Re: [peirce-l] ORDINARY DISCOURSE AS THE FINAL CAUSE OF ALL INTELLECTUAL ENDEAVORS

2012-05-12 Thread Gary Moore
Phyllis Chiasson: Since language only has meaning within contexts, change the 
context and you are likely to change meaning altogether.

Gary Moore: “Change” yes, sometimes even great “change”. However, one should be 
aware of this, and, for a varied and many times antagonistic audience that both 
Peirce and Deely dealt with, one should bend over backwards or nobody simply 
listens. Something I really do not know but suspect is a great problem with 
Peirce :: How many Europeans pay any attention to Peirce? Dealing with people 
like Russell and English linguistic analytics, Wittgenstein, Heidegger, and 
Derrida – people highly sensitive to the use and misuse of language – from 
their very different points of view – who have great problems themselves being 
understood – Peirce’s approach should have attracted great attention in the 
1920s, certainly the 1930s. He was more or less available, talked about by 
American Pragmatists Europeans did pay some attention too – but that is just 
it! Peirce had things to say of much more interest than William James. They 
loved his psychology
 but that seems to be the limit. 
---
Gary Moore: So when you say “change meaning altogether”, that is exactly how 
many Europeans may have found in Peirce – in other words, incomprehensible – 
when in fact he was dealing with exactly their same problems and many times 
providing answers to their problems which they did not bother with. There still 
seems to be a pall over Peirce in Europe. And despite Deely’s own obscurity in 
the matter of “The Ethics of Terminology”, Deely in his own work has abundantly 
connected Peirce not only with the Latin scholastics, but to Jacques Maritain 
[whom I had little respect for before reading Deely] and Martin Heidegger [whom 
he has written one of the best books about in English]. So making one’s meaning 
known in the vocabularies of other philosophers dealing with the same problems 
has been a great accomplishment of Deely’s. However, his very off-hand 
treatment of other European philosophers is so emotionally tainted and stunted 
as to be
 incomprehensible and even logically contradictory when he has to change course 
in mid-stream when forced to admit they had something key to add to his own and 
Peirce’s arguments, for instance Kant’s approach to the categories.
 
Phyllis Chiasson:  Ambiguity and vagueness are the enemies of clarity; Peirce’s 
concept of terminological ethics is one of his main contributions to philosophy 
and the extension (and purpose) of his semeiotic. Torkild Thellefsen discusses 
meaning from a Peircean perspective in his new book. He points out that the 
word, X-ray, has a much deeper and more complete meaning to a physician than it 
does to nonprofessionals, who in their fundamental ignorance may nevertheless 
think they well know what X-rays mean and do. E. David Ford also explains the 
need for effective definitions in his book, Scientific Method for Ecological 
Research. Those who do not engage in so-called “ethical terminology” risk being 
misunderstood—or worse. 

Gary Moore: This is true but, in reality, physicians are forced to explain the 
abilities and limits of x rays to patients and their families. This had been 
made so because many physicians made it seem as if the patient and their 
families are too stupid to understand such highly intellectual concepts. This 
had two wonderful results. They could literally get away with murder. They 
could take as many x rays as they could get away changing for. And that sort of 
behavior is now, after so many years of terrible abuse, coming to a stop – but 
at the expense of everyone in general. Now, when someone comes into the 
emergency room, an x-ray is taken simply to say, based on some extremely remote 
possibility, it has been done instead of dealing with the immediate problem 
immediately. The extravagant rise in the price of healthcare, therefore, is 
raised directly linked, and abundantly documented, to just such behavior.  To 
supposedly avoid an anticipated problem of
 explanation, you eliminate the problem by an action that has a physical, 
expensive, but irrelevant result. So bombastic obscurity is the opposite of 
being good and noble and is rather nasty and devious and downright treacherous.

