[EM] An interesting scenario (spoilers, utility)

2012-02-29 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hello,

I have been adding some code to help investigate cases where Approval
shows greater perception of spoiler than, say, IRV. To make the 
scenarios easier to visualize I just allocated six voting factions 
proportionately along 1D, positions ranging from -1 to 1.
 
I found an interesting case with the candidate positions:
.939, 0.333, -.06  (call them A, B, C)
 
Approval showed perception of spoiler as 27%, whereas IRV, TTR, and FPP
showed none. So I checked to see if it was consistent and what was 
happening.
 
With six blocs the scenario looks roughly like this (with the pipe
indicating the location of average utility for the bloc):
~3 CB | A
~1 BC | A
~1 BA | C
~1 A | BC
 
Under IRV, all votes were sincere. Under FPP and TTR, the lone A bloc
was compromising and voting for B. The result was that the sincere CW
(either C or B) was always winning and no one perceived spoilers.
 
Under Approval, the CB voters bullet-voted, the two B blocs voted for
their top two candidates, and the A bloc bullet-voted.
 
(A much rarer outcome had the BC faction bullet-voting, with the BA
and A factions voting for both A and B, giving the same result as the
other three methods. I think it's clear that this outcome was rarer
because the BC voters are happier with settling for C than the A 
voters are with settling for B.)
 
The result of this is that Approval was only electing the sincere CW
half the time. Instead of alternating between C and B winning, C won by
far the most often. B or A won rarely (and, I'd say, largely thanks
to the AI confusion that results from one candidate winning most of
the time).
 
Note that C is easily the closest candidate to the median. Even when 
B has a majority win over C, B is still not likely to be the utility 
maximizer. Approval's success rate at electing the utility maximizer 
was thus nearly perfect (instead of 50%).
 
I'm not sure what I think of this personally. I'm sure this scenario
isn't any kind of general rule for Approval, but suppose that it was?
Would it be a viable trade-off, to elect the utility maximizer more
often, in exchange for more complaints about spoiled elections?
 
Kevin Venzke

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] The oldest bad-example trick in the book

2012-02-29 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF

Instructions for how to make a method look bad:

Contrive an example in which the main contending candidates barely differ
by the method's own standard, but in which those candidates differ humungously 
and outrageously
by some other standard. In order to achieve the latter condition as strongly as 
possible, it's typically
necessary that the candidates are within one vote of eachother, in terms of the 
method's standard.

Then say, Look how wrongly that method can choose! Try to sound especially 
outraged when you say that,
as some here are already practiced at doing.

And yes, it's true: In Kevin's MMPO bad-example, A, B, and C do almost 
identically, in terms of MMPO's
own standard. No choice would be significantly worse than another in terms of 
that standard.

But, in terms of the favoriteness standard, they differ drastically and 
dramatically. 

Has someone followed my above-supplied instructions? Sure. To the letter.

So, because the candidates don't significantly differ by MMPO's standard, but 
differ outrageously
by the favoriteness standard, guess which standard we notice? Yes, intuitively, 
you look at that
and say that A or B should win. The winner should come from [A,B ]. In other 
words, if A doesn't
win, then B should win. If B doesn't win, then A should win.

You know it. I know it.

Problem: The voters don't think so. (Remember them?)

Why don't the voters think so? Because that's necessary in order to create the 
favoriteness-outrageous outcome
of Kevin's MMPO bad-example. 

Early on in the discussion of that example, I asked who was wronged in that 
bad-example.

Someone answered that the [A,B ] voters as a whole, were collectively wronged. 

But, as I discussed in my previous post about this, the A voters couldn't care 
less whether B or C wins. Therefore,
it's a bit creative to say that they're wronged because B didn't win instead of 
C. C won precisely because and only
because the A voters didn't care about B vs C, and the B voters didn't care 
about A vs C.

In fact, strictly speaking, if you took a poll among the A voters, between B 
and C, C would win that poll.

