RE: On a different strand of the seamless web

2014-07-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
   I’m not a fan of official prayers.  But it seems a plausible 
view of religious liberty that (1) people should have exemptions, when 
possible, that let them practice their religion, but (2) government 
institutions should have considerable latitude to include religious speech in 
their programs – so long as they don’t force people to pray – especially given 
longstanding American traditions approving of some such inclusion.  (In 
particular, being in the audience while a chaplain is praying strikes me as not 
that much to “endure,” and I say this as someone who is irreligious; while 
being required to participate would be wrong, I think, being required to simply 
be present in the room, or to briefly leave the room for the occasion, seems to 
me as quite a different matter.)  The view I describe here may not be 
everyone’s view of religious liberty, but it seems to me quite coherent, and 
has something to recommend it.

   Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 9:51 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: On a different strand of the seamless web

I very much appreciate Doug's post and his reference to Town of Greece.  The 
Becket Fund, which has very ably represented Hobby Lobby and others in the 
contraceptive cases, insists that it is committed to religious liberty.  
(Likewise many on this list.) But in Town of Greece, the Becket Fund filed an 
amicus brief on the side of the Town; it was aligned not with religious 
liberty, but rather with the power of government to shove prayer in the face of 
citizens who wanted to interact with elected officials without having to endure 
a worship exercise for someone else's faith.   If this is our constitutional 
tradition, as many argued, it is not a tradition of religious liberty.

On Sun, Jul 6, 2014 at 1:01 AM, Douglas Laycock 
dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
On Sat, 5 Jul 2014 11:02:00 -0700
 Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:


* * * *
Christians died rather than burn a pinch of incense to the emperor.


Yes they did. A point they entirely forget as they impose brief Christian 
prayer services on their fellow citizens at public meetings, and insist that 
it's no big deal to go through of motions of praying to a God you don't believe 
in.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.



--
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
Co-author (with Professor Robert Tuttle) of Secular Government, Religious 
People (forthcoming, summer 2014, Wm. B. Eerdmans Pub. Co.)
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Hobby Lobby Question

2014-07-06 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
I suppose that Jon's is the 64 billion dollar question. I think the answer 
would depend on the degree to which the single payer system was exclusive. If 
one could still purchase supplemental coverage (for heart transplants, say), 
then I assume the US could treat abortion as special. But if single-payer 
really did in all private insurance, then I assume that abortion would have to 
be covered. 

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

 On Jul 6, 2014, at 1:32 PM, mallamud malla...@camden.rutgers.edu wrote:
 
 Why wouldn't the Congress ban coverage of abortions under a single-payer 
 system?
   Jon
 
 On 2014-07-01 22:22, Levinson, Sanford V wrote:
 I do not understand why the complicity with evil rationale doesn't
 apply to taxpayers ( like Thoreau). The argument against is either
 that it would unduly burden the state to set up a c.o. system for tax
 protesters or that it would invite strategic misrepresentation. Are
 these sufficiently compelling interests to overcome undoubtedly
 sincere (and correct) beliefs that one's taxes are supporting
 oppression at home and around the world (as well as a lot of good
 things). As Uwe Reindhart points out, the craziest American
 exceptionalism is that workers are dependent on their employers for
 medical insurance. Hobby Lobby is another good argument for
 tax-financed single-payer coverage.
 
 Sandy
 
 Sent from my iPhone
 
 On Jun 30, 2014, at 11:48 PM, Steven Jamar stevenja...@gmail.com
 [13] wrote:
 
 The court accepts without inquiry the assertion that the complicity
 with evil theory is the problem that leads to the substantial
 burden. It merely accepts the claim that the adherents cannot comply
 because of the complicity theory. It then bootstraps that there
 would be costs of non-compliance.
 At the core the court buys the argument that an attenuated
 complicity can be the basis of a substantial burden.
 
 Sent from Steve's iPhone
 
 On Jul 1, 2014, at 12:20 AM, Arthur Spitzer artspit...@gmail.com
 [10] wrote:
 
 I'm puzzled by Steve Jamar's statement that yesterday's decision
 arguably requires all courts to simply accept the religious
 adherent's claim that the burden is substantial. The majority
 analyzed whether the burden was substantial and found it was
 because the ACA would impose millions of dollars of financial
 penalties on the plaintiffs if they did not comply. Slip op. at
 32. I don't think the Court tells us whether a $100 fine would
 have been a substantial burden. I'm curious what in the opinion
 Steve points to in support of the proposition that courts may not
 evaluate the substantiality of a burden, especially considering
 that the Court did evaluate that question, as an empirical matter,
 in this case.
 