Gary Moore: You yourself do not make a direct and factual statement of what 
Peirce “main contributions to philosophy and the extension (and purpose) of his 
semeiotic” clearly is at all, but just shuffle off explanation by saying it is 
important and that “ambiguity and vagueness” are bad things. But just saying 
that or Thellefsen’s saying that or Ford’s saying that does not at all clarify 
what Peirce actually said that was distinctively, on his own, important – or it 
is just hum-bug obscurity? He means to say something important, and he has said 
important things in the past, but on “The Ethics of Terminology” has he really 
said anything substantially different from what anyone else has 

Re: [peirce-l] Frege against the Booleans

2012-05-12 Thread Jim Willgoose

Thanks Ben. I heartily concur on dropping the thread. There is little 
indication that anyone is interested in the specific H. Sluga paper or the 
priority principle as put forth in that paper.  Jim W
 Date: Fri, 11 May 2012 22:42:12 -0400
From: bud...@nyc.rr.com
Subject: Re: [peirce-l] Frege against the Booleans
To: PEIRCE-L@LISTSERV.IUPUI.EDU


  

  
  
Jim,

Sorry, I'm just getting more confused. I've actually seen a,
  b, etc. called constants as opposed to variables such as
  x, y, etc. Constant individuals and variable individuals, so
  to speak, anyway in keeping with the way the words constant and
  variable seem to be used in opposition to each other in math.
  But if that's not canonical, then it's not canonical. Also, I
  thought F was a predicate term, a dummy letter, and at any
  rate a (unknown or veiled) constant as I would have called it up
  till a few minutes ago.  I thought ~ was a functor that makes a
  new predicate ~F out of the predicate F. If ~ and the other
  functors are logical constants, then isn't the predication
  relationship between F and x in Fx also a logical constant,
  though it has no separate symbol? Really, I think the case is
  hopeless. I need to read a book on the subject.


I don't see why conceptual analysis would start with the third
  trichotomy of signs (rheme, dicisign, argument) and move to the
  first trichotomy of signs (qualisign, sinsign, legisign). Maybe
  you mean that conceptual analysis would start with Third in the
  trichotomy of rheme, dicisign, argument and move to that
  trichotomy's First. I.e. move from argument back to rheme. But I
  don't see why the conceptual-analysis approach would prefer that
  direction.


On your P.S., I don't know whether you're making a distinction
  between propositions and sentences.


Thanks but this all seems hopeless! Let's drop this sub-thread
  for at least 24 hours.


Best, Ben 

On 5/11/2012 10:06 PM, Jim Willgoose wrote:

  
  
Ben,

 

I made it too complicated. Sorry. It didn't help that /- was
brought into the discussion.  You had the basic idea earlier
with dicent and rheme. Fx and Fa have to be kept together.
So, the interpretant side of the semiotic relation has priority.
Conceptual  analysis would move from the third trichotomy back
to the first. Synthesis would move from the first to the
third. If this is close, the priority principle would place
emphasis on the whole representation. (By the way, F is a
function and a is an individual, ~+-- are the logical
constants.) 

 

Jim W

 

PS If words have meaning only in sentences (context principle),
does this mean that term, class, and propositional logics are
meaningless?


  Date: Fri, 11 May 2012 20:30:53 -0400

  From: bud...@nyc.rr.com

  Subject: Re: [peirce-l] Frege against the Booleans

  To: PEIRCE-L@LISTSERV.IUPUI.EDU

  

  Hi, Jim,

  Sorry, I'm not following you here. F and a look like
  logical constants in the analysis. I don't know how you're
  using v, and so on.  I don't know why there's a question
  raised about taking the judgment as everything that implies
  it, or as everything that it implies. Beyond those things,
  maybe you're suggesting, that Frege didn't take judgments as
  mere fragments of inferences, because he wasn't aware of some
  confusion that would be clarified by taking judgments as mere
  fragments of inferences? But I'm afraid we're just going to
  have to admit that I'm in over my head.

