[geo] Re: Geoengineering and Climate Change Polarization: Testing a Two-channel Model of Science Communication, Ann. Am. Acad. Pol. Soc. Sci.

2014-03-03 Thread David Morrow
FYI, the lead author of that paper, Dan Kahan, posted two additional blog 
posts on culture, values, and geoengineering:

http://www.culturalcognition.net/blog/2014/2/24/geoengineering-the-cultural-plasticity-of-climate-change-ris.html

http://www.culturalcognition.net/blog/2014/2/26/geoengineering-the-science-communication-environment-the-cul.html



On Thursday, February 27, 2014 2:04:00 AM UTC-6, andrewjlockley wrote:

 Poster's note : This is just brilliant. At last an explanation of why 
 believing nonsense is rational. Useful to reflect on how this paper replies 
 to the origin and persistence of other belief systems, as well as climate 
 change. Leaves me wondering what nonsense I believe. 


 http://www.culturalcognition.net/blog/2014/2/23/three-models-of-risk-perception-their-significance-for-self.html

 Three models of risk perception  their significance for self-government

 Dan Kahan Posted on Sunday, February 23, 2014 at 7:52AM

 From Geoengineering and Climate Change Polarization: Testing a Two-channel 
 Model of Science Communication, Ann. Am. Acad. Pol.  Soc. Sci. (in press).

 Theoretical background

 Three models of risk perception

 The scholarly literature on risk perception and communication is dominated 
 by two models. The first is the rational-weigher model, which posits that 
 members of the public, in aggregate and over time, can be expected to 
 process information about risk in a manner that promotes their expected 
 utility (Starr 1969). The second is the irrational-weigher model, which 
 asserts that ordinary members of the pubic lack the ability to reliably 
 advance their expected utility because their assessment of risk information 
 is constrained by cognitive biases and other manifestations of bounded 
 rationality (Kahneman 2003; Sunstein 2005; Marx et al. 2007; Weber 
 2006).Neither of these models cogently explains public conflict over 
 climate change—or a host of other putative societal risks, such as nuclear 
 power, the vaccination of teenage girls for HPV, and the removal of 
 restrictions on carrying concealed handguns in public. Such disputes 
 conspicuously feature partisan divisions over facts that admit of 
 scientific investigation. Nothing in the rational-weigher model predicts 
 that people with different values or opposing political commitments will 
 draw radically different inferences from common information. Likewise, 
 nothing in the irrational-weigher model suggests that people who subscribe 
 to one set of values are any more or less bounded in their rationality than 
 those who subscribe to any other, or that cognitive biases will produce 
 systematic divisions of opinion of among such groups.

 One explanation for such conflict is the cultural cognition thesis (CCT). 
 CCT says that cultural values are cognitively prior to facts in public risk 
 conflicts: as a result of a complex of interrelated psychological 
 mechanisms, groups of individuals will credit and dismiss evidence of risk 
 in patterns that reflect and reinforce their distinctive understandings of 
 how society should be organized (Kahan, Braman, Cohen, Gastil  Slovic 
 2010; Jenkins-Smith  Herron 2009). Thus, persons 
 with individualistic values can be expected to be relatively dismissive of 
 environmental and technological risks, which if widely accepted would 
 justify restricting commerce and industry, activities that people with such 
 values hold in high regard. The same goes for individuals 
 withhierarchical values, who see assertions of environmental risk as 
 indictments of social elites. Individuals 
 with egalitarian and communitarian values, in contrast, see commerce and 
 industry as sources of unjust disparity and symbols of noxious 
 self-seeking, and thus readily credit assertions that these activities are 
 hazardous and therefore worthy of regulation (Douglass  Wildavsky 1982). 
 Observational and experimental studies have linked these and comparable 
 sets of outlooks to myriad risk controversies, including the one over 
 climate change (Kahan 2012).Individuals, on the CCT account, behave not as 
 expected-utility weighers—rational or irrational—but rather as cultural 
 evaluators of risk information (Kahan, Slovic, Braman  Gastil 2006). The 
 beliefs any individual forms on societal risks like climate change—whether 
 right or wrong—do not meaningfully affect his or her personal exposure to 
 those risks. However, precisely because positions on those issues are 
 commonly understood to cohere with allegiance to one or another cultural 
 style, taking a position at odds with the dominant view in his or her 
 cultural group is likely to compromise that individual’s relationship with 
 others on whom that individual depends for emotional and material support. 
 As individuals, citizens are thus likely to do better in their daily lives 
 when they adopt toward putative hazards the stances that express their 
 commitment to values that they share with others, 

RE: [geo] Re: Geoengineering and Climate Change Polarization: Testing a Two-channel Model of Science Communication, Ann. Am. Acad. Pol. Soc. Sci.