It's obviously fallacious to speak of [A,B] as a person who has been 
wronged--a resort of desperation needed 
because no one can point to a particular individual who was wronged.

Mike Ossipoff



  
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] An interesting scenario (spoilers, utility)

2012-02-29 Thread Jameson Quinn
This is indeed an interesting scenario. Something is particularly weak
about those BC preferences. It could be one of two things:

1) Maybe you're using some kind of trimmed or decaying utility function,
where the difference between a candidate who's 2/3 units away and one who's
1 unit away is negligible. Thus, your A voters are like Nader voters; so
far out of the mainstream that the other two candidates appear more similar
than they really are. So they bullet vote, holding out for a tiny chance of
victory. The rest follows; the hapless BA voters give A a vote, to prevent
the likely C win; the BC voters thus vote for C to ensure A doesn't win;
and C's win is almost guaranteed.

2) Depending what you mean by six factions proportionally from -1 to 1,
the BCA voters could have tiny BC preferences. They're either at 0.2 (if
the factions are evenly-spaced points), which puts them .1 from B and
.26  from C; or they're at 0.1 (if the factions are the center of
evenly-spaced line segments) which puts them .1 from B and .22666 from
C, a difference of only 0.06.

In the second case, the B=()CA votes cause the AB=()C votes and not
vice versa. But in either case, the two blocs together form an equilibrium;
neither has much motive to change until the other one does.

I wouldn't be surprised if there is an alternate equilibrium where the A
voters approve B, and a more traditional chicken dilemma ensues.

The funny thing is that this is both a chicken dilemma, and precisely the
opposite of a chicken dilemma, at the same time. A's bullet vote could be
seen as trying to provoke a chicken dilemma between B and C, but since B
voters are not unified on their second choices, the fight ends up being
played out between B voters, not between B and C. Or you could say that C
is trying to cause a chicken dilemma between B and A, and, with the help of
some extremely weak-willed CB voters, is succeeding brilliantly.

Anyway: in real life, I think that the A voters would be able to see that
if they changed, then the BC voters would change, and so the A voters
would only continue to bullet vote if they really were largely indifferent
about BC.

Jameson

2012/2/28 Kevin Venzke step...@yahoo.fr

 Hello,

 I have been adding some code to help investigate cases where Approval
 shows greater perception of spoiler than, say, IRV. To make the
 scenarios easier to visualize I just allocated six voting factions
 proportionately along 1D, positions ranging from -1 to 1.

 I found an interesting case with the candidate positions:
 .939, 0.333, -.06  (call them A, B, C)

 Approval showed perception of spoiler as 27%, whereas IRV, TTR, and FPP
 showed none. So I checked to see if it was consistent and what was
 happening.

 With six blocs the scenario looks roughly like this (with the pipe
 indicating the location of average utility for the bloc):
 ~3 CB | A
 ~1 BC | A
 ~1 BA | C
 ~1 A | BC

 Under IRV, all votes were sincere. Under FPP and TTR, the lone A bloc
 was compromising and voting for B. The result was that the sincere CW
 (either C or B) was always winning and no one perceived spoilers.

 Under Approval, the CB voters bullet-voted, the two B blocs voted for
 their top two candidates, and the A bloc bullet-voted.

 (A much rarer outcome had the BC faction bullet-voting, with the BA
 and A factions voting for both A and B, giving the same result as the
 other three methods. I think it's clear that this outcome was rarer
 because the BC voters are happier with settling for C than the A
 voters are with settling for B.)

 The result of this is that Approval was only electing the sincere CW
 half the time. Instead of alternating between C and B winning, C won by
 far the most often. B or A won rarely (and, I'd say, largely thanks
 to the AI confusion that results from one candidate winning most of
 the time).

 Note that C is easily the closest candidate to the median. Even when
 B has a majority win over C, B is still not likely to be the utility
 maximizer. Approval's success rate at electing the utility maximizer
 was thus nearly perfect (instead of 50%).