  Best, Ben

  On 5/11/2012 7:36 PM, Jim Willgoose wrote:
  

 Ben,

   

  I suppose you could take the judgment as everything which
  implies it. (or is implied by it) In this way, you could
  play around with the judgment stroke and treat meaning
  as inferential. But, using a rule of substitution and
  instantiation, I could show the content of the following
  judgment without any logical constants

   

  /- ExFx

  Fa x=a

  ExFx

   

  But if I say vx, is v a or is it another class G?
  Further, vx is a logical product.  The above analysis
  has no logical constants.  I guess the point is that once
  you segment Fx and then talk of two interpretations;
  boolean classes or propositions, you create some confusion
  which Frege (according to Sluga) traces back to favoring
  concepts over judgments with resulting totalities such as
 

Re: [peirce-l] ORDINARY DISCOURSE AS THE FINAL CAUSE OF ALL INTELLECTUAL ENDEAVORS

2012-05-12 Thread John Harvey

Gary, Phyllis, list,

The use of ambiguity and precision or clarity as antonyms is what 
I. A. Richards might have called a killer dichotomy[1] which doesn't 
recognize they are all on the continuum of discourse academic as well as 
ordinary. Before a more precise term can be used by more than one 
person, someone has to define and explain it in the less precise (i.e. 
more ambiguous) vocabulary that is already understood by others. The 
limited communication which ambiguity provides is a hermeneutic path 
toward more understanding. In other words, ambiguity is a tool for 
achieving greater precision.


The x-ray example is a good illustration of a situation in which 
ambiguity and precision both have economic, health, ethical and 
semeiotic costs and benefits.


The question isn't, Is there perfect precision? Some of the questions 
are, Is there enough precision for the situation or context? and when 
necessary, How does further inquiry increase the precision and clarity 
of our understanding?


Regards, John

[1] Berthoff, Ann E., The Mysterious Barricades: Language and Its 
Limits (1999), p. 15-17.


The Mysterious Barricades makes the case that escaping the enthrallment 
of recent theory in literary criticism and the philosophy of language 
will be impossible so long as the meaning relationship is conceived in 
dyadic terms. Ann E. Berthoff examines certain dyadic 
misunderstandings, including the gangster theories fostered by 
Deconstruction and its successors, and offers triadic remedies, which 
are all informed by a Peircean understanding of interpretation as the 
logical condition of signification.--BOOK JACKET.


The remedies come from a logician, the inventor of semiotics (Peirce); 
a rhetorician who reclaimed practical criticism (I.A. Richards); a 
philologist who became the first to develop a general theory of 
hermeneutics (Schleiermacher); a linguist - some would say the greatest 
of the century (Sapir); a philosophical anthropologist who sought to 
define what we need to discover if we are to appreciate the role of 
symbols in building the human world (Susanne K. Langer); and an amateur 
semiotician novelist, and religious man who defined the capacity for 
symbolization as the power which sets the human being apart from the 
rest of Creation (Kleist). All have seen that pragmatism is the chief 
consequence of a triadic view of the sign. All have seen that the powers 
of language are contingent on its limits, whether linguistic or 
discursive. All recognize the heuristic power of limits, seeing them as 
mysterious barricades.


In a concluding section, Professor Berthoff turns to the idea of a 
fall into language by way of a discussion of Kleist's essays on 
marionette theatre and the shaping of thought at the point of utterance.


-
You are receiving this message because you are subscribed to the PEIRCE-L listserv.  To 
remove yourself from this list, send a message to lists...@listserv.iupui.edu with the 
line SIGNOFF PEIRCE-L in the body of the message.  To post a message to the 
list, send it to PEIRCE-L@LISTSERV.IUPUI.EDU


Re: [peirce-l] ORDINARY DISCOURSE AS THE FINAL CAUSE OF ALL INTELLECTUAL ENDEAVORS

2012-05-12 Thread Gary Moore
Dear John Harvey,
Gary Moore: Absolutely excellent! Before a more precise term can be used by 
more than one person, someone has to define and explain it in the less precise 
(i.e. more ambiguous) vocabulary that is already understood by others. The 
limited communication which ambiguity provides is a hermeneutic path toward 
more understanding. In other words, ambiguity is a tool for achieving greater 
precision. This is perfect! Ambiguity, established within a locating context, 
is therefore necessary for communication per se. Establish the context 
precisely and you sizably decrease, but never eliminate, the ambiguity. If what 
you say is important enough, at some time you must enunciate your thoughts to a 
wider, broader community. Peirce uses the term “prime necessity” as if it were 
a very precise scholastic logical term. And yet an explanation for “prime 
necessity” is not to be found anywhere in the Peirce sites nor in any major 
philosophy resource like the
 Stanford University Encyclopedia of Philosophy. If, on the other hand as I 
advocated, we had the literal Latin phrase he was referring to, I would have no 
problem locating at least a context in which it is used as “prime necessity”. 
Peirce praises it by saying, “He could not have sought out a more technical 
phrase” as it “strictly means”. And yet it is impossible to find except in this 
paragraph in “The Ethics of Terminology” (EP volume 2, page266). So it is 
hardly a model of intelligibility considering its lack of context and its near 
total lack of use.¶

