Re: [EM] good method ? was IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-15 Thread Kathy Dopp
On Sun, Feb 14, 2010 at 7:46 PM, Abd ul-Rahman Lomax
a...@lomaxdesign.com wrote:

 I seem to be one of the few people on this list who recognizes that I
 don't read voters' minds and cannot convert one vote-type to another
 for voters.

 Kathy, there was no reading of voter's minds. What was expressed was the
 votes themselves. Not the voter's internal, unexpressed preferences.


 For example, in the above example, by:

   35:A

 Some voters if they chose to rank further might have meant:

 AB=C
 or they might have wanted:

 ACB
 or
 ABC

 Whether they wanted that or not, they did not vote that. It's like
 Plurality, with three candidates, A, B, and C:

 35:A

 is exactly the same as

 35:AB=C.

It most certainly is **not** the same.

Again if individual **voters** are allowed to describe what they
really meant, the voters could have meant any of the following if they
were forced to fully rank and I would bet that it would be a
freakishly rare occurence for all voters to agree with your
interpretation when voters could have ranked any of the following ways
if forced to fully rank:

 AB=C
 or they might have wanted:

 ACB
 or
 ABC


When someone votes simply

A

What they really mean is A over all other candidates running.  I.e. voters mean
A B and A C and AD etc.  which may *not* certainly be the same
thing at all as
AB=C=D  in the voters' minds.

It changes the results, depending on the counting method if you assume
that the voter meant  35:AB=C. rather than one of the other
possibilities that can translate the voters' true meaning of A B and
A C and AD etc. that may've been the voter's choices if they were
forced to fully rank.

I doubt that all voters understand how you are going to define their
ballots, out of all the possible ways, in cases of voters not fully
ranking.

This seems to be yet another case of removing voters' rights to decide
for them what they meant in some methods of counting RCVs.

Kathy



 Which, of course could reflect an internal preference profile that is just
 that, or it could reflect on where the voter prefers B to C or the reverse.



 and the same for
   33:C

 We disagree on whether or not you and other members' interpretations
 of how voters would alter their votes are self-evident or not.

 I did speculate on *possible* alterations, but nobody presented this as a
 self-evident interpretation of this. What was stated was just that in a
 three-candidate election, 35:A is the same vote as 35:AB=C.

 There is an exception to this. Suppose the method is two-rank Bucklin. The
 voter votes first rank, A. Second rank, B and C. This is indeed a literal
 vote of AB=C, and it can have a different effect, depending on conditions,
 than the bullet vote A. That's because it could be read as an implicit
 approval of both B and C, thus a runoff election might be avoided.

 But that was not the context being discussed, and it was about how a
 Condorcet method is -- I asserted -- a plurality method, that, unless there
 is some kind of majority requirement -- to be defined, to be sure -- it can
 elect without the explicit approval of a majority of voters.

 And all single-ballot methods that don't coerce voters are plurality
 methods, in this sense.

  Poll
 100 voters, I doubt that the mind-reading abilities of persons on this
 list will hold uniformly for all of the voters you poll.

 Except, Kathy, there was no mind-reading. There were only two alternate ways
 of stating the same vote that simply expressed it with complete expressed
 preference profiles. Truncation is, in general, equal-ranking-bottom. It's
 possible to design methods where it means something different (for example,
 consider Approval voting, where the voter votes Yes or No on each candidate,
 but then doesn't vote on this question for some. It's an interesting method,
 in fact, but that's beyond the scope of this. It corresponds to the Average
 Range that is proposed by many Range advocates. I consider it to be probably
 politically impossible at this time, but it would be interesting to study.
 It *is* how multiple conflicting ballot questions are decided. The basis for
 majority approval is different for each question.

 We may disagree with the counting method that is applied when
   35:A
   32:BC
   33:C

 occurs, but it seems very clear that the Condorcet winner in this case
 is C, as you seem to agree with me in this case.

 Yes. The A voters express no preference between B and C. A is the plurality
 winner. But only 35 voters support A, 65 oppose A by their votes.

 A beats B, 35:32.
 but C beats A, 65:35. That's because the B voters express their preference
 for C over A.