 Art Spitzer
 
 WARNING: this message is subject to monitoring by the NSA.
 
 On Mon, Jun 30, 2014 at 11:17 PM, Steven Jamar
 stevenja...@gmail.com [7] wrote:
 
 Brown eliminated the constitutional doctrine of separate but
 equal -- in the Brown decision just for education, but it was
 applied to all racial classifications. The 1964 Civil Rights Act
 accomplished much more, of course, but the Brown decision
 matters a lot.
 
 So it is with numerous decisions. Hobby Lobby's acceptance of
 the complicity with evil theory in this attenuated context and
 its ruling that arguably requires all courts to simply accept
 the religious adherent's claim that the burden is substantial,
 could dramatically change the landscape of RFRA interpretation
 federally and by example at the state level. These underlying
 principles could also be restricted by later decisions or
 expanded. It is a very troubling expansion of RFRA beyond what
 was intended originally. But that is hardly unique to this bit
 of legislation.
 
 I think it is a very bad decision, but not even in the top ten.
 
 --
 Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox: 202-806-8017 [1]
 Director of International Programs, Institute for Intellectual
 Property and Social Justice http://iipsj.org [2]
 Howard University School of Law fax: 202-806-8567 [3]
 http://sdjlaw.org [4]
 
 For all men of good will May 17, 1954, came as a joyous
 daybreak to end the long night of enforced segregation. . . . It
 served to transform the fatigue of despair into the buoyancy of
 hope.
 
 Martin Luther King, Jr., in 1960 on Brown v. Board of Education
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu [5]
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw [6]
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be
 viewed as private. Anyone can subscribe to the list and read
 messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; and
 list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to
 others.
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu [8]
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 

RE: On a different strand of the seamless web

2014-07-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
   I take it that the authors of those briefs saw a law requiring 
someone to do something that they thought was sinful as different from a 
practice under which people end up hearing things from the government that they 
might find offensive or alienating.

   Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 11:10 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: On a different strand of the seamless web


I think Chips and Doug's key points in their posts are worth emphasizing. Many 
briefs supporting the town of Greece and the Court's opinion in that case 
treated the religious liberty arguments of plaintiffs with complete distain. 
The authors of many of those briefs and the same justices who wrote the opinion 
upholding coercive and discriminatory prayer practices  in Town of Greece 
insisted that the religious liberty of Hobby Lobby must be protected.



As Chip suggests, a tradition, or support for a legal regime, of religious 
liberty for me but not for you cannot be fairly described as a commitment to 
religious liberty.



An incidental, but not insignificant, result of this kind one-sided support for 
religious liberty is the burden it places on those of us who try to defend and 
promote religious liberty and equality for people on both sides of the culture 
wars.



Alan


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: On a different strand of the seamless web

2014-07-06 Thread Alan Brownstein
When people are asking government officials to exercise their discretion in a 
way that seriously impacts their important interests in a courtroom, at an 
administrative proceeding, in a government bureaucrat's office, in a classroom 
, or at the town hall meeting in a small town, I think it is intrinsically 
coercive for the officials or the chaplain they designate to ask the 
petitioners to stand, bow their heads and join them in collective prayer.

Indeed, I cannot imagine anyone not feeling pressured and coerced in that 
situation -- just as I believe there is a significant likelihood that a member 
of the small audience remaining seated while everyone else stands or leaving 
the room as the prayer begins will have an adverse influence of the officials 
who are being asked to exercise their discretion.



Alan










From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Volokh, Eugene [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 11:07 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: On a different strand of the seamless web

   I’m not a fan of official prayers.  But it seems a plausible 
view of religious liberty that (1) people should have exemptions, when 
possible, that let them practice their religion, but (2) government 
institutions should have considerable latitude to include religious speech in 
their programs – so long as they don’t force people to pray – especially given 
longstanding American traditions approving of some such inclusion.  (In 
particular, being in the audience while a chaplain is praying strikes me as not 
that much to “endure,” and I say this as someone who is irreligious; while 
being required to participate would be wrong, I think, being required to simply 
be present in the room, or to briefly leave the room for the occasion, seems to 
me as quite a different matter.)  The view I describe here may not be 
everyone’s view of religious liberty, but it seems to me quite coherent, and 
has something to recommend it.

   Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 9:51 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: On a different strand of the seamless web

I very much appreciate Doug's post and his reference to Town of Greece.  The 
Becket Fund, which has very ably represented Hobby Lobby and others in the 
contraceptive cases, insists that it is committed to religious liberty.  
(Likewise many on this list.) But in Town of Greece, the Becket Fund filed an 
amicus brief on the side of the Town; it was aligned not with religious 
liberty, but rather with the power of government to shove prayer in the face of 
citizens who wanted to interact with elected officials without having to endure 
a worship exercise for someone else's faith.   If this is our constitutional 
tradition, as many argued, it is not a tradition of religious liberty.

On Sun, Jul 6, 2014 at 1:01 AM, Douglas Laycock 
dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
On Sat, 5 Jul 2014 11:02:00 -0700
 Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:


* * * *
Christians died rather than burn a pinch of incense to the emperor.


Yes they did. A point they entirely forget as they impose brief Christian 
prayer services on their fellow citizens at public meetings, and insist that 
it's no big deal to go through of motions of praying to a God you don't believe 
in.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.



--
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
Co-author (with Professor Robert Tuttle) of Secular Government, Religious 
People (forthcoming, summer 2014, Wm. B. Eerdmans Pub. Co.)
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and 

Hobby Lobby: Narrow Holding but Potentially Momentous Nonetheless?

2014-07-06 Thread Marty Lederman
My thoughts on the longer-term ramifications of the decision.  The upshot
is that I think it's very important in two respects:  (i) the strong
affirmation of the holding in *Thomas *that civil authorities cannot
evaluate religious claims that X is a forbidden form of complicity with
evil; and, most importantly, as Micah, Rich and Nelson also stress in their
Slate piece, (ii) the shocking abandonment of pre-Smith doctrine as a guide
to applying RFRA.

http://balkin.blogspot.com/2014/07/hobby-lobby-part-xviii-one-potentially.html

As I say in the post, Chip was right 20 years ago:  Even if one favors a
statutory regime of religious accommodation, and thus supported RFRA -- as
I do and I did -- it turns out to have been a huge mistake for Congress to
use the words of strict scrutiny, when virtually no one supporting the
legislation actually favored such scrutiny.  In an age of Scalian
textualism, that was a disaster waiting to happen . . . and now, perhaps,
it has.

I'm curious:  Does anyone on the list (i) think the Court was right to say
(or at least come very close to holding) that pre-Smith doctrine is
inapposite to RFRA; and/or (ii) still think it was a good idea for Congress
to use least-restrictive-means language in RFRA?
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: On a different strand of the seamless web

2014-07-06 Thread Paul Finkelman


unlike Doug, I do not believe corporations are people, that they have 
religious believes or that they have souls (that is of course an 
understatement); corporations are legal vehicles designed to make money 
for the investors and to shield the investors from having to use their 
own assets to cover losses and debts. 

I do not believe any faith thinks Hobby Lobby has an immortal soul, can 
go to heaven or hell, or that it prays.  So, I guess I am unpersuaded that 
there can be an exemption issue for a corporation



 From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: Paul Finkelman paul.finkel...@yahoo.com; Law  Religion issues for Law 
Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu; Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu 
Sent: Sunday, July 6, 2014 11:36 AM
Subject: Re: On a different strand of the seamless web
 

Unlike Paul, I think the exemption issues and the government-sponsored prayer 
issues are very different.

On Sun, 6 Jul 2014 01:36:45 -0700
Paul Finkelman paul.finkel...@yahoo.com wrote:
Doug's point here seems to encapsulate what is the problem for so many of us.  
Those in the majority would make the rest of us burn incense, or listen to 
their prayers, or pay for their prayers or pray with them, or obey their views 
on sex and marriage and children, and we can go on and on.  And many in the 
majority forget that they were once persecuted, whether it was Christians 
killed in Rome or Baptists whipped in Virginia, and now that they have the 
power, they would impose it on us, whether it is health care if you are 
unfortunate enough to have to work for Hobby Lobby or prayers if you are 
unfortunate enough to need something form the government of the Town of Greece.