Gary Moore: I. A. Richards I am mainly familiar with as a literary critic, 
obviously with a command of philosophy and logic. However one communicates in 
English, one uses literary or, better, rhetorical tropes that, while not 
necessarily being precisely logical (but not hindering it either), none the 
less state the existential fact a human being who is in a certain situation is 
making a statement. If done well, all parties, with their appropriate usage of 
ambiguity, can more or less correctly understand each other. Abuse the 
ambiguity as Peirce can do in a purely arbitrary fashion, people think, because 
he has said something extremely obscure, that it is extremely brilliant because 
either no one understands it or everyone is afraid of saying “The emperor has 
no clothes on,” that the great ‘truths’ are merely very ordinary pedestrian 
sideswipes.¶
-
Gary Moore: “The x-ray example is a good illustration of a situation in which 
ambiguity and precision both have economic, health, ethical and semeiotic 
costs and benefits.” The doctor is now being legally forced to explain why an 
x-ray is necessary and what it can and cannot do in common, though un-precise, 
terms. Instead of what? Instead of just doing the x-ray to legally say he did 
an x-ray to cover himself from legal suits without necessarily being of any use 
to the patient even from the most outlandish of possibilities, while at the 
same time economically harming the patient with a needless very expensive 
charge. As Churchill said of politics, “America and England are divided by a 
common language.”  Well, he had to break down and learn American context if he 
was going to get American money and weapons, did he not? No one was going to 
give those things to him simply because he wanted them.¶
---
Gary Moore:  Herein perfectly fits the following, “The question isn't, Is 
there perfect precision? Some of the questions are, Is there enough precision 
for the situation or context? and when necessary, How does further inquiry 
increase the precision and clarity of our understanding? “Further inquiry”, 
though, can only proceed from ambiguity as what is at hand to any possible 
precision.¶
--
Gary Moore: “In a concluding section, Professor Berthoff turns to the idea of 
a fall into language by way of a discussion of Kleist's essays on marionette 
theatre and the shaping of thought at the point of utterance. It has been a 
while since I have dealt with Kleist’s essays on marionettes and Immanuel Kant. 
Has a better format and treatment of his essays occurred I do not know about?
Regards,
Gary Moore
 
 

From: John Harvey johnhar...@earthlink.net
To: Peirce-L peirce-l@listserv.iupui.edu 
Sent: Saturday, May 12, 2012 10:28 AM
Subject: Re: [peirce-l] ORDINARY DISCOURSE AS THE FINAL CAUSE OF ALL 
INTELLECTUAL ENDEAVORS

Gary, Phyllis, list,

The use of ambiguity and precision or clarity as antonyms is what I. A. 
Richards might have called a killer dichotomy[1] which doesn't recognize they 
are all on the continuum of discourse academic as well as ordinary. Before a 
more precise term can be used by more than one person, someone has to define 
and explain it in the less precise (i.e. more ambiguous) vocabulary that is 
already understood by others. The limited communication which ambiguity 
provides is a hermeneutic path toward more understanding. In other 

Re: [peirce-l] ORDINARY DISCOURSE AS THE FINAL CAUSE OF ALL INTELLECTUAL ENDEAVORS

2012-05-12 Thread Benjamin Udell

Gary M., list,

In the passage that you quote from EP 2: 266, what Peirce says is,

   [] This scholastic terminology has passed into English speech
   more than into any other modern tongue, rendering it the most
   logically exact of any. This has been accomplished at the
   inconvenience that a considerable number of words and phrases have
   come to be used with a laxity quite astounding. Who, for example,
   among the dealers in Quincy Hall who talk of articles of /prime
   necessity/, would be able to say what that phrase prime necessity
   strictly means? He could not have sought out a more technical
   phrase. There are dozens of other loose expressions of the same
   provenance. 