 B, on the other hand, gets no support from the C voters over A. The C voter
 *means* A=B, bottom ranked equal.

 In most voting methods, not voting for a candidate is quite equivalent to
 ranking the candidate bottom or voting *against* the candidate.

 This example was *not* an example of majority failure in a Condorcet method,
 which 

Re: [EM] good method ? was IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-15 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Jonathan Lundell wrote:

On Feb 14, 2010, at 4:46 PM, Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:


We may disagree with the counting method that is applied when

35:A 32:BC 33:C

occurs, but it seems very clear that the Condorcet winner in this
case is C, as you seem to agree with me in this case.

Yes. The A voters express no preference between B and C. A is the
plurality winner. But only 35 voters support A, 65 oppose A by
their votes.


We don't actually know that. Suppose the BC voters are saying, I
love B, hate C, and have no idea who A is. Granted, in this limited
example, they could easily have voted BAC to indicate something
like that. But if there are a lot of candidates who may be unknown to
many voters, it's asking a lot for them to list them all (whether or
not we allow equality of preference).

I've been thinking of the possibility of handling indifference
differently. Suppose that '*' means all candidates not explicitly
ranked. Then

AB is interpreted as usual, implying AB*

But A*B mean A is best, B is worst, and all the others are
indifferent, without having to rank them explicitly between A  B.


Would it be possible to use something like Warren's quorum rule here, so 
that if a voter ranks AB but not ABC, then the B vs C and A vs C 
contest remains completely unaltered?


I suppose so, but would it be any good?


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] good method ? was IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-15 Thread Dave Ketchum
Clearly there has been a lack of clarity in this thread.  While others  
may have made the mess you joined in, seems like you might have stated  
your objections more clearly.


From IRV ballot pile and previous discussion of such piles, the  
subject is IRV, a method that has rules.


Then there was a post that assumed Condorcet, since the description of  
what happened fitted Condorcet rules, but that post said nothing about  
switching rules.


Then you objected.  Per the above you had cause, but your words about  
voters' minds led to continuing trouble.


On Feb 15, 2010, at 11:35 AM, Kathy Dopp wrote:

On Sun, Feb 14, 2010 at 7:46 PM, Abd ul-Rahman Lomax
a...@lomaxdesign.com wrote:

I seem to be one of the few people on this list who recognizes  
that I

don't read voters' minds and cannot convert one vote-type to another
for voters.


Kathy, there was no reading of voter's minds. What was expressed  
was the

votes themselves. Not the voter's internal, unexpressed preferences.


He was right about minds - the problem was ambiguity as to what rules  
applied - a detail that neither of you pointed at.





For example, in the above example, by:


35:A


Some voters if they chose to rank further might have meant:

AB=C


This is what they DID mean in Condorcet, assuming exactly three  
candidates.  Adding D, similar thinking would lead to AB=C=D while  
AB=CD would mean the same as AB=C.


Clearly we are not in IRV, which does not use =.


or they might have wanted:

ACB
or
ABC


Whether they wanted that or not, they did not vote that. It's like
Plurality, with three candidates, A, B, and C:

35:A

is exactly the same as

35:AB=C.


Except that this latter, while implied in Plurality, cannot be  
expressed that way in Plurality.



It most certainly is **not** the same.

Again if individual **voters** are allowed to describe what they
really meant, the voters could have meant any of the following if they
were forced to fully rank and I would bet that it would be a
freakishly rare occurence for all voters to agree with your
interpretation when voters could have ranked any of the following ways
if forced to fully rank:


AB=C
or they might have wanted:

ACB
or
ABC




When someone votes simply

A

What they really mean is A over all other candidates running.  I.e.  
voters mean

A B and A C and AD etc.  which may *not* certainly be the same
thing at all as
AB=C=D  in the voters' minds.

It changes the results, depending on the counting method if you assume
that the voter meant  35:AB=C. rather than one of the other
possibilities that can translate the voters' true meaning of A B and
A C and AD etc. that may've been the voter's choices if they were
forced to fully rank.