Paul Finkelman (writing from Granada, where the evidence and reminders of 
religious intolerance and persecution is everywhere)




 From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu; 
Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu 
Sent: Sunday, July 6, 2014 1:01 AM
Subject: On a different strand of the seamless web
 

On Sat, 5 Jul 2014 11:02:00 -0700
Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:


* * * *
Christians died rather than burn a pinch of incense to the emperor. 


Yes they did. A point they entirely forget as they impose brief Christian 
prayer services on their fellow citizens at public meetings, and insist that 
it's no big deal to go through of motions of praying to a God you don't 
believe in.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
     434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private. 
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people 
can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward 
the messages to others.


Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
     434-243-8546___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: On a different strand of the seamless web

2014-07-06 Thread Paul Finkelman
Eugene has obviously never been to a city council meeting or town board to ask 
for something.  Those in the audience in Town of Greece who do not pray are 
setting themselves up to lose before the board; those who are religious 
outsiders (by dress for example) are being told, from the opening of the 
meeting that they count less.

The Town said it invited clergy from all churches in the town.  But that is a 
subterfuge since many people in the town (a suburb of Rochester) will attend a 
temple, mosque, synagogue, etc. that is not in the town.  So the town is 
essentially confirming their outsider status even before they come before the 
council/town board.

Eugene, your view is utterly incoherent if you connect it to the reality of 
small town politics and how government at that level works.  


Paul Finkelman




 From: Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu 
Sent: Sunday, July 6, 2014 2:07 PM
Subject: RE: On a different strand of the seamless web
 


   I’m not a fan of official prayers.  But it seems a plausible 
view of religious liberty that (1) people should have exemptions, when 
possible, that let them practice their religion, but (2) government 
institutions should have considerable latitude to include religious speech in 
their programs – so long as they don’t force people to pray – especially given 
longstanding American traditions approving of some such inclusion.  (In 
particular, being in the audience while a chaplain is praying strikes me as not 
that much to “endure,” and I say this as someone who is irreligious; while 
being required to participate would be wrong, I think, being required to simply 
be present in the room, or to briefly leave the room for the occasion, seems to 
me as quite a different matter.)  The view I describe here may not be 
everyone’s view of religious liberty, but it seems to me quite coherent, and 
has something to recommend it.
 
   Eugene
 



From:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 9:51 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: On a different strand of the seamless web
 
I very much appreciate Doug's post and his reference to Town of Greece.  The 
Becket Fund, which has very ably represented Hobby Lobby and others in the 
contraceptive cases, insists that it is committed to religious liberty.  
(Likewise many on this list.) But in Town of Greece, the Becket Fund filed an 
amicus brief on the side of the Town; it was aligned not with religious 
liberty, but rather with the power of government to shove prayer in the face of 
citizens who wanted to interact with elected officials without having to endure 
a worship exercise for someone else's faith.   If this is our constitutional 
tradition, as many argued, it is not a tradition of religious liberty.
 
On Sun, Jul 6, 2014 at 1:01 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
On Sat, 5 Jul 2014 11:02:00 -0700
 Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:


* * * *
Christians died rather than burn a pinch of incense to the emperor.


Yes they did. A point they entirely forget as they impose brief Christian 
prayer services on their fellow citizens at public meetings, and insist that 
it's no big deal to go through of motions of praying to a God you don't believe 
in.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
     434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


 
-- 
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW 
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
Co-author (with Professor Robert Tuttle) of Secular Government, Religious 
People (forthcoming, summer 2014, Wm. B. Eerdmans Pub. Co.)
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to 

RE: Extent of Wheaton College's Objection

2014-07-06 Thread Michael Watson
Yes, Wheaton’s application referred to the legal effects of the Form 700.  But 
the legal effects correspond to what reasonably would be expected from its 
language, the required deliveries and the underlying regulations.  (One could 
imagine a similar notice structure being agreed to in a multiparty commercial 
transaction in which one party give notices which trigger contingent 
obligations of another party owed to yet another.)  Suppose the problematic 
form language and third-party deliveries are dispensed with, and the 
government, for whatever reasons, decides to support continuation of the 
desired coverage by deeming the college’s notice to the government of its 
religious objection as having the same effect as a Form 700 sent to the 
originally required recipients (also requiring the government itself to step in 
and send notices).  It seems to me the college would then have significantly 
less reason to object through legal means.