 I'm not sure what I think of this personally. I'm sure this scenario
 isn't any kind of general rule for Approval, but suppose that it was?
 Would it be a viable trade-off, to elect the utility maximizer more
 often, in exchange for more complaints about spoiled elections?

 Kevin Venzke
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] STV vs Party-list PR, could context matter?

2012-02-29 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

On 02/20/2012 03:34 AM, Richard Fobes wrote:

On 2/19/2012 1:24 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
  On 02/19/2012 06:18 AM, Richard Fobes wrote:
  ...
  More specifically, European politicians seem to be as clueless as U.S.
  politicians about what is needed to create jobs and restore
widespread
  economic prosperity.
 
  Let me just say that, as a Norwegian, that does not match my experience
  at all.

Ah, indeed Norway has a better political system than the main European
nations (France, Germany, Spain, etc.). Also, oil exports put Norway in
a much better position economically than what's going on here in the
U.S. (and tighter budgets result in greater dysfunctionality). And,
culturally, Norwegians seem to be enlightened more so than many other
countries.


I won't deny that oil exports help, but the other Scandinavian/Nordic 
countries seem to be doing well, too. For instance, the Wikipedia 
article on Sweden's economy says that the government budget has 
improved dramatically from a record deficit of more than 12% of GDP in 
1993, and from 1998 to present, has run a surplus in every year except 
2003 and 2004.. The US public debt, on the other hand, is around 60% of GDP.


As for the people being more enlightened, do you think politics could 
have a feedback effect in that respect? One could imagine that a more 
civil state of politics, more focused on issues rather than who's 
electable or who can sling words in one-on-one debates the best, could 
in turn lead the people to be more interested in actual politics.


(On the other hand, Warren does say the actual improvement due to 
democracy may be minor and that it's only compounding over time that 
makes democracies much better that non-democracies. He uses an example 
of Pakistan and what became the US having comparably similarly sized 
economies 300 years ago, but now the US's GDP/capita is 19 times that of 
Pakistan, which works out to about a 1% greater annual growth rate for 
the US.)



The need for Norway to resist the European Union in its effort to bite
off too much underscores my point about European nations, on average --
which implies a lack of wise leadership in both the EU and the countries
that dominate the EU.


I get the impression that, although some people wanted political 
integration from the start, the EU has mainly grown by exceeding its 
scope and then formalizing its new extended scope. It started off being 
special-purpose (as the European Coal and Steel Community), then grew 
from there into/was absorbed by the European Economic Community 
(depending on how you look at it). At that point, it had its own inertia 
and was no longer unambiguously subordinate to the national leadership.


This is not a pattern unique to the EU. I think that has happened in the 
US, as well, although there the political climate may have supported the 
organizations' expansion, particularly in the cases of the DHS and TSA.


One could of course say that the politicians have failed in reining in 
the Union's expansion of scope. To the degree they had a responsibility 
to keep the Union from growing, that is true. What I'm trying to say is 
that the Union is not without its internal dynamics: it did not simply 
rest while the politicians encouraged it to grow, but the bureaucracy 
had its own reasons to expand.



A point about the EU: Personally I think that creating the Eurodollar as
a monetary unit that is represented in currency was a mistake. Before
the Eurodollar was instituted, I publicly (in The Futurist magazine)
suggested that something called a Unidollar should be created as a
monetary unit that is defined in a way that does not inflate or deflate
with respect to tangible things and services, but without being
available as a tangible currency. That would allow people in different
countries to talk about monetary amounts in Unidollars without having to
know the conversion rate for the country of the person they are talking
to. (They only have to know the conversion rate between their country's
currency and the Unidollar.)


Would that be like the IMF special drawing rights? Perhaps a little, but 
if it were to be inflation-neutral, it would have to be adjusted, 
somehow. Things and services would still have different Unidollar prices 
in different economies, so the comparison would be limited.