I doubt that all voters understand how you are going to define their
ballots, out of all the possible ways, in cases of voters not fully
ranking.

This seems to be yet another case of removing voters' rights to decide
for them what they meant in some methods of counting RCVs.

Kathy




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] good method ? was IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-14 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 01:59 PM 2/14/2010, Kathy Dopp wrote:

  From: Chris Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au
  35:A
  32:BC
  33:C,
 
  by which I mean
 
  35:AB=C
  32:BCA
  33:CA=B.

 Kathy doesn't seem to recognize this, or maybe she does, but the two
 statements are equivalent. By not ranking B and C, the voter
 equal-ranks them bottom. That is the exact effect of the vote.

I seem to be one of the few people on this list who recognizes that I
don't read voters' minds and cannot convert one vote-type to another
for voters.


Kathy, there was no reading of voter's minds. What was expressed was 
the votes themselves. Not the voter's internal, unexpressed preferences.




For example, in the above example, by:

  35:A

Some voters if they chose to rank further might have meant:

AB=C
or they might have wanted:

ACB
or
ABC


Whether they wanted that or not, they did not vote that. It's like 
Plurality, with three candidates, A, B, and C:


35:A

is exactly the same as

35:AB=C.

Which, of course could reflect an internal preference profile that is 
just that, or it could reflect on where the voter prefers B to C or 
the reverse.





and the same for
  33:C

We disagree on whether or not you and other members' interpretations
of how voters would alter their votes are self-evident or not.


I did speculate on *possible* alterations, but nobody presented this 
as a self-evident interpretation of this. What was stated was just 
that in a three-candidate election, 35:A is the same vote as 35:AB=C.


There is an exception to this. Suppose the method is two-rank 
Bucklin. The voter votes first rank, A. Second rank, B and C. This is 
indeed a literal vote of AB=C, and it can have a different effect, 
depending on conditions, than the bullet vote A. That's because it 
could be read as an implicit approval of both B and C, thus a runoff 
election might be avoided.


But that was not the context being discussed, and it was about how a 
Condorcet method is -- I asserted -- a plurality method, that, unless 
there is some kind of majority requirement -- to be defined, to be 
sure -- it can elect without the explicit approval of a majority of voters.


And all single-ballot methods that don't coerce voters are plurality 
methods, in this sense.



  Poll
100 voters, I doubt that the mind-reading abilities of persons on this
list will hold uniformly for all of the voters you poll.


Except, Kathy, there was no mind-reading. There were only two 
alternate ways of stating the same vote that simply expressed it with 
complete expressed preference profiles. Truncation is, in general, 
equal-ranking-bottom. It's possible to design methods where it means 
something different (for example, consider Approval voting, where the 
voter votes Yes or No on each candidate, but then doesn't vote on 
this question for some. It's an interesting method, in fact, but 
that's beyond the scope of this. It corresponds to the Average Range 
that is proposed by many Range advocates. I consider it to be 
probably politically impossible at this time, but it would be 
interesting to study. It *is* how multiple conflicting ballot 
questions are decided. The basis for majority approval is different 
for each question.



We may disagree with the counting method that is applied when
  35:A
  32:BC
  33:C

occurs, but it seems very clear that the Condorcet winner in this case
is C, as you seem to agree with me in this case.


Yes. The A voters express no preference between B and C. A is the 
plurality winner. But only 35 voters support A, 65 oppose A by their votes.


A beats B, 35:32.
but C beats A, 65:35. That's because the B voters express their 
preference for C over A.


B, on the other hand, gets no support from the C voters over A. The C 
voter *means* A=B, bottom ranked equal.


In most voting methods, not voting for a candidate is quite 
equivalent to ranking the candidate bottom or voting *against* the candidate.


This example was *not* an example of majority failure in a Condorcet 
method, which points out how, unless there is some approval cutoff 
specified, giving a candidate any rank above bottom can become a vote 
*for* the candidate (in any pairwise race with a lower-ranked candidate).


Now, with approval cutoff expressed, one can do a different kind of 
analysis. Suppose there is a dummy candidate called Z. Ranking a 
candidate above Z means that one approves the candidate. The 
practical meaning of this is clear if a runoff is needed if a 
candidate doesn't gain a majority.