Granted, Wheaton will presumably not be pleased that the funding of what it 
considers objectionable will continue.  But it seems to me the college could 
reasonably take the view that it is responsible for its own actions and the 
consequences that may ordinarily be expected to flow from them.  A governmental 
“deeming” (and other action the government would need to take) would result in 
the same funding outcome but only because the deeming changes the ordinarily 
expected consequences of Wheaton’s more limited action.  The result of the 
changes would be to displace the college from its former position in the causal 
chain except for the initial act of registering its religious objection with 
the government.  The government will still do what it will do, but without the 
direct involvement of the college.

I do not know what Wheaton will do.  But it seems to me if they were to be 
satisfied with a final outcome as seems to be suggested in the Court’s 
injunction order, this would not evidence flawed moral reasoning or 
inconsistency (or for that matter, “increasingly implausible theories of 
complicity” if this is included in what people are referring to in the other 
thread).

 

-Mike Watson

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Saturday, July 05, 2014 1:44 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Extent of Wheaton College's Objection

 

As I said, we shall see what Wheaton's reaction would be if and when the 
government were to treat the new notification as having the same legal effect 
as Form 700.  You'll note that their papers describe their legal complicity as 
being very closely tied to the legal effects of Form 700.

Becket attorneys on this list could, of course, tell us right now what that 
reaction would be . . . but if I were them, I'd wait to see what the government 
does first, and what its legal theory is

 for whatever it does.  ;-)

 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Hobby Lobby: Narrow Holding but Potentially Momentous Nonetheless?

2014-07-06 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
Marty, on your two questions:

1. I don't think the Court said that pre-Smith doctrine is inapposite to 
RFRA.  Indeed, it looked at a lot of pre-Smith free exercise law; and on the 
particular question whether a for-profit corporation has ability to assert free 
exercise claims at the threshold, it found indications in the Crown Heights 
Kosher Supermarket case (1961) that they do.  Slip op. at 26-27 (referring to 
the fact that not one justice in that case adopted the state's argument that a 
for-profit corporation has no standing to assert a free exercise claim).  The 
Court here simply said, correctly, that [e]ven if RFRA was meant to restore 
the status quo ante, there is no reason to believe, as HHS and the dissent seem 
to suggest, that the law was meant to be limited to situations that fall 
squarely within the holdings of pre-Smith cases.

The Court's approach seems to me justified for at least three reasons.
   (a) There was no pre-Smith decision, certainly not in the SCOTUS, rejecting 
for-profit corporations' standing either; it was an open question, on which 
both sides used statutory-purpose arguments as well as case law.
   (b) The legislative history makes clear that the statute does not codif[y] 
the result reached in any prior free exercise decision, only the legal 
standard that was applied in those decisions.  Whatever the line is between 
principles and results, the two don't collapse, and it's the former that govern.
   (c) Finally, as several of us have argued since the statute passed, the 
stated textual purpose is to restore the compelling interest test as set forth 
in Sherbert and Yoder, not as in every pre-Smith decision, especially those in 
lower courts--so if a line of reasoning from such a pre-Smith decision is 
inconsistent with the logic of Sherbert and Yoder, it is probably not warranted 
under the statute.  I take Sherbert and Yoder to have given serious but not 
automatic protection.  That formulation is quite general, I admit, but I think 
it points toward something more than just whatever courts said in any 
exemption case pre-Smith.

2. On least restrictive means, I was quoted by Justice Ginsburg in Hobby 
Lobby (dissent at 12), along with Doug Laycock, for the proposition that the 
concept appeared in pre-Smith law.  (If those are gotcha quotes, I take them 
as a compliment: As long as you spell my name right...).  On this point, I 
believe (still) that the dissent is correct and that the majority was wrong 
both here and in Boerne.  Sherbert clearly referred to no alternative means of 
regulation, Yoder to interests ... not otherwise served.  I just don't think 
that the pre-Smith applications in any way foreclosed what the Court did here, 
which was to apply the least restrictive means phrase pretty carefully--and 
ultimately cautiously--in the commercial context.  The non-profit accommodation 
seemed to be readily available as an alternative means, and Kennedy 
particularly emphasized it.  It will end up as the alternative means in some 
modified form/procedure, I think, after the non-profit challenges play out, for 
some of the reasons you and Tom Goldstein have been discussing.  I don't think 
it is necessary to have a highly severe least restrictive means standard to 
justify the result in Hobby Lobby.