The fact that the EU leaders didn't anticipate the possibility of
Greek and Italian (and other) defaults before they even instituted
the common currency (and did not realize that just asking new EU
nations to make a promise to spend taxpayers' money wisely, with no
real way to back up those promises) reveals a lack of wisdom.


I agree. Compromises sometimes fail to help either party, and moreso if 
the consequences haven't been considered thoroughly.



As for the U.S., the biggest (but not the only) election unfairness
occurs in primary elections as a result of vote splitting. Special
interests -- the people who give the largest amounts of 

Re: [EM] STV seat count, and start small and locally

2012-02-29 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

On 02/26/2012 06:25 PM, Richard Fobes wrote:

On 2/24/2012 1:01 PM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

On 02/23/2012 11:24 PM, Richard Fobes wrote:

Kristofer Munsterhjelm asks: ... why do you propose rules that would
make it harder for third parties to grow? ...

What I promote is VoteFair ranking. It includes a PR-related portion --
called VoteFair partial-proportional ranking -- that gives
representation to third parties that represent enough voters. This
aspect of VoteFair ranking specifically makes it easier (not harder) for
third parties to grow.


Yes, proportional representation would make it easier for third parties
to grow. On the other hand, in an earlier post, you suggested STV (which
is a PR method and thus one would expect to have the same purpose as the
VoteFair ranking) be used with two seats instead of three or five.

In a five-seat district, assuming Droop proportionality, any group of
more than a sixth of the voters can give their candidate a seat.
However, in a two-seat district, the group has to grow to exceed a third
of the voters to be sure of getting that seat; thus, smaller groups
could be splintered (either maliciously by gerrymandering or simply due
to bad luck), if there are few seats.



I'm picturing double-size districts and electing two representatives per
district. STV can use the ballot info to get that part right.

However, getting fair proportional results beyond two seats per district
(for any voting method) requires asking voters to indicate their
favorite political party.

That additional party-preference information then enables additional
proportional seats to be filled.


I'm not entirely sure what you're saying. If you're saying that you 
can't have more than two seats per district and still have 
proportionality unless you use party list PR, that's obviously wrong. 
But if you say that you can use an MMP compensatory mechanism to get 
proportionality beyond the effective threshold, then I get what you're 
saying. So I'll assume that :-)



Using STV to fill more than two seats would lead to very unfair results
in some situations. Those situations don't exist now, but they can (and
I believe would) arise if the voting system changes (such as adopting STV).


I think you said minor parties could get undue power in three-seat 
district STV with the two parties + minor situation that you have today, 
but I also guess that's not what you're referring to (since you say 
those situations don't exist now).


So what kind of unfairness are you envisioning? STV with five-seat 
districts seems to work where it's been used, in the sense that it does 
produce multipartyism and the voters don't complain about vote 
splitting. At least if they do, I don't know it.


MMP is a solution. The Norwegian parliament even combines MMP-like 
top-up with party list PR: if a party gets more than 4%, and the party 
gets a disproportional outcome from constituencies alone, then they get 
a share of the seats allocated for the purpose of compensating for that 
disproportionality.


But if you're going to use MMP, why then use STV at all? Why not use 
party list (since you're going to ask the voters their party 
preferences) or Condorcet + MMP (since the MMP part can handle the 
disproportionality of single member districts just like it can the 
disproportionality of two-member districts)? Questions of where you draw 
your tradeoff line - in this case, of two members per district instead 
of one or five - can be very useful in understanding, and so I ask.


(I tend to think that, all other things equal, seats allocated to STV is 
better than seats allocated to party list, because STV gives 
proportionality by what the voters want, not just proportionality per 
party. Party list PR is easier when the district sizes get large, but 
that's a matter of how many candidates you should have in each district 
before any residual disproportionality will have to be accepted or be 
handled by party-wise top-up.)