Peirce isn't praising the phrase prime necessity by calling it most 
technical. He's just pointing out that people use, without knowing their 
meanings, phrases that are supposed to be reserved for technical senses. 
That much seems clear enough from the context. Less obvious is that 
prime necessity was no doubt in Peirce's view a good example because 
he thought pretty much nobody really knew what it meant.


   Still another threefold distinction, due to Aristotle (I Anal.
   post., iv), is between necessity /de omni/ (/tò katà pantós/), /per
   se / (/kath autó/), and /universaliter primum / (/kathólou prôton/).
   The last of these, however, is unintelligible, and we may pass it
   by, merely remarking that the exaggerated application of the term
   has given us a phrase we hear daily in the streets, 'articles of
   prime necessity.' Necessity /de omni/ is that of a predicate which
   belongs to its whole subject at all times. Necessity /per se/ is one
   belonging to the essence of the species, and is subdivided according
   to the senses of /per se/, especially into the first and second
   modes of /per se/. (Peirce, 1902, from his portion of Necessity in
   Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, James Mark Baldwin, editor,
   v. 2, p. 145 via Google Books
   
http://books.google.com/books?id=Dc8YIAAJpg=PA145lpg=PA145dq=%22Still+another+threefold+distinction%22
   and via Classics in the History of Psychology
   http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/Baldwin/Dictionary/defs/N1defs.htm#Necessity
   . 

I don't know what Latin word is being translated as necessity in that 
paragraph but, given the neuter adjective in /universaliter primum/ 
(literally, universally first), if it's a word with the necess- 
element in it, then it is /necesse/ (= /necessum/) or /necessarium/ 
(necessary, neuter adjectives) rather than /necessitas/ or 
/necessitudo/ (necessity, feminine abstract nouns).


Peirce can be terminologically demanding, but fortunately he defined 
many terms and phrases, in the Century Dictionary and in the Dictionary 
of Philosophy and Psychology. As for Peirce's own terminology, he 
defines some of it in those books, but the first place to look is the 
Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms 
http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/dictionary.html , edited by 
Mats Bergman and Sami Paavola, U. of Helsinki, and containing Peirce's 
own definitions, often many per term across the decades.


Gary Fuhrman very helpfully took a list of Peirce entries at the DPP 
that I started in Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography in Wikipedia, 
and expanded it to include Peirce entries for letters P-W (which aren't 
at the Classics in the History of Psychology). 
http://www.gnusystems.ca/BaldwinPeirce.htm . Where he has not also 
provided the text, he still provides the page number so that one can 
find it via Google Books' edition 
http://books.google.com/books?id=Dc8YIAAJpg=PA145lpg=PA145dq=%22Still+another+threefold+distinction%22 
or via Internet Archive's edition 
http://www.archive.org/details/philopsych02balduoft .


The Century Dictionary is online for free 
http://www.global-language.com/CENTURY/; it's bigger and more 
encyclopedic than the OED. I recommend installing the DjVu reader rather 
than settling for jpg images of pages. A list of the entries written or 
supervised/approved by Peirce is at 
http://www.pep.uqam.ca/listsofwords.pep . Peirce's work on the Century 
Dictionary will be in Writings vol. 7, now scheduled for 2013. Online 
software for W 7 is now planned (Peirce Edition Project April 2012 
Update http://www.iupui.edu/%7Epeirce/PEP-Update-April%202012.pdf ).


As regards ordinary discourse as the final cause of all intellectual 
endeavors, I'd say that ordinary discourse itself can evolve and become 
less vague and more specialized. Some ordinary discourse contains 
hundreds of ways to characterize snow; but not ordinary discourse in 
English, and most of us will not accumulate enough experience with snow 
to get what those characterizations are about. Yet for some those 
characterizations are very practical, often needful. Between highly 
developed ideas and ordinary ideas, there will usually be some struggle, 
it's a two-way street.


Best, Ben

On 5/12/2012 12:25 PM, Gary Moore wrote:


Dear John