I think that least restrictive means will apply with different degrees of 
severity in different contexts.  That's basically what it's done in the 20 
years of RFRA; and in end Hobby Lobby (factoring in Kennedy's opinion) read it 
fairly cautiously in the commercial context.  Yes, that's a good idea.

Many people who are unhappy that least restrictive means put any constraint 
on the government here will be happy in the upcoming case when it constrains 
the Arkansas prison that refuses to let a Muslim prisoner grow a half-inch 
beard.  Prisons can always claim a compelling interest in safety; often the 
least-restrictive-means test is the crucial part forcing them to show some 
connection between safety (or other interests like cost) and the restriction 
they're imposing.

Tom

-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy
University of St. Thomas School of Law
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edumailto:tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Marty Lederman [lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 3:36 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Hobby Lobby: Narrow Holding but Potentially Momentous Nonetheless?

My thoughts on the longer-term ramifications of the decision.  The upshot is 
that I think it's very important in two 

RE: Hobby Lobby: Narrow Holding but Potentially Momentous Nonetheless?

2014-07-06 Thread Alan Brownstein
A few quick thoughts on Marty's second question. At least some of us saw value 
in religious liberty legislation employing an intermediate level scrutiny 
standard of review rather than strict scrutiny years ago. I worked with a group 
trying to get a state religious land use bill adopted in California prior to 
RLUIPA being enacted by Congress and our bill called for intermediate level 
scrutiny.



I thought the shift to intermediate level scrutiny in a land use bill was a 
good idea for both political and policy reasons. There are very few land use 
regulations that can survive either prong of strict scrutiny if it is 
rigorously applied. But there might be other circumstances outside of the land 
use context in which I would support more rigorous review. I thought RLUIPA 
involved very strange bedfellows because a rigorous review of the means 
employed by prisons seemed more appropriate in these cases since the compelling 
state interest was typically a foregone conclusion in prison cases. It may be 
that religious liberty legislation should be generic to some extent -- but not 
as broad as RFRA or even RLUIPA.



In any case, the opponents of our land use bill fought it just as aggressively 
as they would have fought a strict scrutiny bill -- and succeeded in killing 
the bill. Some interest groups and legislators seemed to be genuinely concerned 
about the lack of guidance an intermediate level scrutiny standard provided. 
And some legislators seemed genuinely befuddled by the move to intermediate 
level scrutiny (or were putting on a good act to conceal the fact that they 
opposed the bill for other reasons that they preferred not to disclose.) I 
still remember a member of the state judiciary committee (someone who I thought 
was a generally thoughtful legislator) trying to explain to me why he had no 
problem with religious liberty statutes that applied a minimal reasonableness 
standard of review and he had supported a state RFRA bill the year before that 
required strict scrutiny review -- but there was something about intermediate 
level scrutiny that seemed so problematic to him that he could not support the 
bill.



So Marty is probably right that more thought should have been given to the 
standard of review to be applied. But determining what would be an appropriate 
standard of review is not an easy question to answer.



Alan










From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Marty Lederman [lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 1:36 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Hobby Lobby: Narrow Holding but Potentially Momentous Nonetheless?

My thoughts on the longer-term ramifications of the decision.  The upshot is 
that I think it's very important in two respects:  (i) the strong affirmation 
of the holding in Thomas that civil authorities cannot evaluate religious 
claims that X is a forbidden form of complicity with evil; and, most 
importantly, as Micah, Rich and Nelson also stress in their Slate piece, (ii) 
the shocking abandonment of pre-Smith doctrine as a guide to applying RFRA.

http://balkin.blogspot.com/2014/07/hobby-lobby-part-xviii-one-potentially.html

As I say in the post, Chip was right 20 years ago:  Even if one favors a 
statutory regime of religious accommodation, and thus supported RFRA -- as I do 
and I did -- it turns out to have been a huge mistake for Congress to use the 
words of strict scrutiny, when virtually no one supporting the legislation 
actually favored such scrutiny.  In an age of Scalian textualism, that was a 
disaster waiting to happen . . . and now, perhaps, it has.

I'm curious:  Does anyone on the list (i) think the Court was right to say (or 
at least come very close to holding) that pre-Smith doctrine is inapposite to 
RFRA; and/or (ii) still think it was a good idea for Congress to use 
least-restrictive-means language in RFRA?






___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Hobby Lobby: Narrow Holding but Potentially Momentous Nonetheless?

