsoftware.com/forums.htm

Reply via email to