Currently the tiny state of Rhode Island is so frustrated by what goes
on in its state legislature that it is ripe for election-method reform.
That state is so small that it is more local than the Los Angeles area.

In other words, I agree that reform must start at the local level, but
I think that some state-level changes would fit your idea of local. (I
don't know if there are cities that are ripe for proportional
improvements.)


I know too little about US politics to comment, but if you're right, 
that's good, and I hope your strategy can work :-) Do you have any 
specific plans on how to advocate substantial electoral reform in Rhode 
Island?



I'll add that here in the state of Oregon there was a ballot measure
about adopting an open primary, so there are opportunities to adopt
election-method change at the state level if it's the right change. (It
failed; I opposed that change for what I hope are obvious reasons.)


Was that a partisan or nonpartisan open primary?


I continue to be 

[EM] Jameson: SODA FBC

2012-02-29 Thread MIKE OSSIPOFF


Jameson:

You wrote:



Still, again I have to ask you, Mike: where's SODA? 
You were right earlier that SODA fails FBC. But there are three 
mitigating factors.
1) Failure would be very rare; I hope to be able to be more precise about this 
in the near future.

[endquote]

I told you why that doesn't help. You can't assure a voter that SODA can't make 
them regret that they didn't vote someone else over their favorite. If you 
can't give that
assurance, then voters will continue to favorite-bury.



You continued:

2) Even when failure happens, SODA would never fail 
FBC without at least giving the non-betrayed favorite a chance to 
restore FBC by giving the win to the should-have-betrayed-for-them lower
 choice. (This is not mathematically necessary, but to make it untrue, 
you must divide the candidates in question into several clones, or give 
them a negligible fraction of their votes in delegated form, either of 
which makes an already-strained scenario completely implausible.)

[endquote]

You'd have to give more detail. The above paragraph isn't specific enough.

You continued:




3) There is a polytime(?), summable fix for the 
method, which restores full FBC; though I admit it's an ugly hack. 
Basically, there's a way to use the co-approval matrix to check if FBC 
has been violated and make those voters for whom it was violated 
virtually betray their favorite. Since, when that happens, it is the 
only way to give these voters a winner who they approved, it is not 
hurting them at all. There's also a slightly less-ugly, but imperfect, 
fix that merely makes the process in step 2 automatic; this would be 
good enough in practice.

[endquote]

Again, something more specific would be necessary. 

But, just from what you said, I suggest that the automated virtual 
favorite-betrayal that you suggested would
change the method to an entirely different method, bringing with it a new set 
of problems. For those problems to show, so that their seriousness can
be discussed, the suggestion in your above paragraph would have to be spelled 
out specifically, in detail.



You continued:

I believe that with these three factors, and most 
particularly the first one, SODA's FBC failure is tolerable. 

[endquote]

As I said yesterday, even IRV's FBC failure would be tolerable, if voters 
weren't so resignedly over-compromising.

An FBC failure can't be tolerable, because it means that you can't assure 
voters that it's safe to vote their favorite
in 1st place. As I said, for the excessively timid, giveaway-resigned, 
over-compromising voter, probably won't do.



You continued:

And as for cooperation/defection: SODA without 
question solves that problem more completely than any of the alphabet 
soup you mention.

[endquote]

Nonsense. Methods and criteria are routinely designated by 
letter-abbreviations. You mean alphabet soup like SODA?

You continued:

 (Though I'd still really appreciate it if you made 
quick electowiki pages for all of that

[endquote]

I definitely intend to, within the next few days.

You continued:

, because I'd bet that nobody but 
you actually knows what every one of those means ,and it would be 
considerate of you not to ask us to continually look up all the 
definitions and redefinitions in the archives).

[endquote]

Again, nonsense. You were reading the mailing list at the times when I defined 
each and every method and criterion that you're referring to. Most were 
initially defined in posts
that named them in the subject line. All of the new method and criterion 
definitions of mine were posted during a period of a few months, from October 
or November to the present.