2014-07-06 Thread Marty Lederman
Thanks, Tom.  Yes, as Chip's article helpfully elaborates, back in the
early 1990s there was a tension between those who wished to frame the
statute as a restoration of the doctrine as it stood on April 16, 1990, and
those who wished to restore simply Sherbert and Yoder, and to jettison
the entire rest of the Court's jurisprudence, including Lee, Hernandez,
Jimmy Swaggart, Tony  Susan Alamo, etc.  Quite frankly, based on my
recollection, I think that there was a great deal of reliance among
legislators -- especially by abortion opponents -- on the former view:
They were repeatedly assured that the point of the statute was to restore
the state of affairs as of 04/90, except that the enclaves (military and
prisons) would no longer get special treatment.  And, more to the point,
I've never run across anyone, in the executive branch or the private
sector, who has not simply assumed for the past two decades that RFRA
incorporates the whole corpus of pre-Smith Supreme Court jurisprudence.
Therefore the signals from the HL Court to the contrary are, to my mind, a
radical shift, and not at all reflective of congressional intent.

As my post explains, I agree with you that the pre-Smith applications did
not foreclose what the Court *did* here, which was (in your words) to apply
the least restrictive means test pretty carefully--and ultimately
cautiously--in the commercial context, and to grant the exemption only
because there would be no significant third-party harms.

But what it did and what it said are two different things.  It could have
distinguished Lee (as I do) by saying that this is the rare case in which
an exemption for an employer will not harm others.  But instead, both at
oral argument and in the opinion, the Justices said:  Who cares about
Lee?  It was a free exercise case and did not apply a LRM test.

You are also correct that Alito does *selectively* invoke pre-Smith
precedents.  That's my point:  The precedents that are strongly
pro-exemption (not only Thomas but even Gallagher, hardly part of the
canon!) still have generative force for him . . . but not the long series
of cases in which claims to exemptions in the commercial sphere got almost
no votes, for decades.


On Sun, Jul 6, 2014 at 6:27 PM, Berg, Thomas C. tcb...@stthomas.edu wrote:

  Marty, on your two questions:

 1. I don't think the Court said that pre-Smith doctrine is inapposite to
 RFRA.  Indeed, it looked at a lot of pre-Smith free exercise law; and on
 the particular question whether a for-profit corporation has ability to
 assert free exercise claims at the threshold, it found indications in the
 Crown Heights Kosher Supermarket case (1961) that they do.  Slip op. at
 26-27 (referring to the fact that not one justice in that case adopted the
 state's argument that a for-profit corporation has no standing to assert a
 free exercise claim).  The Court here simply said, correctly, that [e]ven
 if RFRA was meant to restore the status quo ante, there is no reason to
 believe, as HHS and the dissent seem to suggest, that the law was meant to
 be limited to situations that fall squarely within the holdings of
 pre-Smith cases.

 The Court's approach seems to me justified for at least three reasons.
(a) There was no pre-Smith decision, certainly not in the SCOTUS,
 rejecting for-profit corporations' standing either; it was an open
 question, on which both sides used statutory-purpose arguments as well as
 case law.
(b) The legislative history makes clear that the statute does not
 codif[y] the result reached in any prior free exercise decision, only
 the legal standard that was applied in those decisions.  Whatever the
 line is between principles and results, the two don't collapse, and it's
 the former that govern.
(c) Finally, as several of us have argued since the statute passed, the
 stated textual purpose is to restore the compelling interest test as set
 forth in Sherbert and Yoder, not as in every pre-Smith decision,
 especially those in lower courts--so if a line of reasoning from such a
 pre-Smith decision is inconsistent with the logic of Sherbert and Yoder, it
 is probably not warranted under the statute.  I take Sherbert and Yoder to
 have given serious but not automatic protection.  That formulation is quite
 general, I admit, but I think it points toward something more than just
 whatever courts said in any exemption case pre-Smith.

 2. On least restrictive means, I was quoted by Justice Ginsburg in Hobby
 Lobby (dissent at 12), along with Doug Laycock, for the proposition that
 the concept appeared in pre-Smith law.  (If those are gotcha quotes, I
 take them as a compliment: As long as you spell my name right...).  On
 this point, I believe (still) that the dissent is correct and that the
 majority was wrong both here and in Boerne.  Sherbert clearly referred to
 no alternative means of regulation, Yoder to interests ... not otherwise
 served.  I just don't think that the pre-Smith applications in any way
 

RE: Hobby Lobby: Narrow Holding but Potentially Momentous Nonetheless?