2014-03-03 Thread Rau, Greg
This observation may bear repeating:
To be effective, science communication must successfully negotiate both 
channels. That is, in addition to furnishing individuals with valid and 
pertinent information about how the world works, it must avail itself of the 
cues necessary to assure individuals that assenting to that information will 
not estrange them from their communities.

Isn't this what good advertising does, and couldn't our community benefit from 
some cogent advice from Madison Ave, if we could afford it? Science and 
scientific reasoning alone apparently isn't enough, especially when there are 
(well funded) individuals who would cast such reasoning as a threat to their 
communities.
Greg

From: geoengineering@googlegroups.com [geoengineering@googlegroups.com] on 
behalf of David Morrow [dmorr...@gmail.com]
Sent: Monday, March 03, 2014 6:27 PM
To: geoengineering@googlegroups.com
Subject: [geo] Re: Geoengineering and Climate Change Polarization: Testing a 
Two-channel Model of Science Communication, Ann. Am. Acad. Pol.  Soc. Sci.

FYI, the lead author of that paper, Dan Kahan, posted two additional blog posts 
on culture, values, and geoengineering:

http://www.culturalcognition.net/blog/2014/2/24/geoengineering-the-cultural-plasticity-of-climate-change-ris.html

http://www.culturalcognition.net/blog/2014/2/26/geoengineering-the-science-communication-environment-the-cul.html



On Thursday, February 27, 2014 2:04:00 AM UTC-6, andrewjlockley wrote:

Poster's note : This is just brilliant. At last an explanation of why believing 
nonsense is rational. Useful to reflect on how this paper replies to the origin 
and persistence of other belief systems, as well as climate change. Leaves me 
wondering what nonsense I believe.

http://www.culturalcognition.net/blog/2014/2/23/three-models-of-risk-perception-their-significance-for-self.html

Three models of risk perception  their significance for self-government

Dan Kahan Posted on Sunday, February 23, 2014 at 7:52AM

From Geoengineering and Climate Change Polarization: Testing a Two-channel 
Model of Science Communication, Ann. Am. Acad. Pol.  Soc. Sci. (in press).

Theoretical background

Three models of risk perception

The scholarly literature on risk perception and communication is dominated by 
two models. The first is the rational-weigher model, which posits that members 
of the public, in aggregate and over time, can be expected to process 
information about risk in a manner that promotes their expected utility (Starr 
1969). The second is the irrational-weigher model, which asserts that ordinary 
members of the pubic lack the ability to reliably advance their expected 
utility because their assessment of risk information is constrained by 
cognitive biases and other manifestations of bounded rationality (Kahneman 
2003; Sunstein 2005; Marx et al. 2007; Weber 2006).Neither of these models 
cogently explains public conflict over climate change--or a host of other 
putative societal risks, such as nuclear power, the vaccination of teenage 
girls for HPV, and the removal of restrictions on carrying concealed handguns 
in public. Such disputes conspicuously feature partisan divisions over facts 
that admit of scientific investigation. Nothing in the rational-weigher model 
predicts that people with different values or opposing political commitments 
will draw radically different inferences from common information. Likewise, 
nothing in the irrational-weigher model suggests that people who subscribe to 
one set of values are any more or less bounded in their rationality than those 
who subscribe to any other, or that cognitive biases will produce systematic 
divisions of opinion of among such groups.

One explanation for such conflict is the cultural cognition thesis (CCT). CCT 
says that cultural values are cognitively prior to facts in public risk 
conflicts: as a result of a complex of interrelated psychological mechanisms, 
groups of individuals will credit and dismiss evidence of risk in patterns that 
reflect and reinforce their distinctive understandings of how society should be 
organized (Kahan, Braman, Cohen, Gastil  Slovic 2010; Jenkins-Smith  Herron 
2009). Thus, persons with individualistic values can be expected to be 
relatively dismissive of environmental and technological risks, which if widely 
accepted would justify restricting commerce and industry, activities that 
people with such values hold in high regard. The same goes for individuals 
withhierarchical values, who see assertions of environmental risk as 
indictments of social elites. Individuals with egalitarian and communitarian 
values, in contrast, see commerce and industry as sources of unjust disparity 
and symbols of noxious self-seeking, and thus readily credit assertions that 
these activities are hazardous and therefore worthy of regulation (Douglass  
Wildavsky 1982). Observational and experimental studies have linked these and