Yes, new definitions should always be posted to the electowiki too. --even 
though a search at the archives page will quickly find recent references to 
a method or criterion name. 

So yes, I will definitely post the new definitions to the electowiki.

By the way, how many times have I asked for the definition of IRV3/AV3?  It's 
not at the electowiki either. The definition didn't come up in archives
searches. Dave repeatedly refused to post its definition.

Alright, a few of my new method definitions weren't posted with a subject line 
that named them, so I'll repeat here something I've several times posted:

MMT and GMAT are defined at postings that name them in the subject line.

MTAOC was defined in a posting that named it in the subject line. That posting 
consisted of pseudocode for an algorithm for determining which middle ratings 
are
to be kept and which are discarded due to lack of mutuality, and for thereby 
re-calculating the candidates' numbers of middle ratings.

As I've said several times:

MCAOC is identical to MTAOC, except that the method is MCA instead of MTA.

AOC is Approval, in which optional conditionality-by-mutuality is implemented 
as shown in the MTAOC pseudocode.

AOCBucklin is ABucklin in which optional conditionality by mutuality is 
implemented in that manner.

As I've said 

Re: [EM] Jameson: SODA FBC

2012-02-29 Thread Jameson Quinn
2012/2/29 MIKE OSSIPOFF nkk...@hotmail.com


 Jameson:

 You wrote:

 Still, again I have to ask you, Mike: where's SODA? You were right earlier
 that SODA fails FBC. But there are three mitigating factors.

 1) Failure would be very rare; I hope to be able to be more precise about
 this in the near future.

 [endquote]

 I told you why that doesn't help. You can't assure a voter that SODA can't
 make them regret that they didn't vote someone else over their favorite. If
 you can't give that
 assurance, then voters will continue to favorite-bury.

 Actually, with SODA, it does help, because you can know ex ante (by
looking at the predeclared preferences) when you are safe by FBC. That is,
if you prefer AB, and B prefers A, or A prefers B, or A and B both prefer
a certain viable C, then you are safe. Only if B prefers the most-viable
third candidate C, but A is indifferent between B and C, then you might
consider a favorite-betraying vote for B. And even then, it's only
appropriate if A very nearly, but not quite, is able to win... not exactly
the situation where favorite betrayal is the first thing on your mind.

This is a specific enough circumstance that favorite-betraying strategy
would never take off and become a serious factor in SODA.



  You continued:

 2) Even when failure happens, SODA would never fail FBC without at least
 giving the non-betrayed favorite a chance to restore FBC by giving the win
 to the should-have-betrayed-for-them lower choice. (This is not
 mathematically necessary, but to make it untrue, you must divide the
 candidates in question into several clones, or give them a negligible
 fraction of their votes in delegated form, either of which makes an
 already-strained scenario completely implausible.)

 [endquote]

 You'd have to give more detail. The above paragraph isn't specific enough.

 You continued:


 3) There is a polytime(?), summable fix for the method, which restores
 full FBC; though I admit it's an ugly hack. Basically, there's a way to use
 the co-approval matrix to check if FBC has been violated and make those
 voters for whom it was violated virtually betray their favorite. Since,
 when that happens, it is the only way to give these voters a winner who
 they approved, it is not hurting them at all. There's also a slightly
 less-ugly, but imperfect, fix that merely makes the process in step 2
 automatic; this would be good enough in practice.

 [endquote]

 Again, something more specific would be necessary.

 But, just from what you said, I suggest that the automated virtual
 favorite-betrayal that you suggested would
 change the method to an entirely different method, bringing with it a new
 set of problems. For those problems to show, so that their seriousness can
 be discussed, the suggestion in your above paragraph would have to be
 spelled out specifically, in detail.

 You continued:

 I believe that with these three factors, and most particularly the first
 one, SODA's FBC failure is tolerable.

 [endquote]

 As I said yesterday, even IRV's FBC failure would be tolerable, if voters
 weren't so resignedly over-compromising.