So the B votes in the example above might be AZBC or ABZC. It's 
also possible that it could be ZABC, meaning I'd prefer to see a 
runoff in any case, I really don't like any of these candidates and 
maybe we could get some write-in campaign together or I can do more 
investigation and change my mind Or it could be ABCZ, meaning, 
I'd prefer any of the three to holding a runoff, there isn't that 
much difference between them, and the worst of them is still good enough.




Re: [EM] good method ? was IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-14 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Feb 14, 2010, at 4:46 PM, Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:

 We may disagree with the counting method that is applied when
   35:A
   32:BC
   33:C
 
 occurs, but it seems very clear that the Condorcet winner in this case
 is C, as you seem to agree with me in this case.
 
 Yes. The A voters express no preference between B and C. A is the plurality 
 winner. But only 35 voters support A, 65 oppose A by their votes.

We don't actually know that. Suppose the BC voters are saying, I love B, hate 
C, and have no idea who A is. Granted, in this limited example, they could 
easily have voted BAC to indicate something like that. But if there are a lot 
of candidates who may be unknown to many voters, it's asking a lot for them to 
list them all (whether or not we allow equality of preference). 

I've been thinking of the possibility of handling indifference differently. 
Suppose that '*' means all candidates not explicitly ranked. Then

AB is interpreted as usual, implying AB*

But A*B mean A is best, B is worst, and all the others are indifferent, 
without having to rank them explicitly between A  B.



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] good method ? , was IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-13 Thread Kathy Dopp
 From: Chris Benham cbenha...@yahoo.com.au
 To: EM election-methods@lists.electorama.com

 Rob LeGrand wrote (11 Feb 2010):

 snip

 35:A
 32:BC
 33:C,

 by which I mean

 35:AB=C
 32:BCA
 33:CA=B.

 In this example, C is the Condorcet winner even though C does not have a
 majority over B.? I can see how this example could be seen as an
 embarrassment to the Condorcet criterion, in that a good method might not
 choose C as the winner.

 end quoted message

I agree with Chris (below), If you require every winner to have a
majority *over* ever other candidate, then there is no system that
would give you any winners.  Clearly above, C has 65 votes and B only
has 35 votes, at least in scenario #1 above.

Guessing as to what voters really mean, by assuming scenario #2 from
scenario #1 -- you may have read the minds of all those voters who you
believe all think exactly alike in each category, incorrectly.
However, in scenario #2, I think A is the correct winner.

I think election methods enthusiasts too often think they can read
voters' minds and translate votes between between two different
scenarios for voters.

Kathy


 Rob,

 Well I can't. Electing A would be a violation of the Minmal Defense criterion,
 and electing B would violate Woodall's Plurality criterion and Condorcet 
 Loser.

 What good method do you have in mind that might not elect C?

 And what's good about it?

 Chris Benham







-- 

Kathy Dopp
http://electionmathematics.org
Town of Colonie, NY 12304
One of the best ways to keep any conversation civil is to support the
discussion with true facts.

Realities Mar Instant Runoff Voting
http://electionmathematics.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf

Voters Have Reason to Worry
http://utahcountvotes.org/UT/UtahCountVotes-ThadHall-Response.pdf

Checking election outcome accuracy
http://electionmathematics.org/em-audits/US/PEAuditSamplingMethods.pdf

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] good method ? , was IRV ballot pile count (proof of closed form)

2010-02-12 Thread Chris Benham
Rob LeGrand wrote (11 Feb 2010):

snip

35:A
32:BC
33:C,

by which I mean

35:AB=C
32:BCA
33:CA=B.

In this example, C is the Condorcet winner even though C does not have a
majority over B.  I can see how this example could be seen as an
embarrassment to the Condorcet criterion, in that a good method might not
choose C as the winner.

end quoted message

Rob,

Well I can't. Electing A would be a violation of the Minmal Defense criterion,
and electing B would violate Woodall's Plurality criterion and Condorcet Loser.

What good method do you have in mind that might not elect C?

And what's good about it?

Chris Benham



  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info