 An FBC failure can't be tolerable, because it means that you can't assure
 voters that it's safe to vote their favorite
 in 1st place.


With SODA, you can give that as a solid ex-ante guarantee to most voters,
just not quite all of them. This is unlike the situation in most voting
systems, where you can make no solid guarantees before the vote unless you
can make them to all voters.


 As I said, for the excessively timid, giveaway-resigned, over-compromising
 voter, probably won't do.

 You continued:

 And as for cooperation/defection: SODA without question solves that
 problem more completely than any of the alphabet soup you mention.

 [endquote]

 Nonsense. Methods and criteria are routinely designated by
 letter-abbreviations. You mean alphabet soup like SODA?


I wasn't saying that SODA was superior because you used acronyms and I
didn't, I was just using a collective term to refer to your proposals. I'm
sorry if you found it offensive, there was no disparagement intended, and
certainly not on the basis of names.



 You continued:

  (Though I'd still really appreciate it if you made quick electowiki pages
 for all of that

 [endquote]

 I definitely intend to, within the next few days.

 You continued:

 , because I'd bet that nobody but you actually knows what every one of
 those means ,and it would be considerate of you not to ask us to
 continually look up all the definitions and redefinitions in the archives).

 [endquote]

 Again, nonsense. You were reading the mailing list at the times when I
 defined each and every method and criterion that you're referring to. Most
 were initially defined in posts
 that named them in the subject line. All of the new method and criterion
 definitions of mine were posted during a period of a few months, from
 October or November to the present.

 Yes, new definitions should always be 

Re: [EM] STV seat count, and start small and locally

2012-02-29 Thread Jameson Quinn


 Currently the tiny state of Rhode Island is so frustrated by what goes on
 in its state legislature that it is ripe for election-method reform.  That
 state is so small that it is more local than the Los Angeles area.


By the way, does anyone on the list have any news at all about the Rhode
Island Voting Commission? I think it would be to the interests of basically
everyone on this list to see that their report is sensible, yet despite
having written to every city and town clerk in the state, I haven't been
able to get any further news on the commissions members, schedule, or work.

Jameson

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] STV seat count, and start small and locally

2012-02-29 Thread Jameson Quinn
2012/2/29 Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com


 Currently the tiny state of Rhode Island is so frustrated by what goes on
 in its state legislature that it is ripe for election-method reform.  That
 state is so small that it is more local than the Los Angeles area.


 By the way, does anyone on the list have any news at all about the Rhode
 Island Voting Commission?


oops, wrong name. I mean the RI Voter Choice Commission, established by H
6176.

I think it would be to the interests of basically everyone on this list to
 see that their report is sensible, yet despite having written to every city
 and town clerk in the state, I haven't been able to get any further news on
 the commissions members, schedule, or work.

 Jameson


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] The oldest bad-example trick in the book

2012-02-29 Thread Kevin Venzke
Hi Mike,

Personally I don't think anyone is wronged in the MMPO example.
I just don't think voters would accept it, and it would be difficult
to advocate. People will ask how the outcome can possibly make sense
and I don't think you can reassure them by asking who's wronged.

The issue isn't really favoriteness but the near lack of any votes
at all. Most people expect winning candidates to have their own
positive support, not just lack of opposition.

That said, the voters could see themselves as wronged if they felt
it was strategically advisable under the method to truncate. You
suggest that if the A voters really preferred B (the other big
candidate) to C (tiny candidate) then they should have voted for A
and B? I for one can't see myself doing that. The apparent front-
runners are A and B and I wouldn't vote for the worse frontrunner 
under MMPO. It makes more sense to try to deter burial attempts than
to defend against an extremely unlikely C victory.
 
But I don't want to discourage you from supporting MMPO. The first 
method I ever invented was in effect MMPO on approval ballots. I 
have a soft spot for this mechanic.
 
Kevin

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info