2014-07-06 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
(I and others on the list can read your Balk. post too, but for now...)

If the proposition is that every statement in that paragraph in US v. Lee is 
determinative for RFRA, then Lee also foreclosed the Court from turning to the 
insurer-pays accommodation even assuming it imposed no costs on employees. In 
that same paragraph, Lee said that for commercial actors the limits they 
accept on their own conduct as a matter of conscience and faith are not to be 
superimposed on the statutory schemes which are binding on others in that 
activity.  That would mean, as the government argued, no accommodation period, 
even if it was easy and had no effect on employees.

To conclude that Lee didn't foreclose the Court from looking to the nonprofit 
accommodation, you have to say that that sentence by itself is 
dictum--potentially tempered, as in many cases, by other statements in this and 
other cases if that's justified on other interpretive grounds.  So you, and I, 
like the justices, are engaged in the project of interpreting U.S. v. Lee and 
selecting what part that must be carried over into RFRA to be most consistent 
with the statute.  It's not a matter of one side or the other ignoring it, or 
being selective in some unacceptable way.  Alito does apply Lee and reads the 
key holding, most consistent with RFRA, as collecting taxes is the least 
restrictive means.  And the other for-profit cases pre-Smith were mostly 
discrimination cases, which--however they should be resolved--present different 
questions than the case where there's an alternative mechanism at hand for 
providing the benefits.

On whether the expectation was that there would be no claims by for-profit 
businesses that might have any effect on anyone else, I think Doug's brief for 
the Christian Legal Society shows, based on the deleted earlier language and 
the public meaning as revealed in the RLPA debate, that members on both sides, 
when they considered it, thought the statute meant for-profits could still make 
a claim and have it judged, even if they might lose in most cases.  (I have to 
know what harm means to evaluate whether that's beyond RFRA's protection.  If 
harm is not qualified somehow, it can cover anything.  If a law required 
certain businesses to stay open 7 days a week, an objection by a Sabbath 
observer could be characterized as a harm to customers even if the vast 
majority of businesses were willing to stay open.  You and I agree at least 
that for-profit objectors will lose most cases; the question is whether they 
must lose all of them.)

-
Thomas C. Berg
James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy
University of St. Thomas School of Law
MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
Phone: 651 962 4918
Fax: 651 962 4881
E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edumailto:tcb...@stthomas.edu
SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Marty Lederman [lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 5:55 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Hobby Lobby: Narrow Holding but Potentially Momentous Nonetheless?

Thanks, Tom.  Yes, as Chip's article helpfully elaborates, back in the early 
1990s there was a tension between those who wished to frame the statute as a 
restoration of the doctrine as it stood on April 16, 1990, and those who wished 
to restore simply Sherbert and Yoder, and to jettison the entire rest of the 
Court's jurisprudence, including Lee, Hernandez, Jimmy Swaggart, Tony  Susan 
Alamo, etc.  Quite frankly, based on my recollection, I think that there was a 
great deal of reliance among legislators -- especially by abortion opponents -- 
on the former view:  They were repeatedly assured that the point of the statute 
was to restore the state of affairs as of 04/90, except that the enclaves 
(military and prisons) would no longer get special treatment.  And, more to the 
point, I've never run across anyone, in the executive branch or the private 
sector, who has not simply assumed for the past two decades that RFRA 
incorporates the whole corpus of pre-Smith Supreme Court jurisprudence.  
Therefore the signals from the HL Court to the contrary are, to my mind, a 
radical shift, and not at all reflective of congressional intent.

As my post explains, I agree with you that the pre-Smith applications did not 
foreclose what the Court did here, which was (in your words) to apply the 
least restrictive means test pretty carefully--and ultimately cautiously--in 
the commercial context, and to grant the exemption only because there would be 
no significant third-party harms.

But what it did and what it said are two different things.  It could have 
distinguished Lee (as I do) by saying that this is the rare 

RE: On a different strand of the seamless web

2014-07-06 Thread Friedman, Howard M.
It seems to me that Justice Alito rather nicely avoided having to deal with the 
question of how much a corporation is like a real person (including whether it 
has a soul, etc.), and also avoided dealing with the well-developed piercing 
the corporate veil doctrine by adopting a view of corporations long held by 
law-and-economics scholars.  In this view, a corporation is not primarily an 
artificial entity or person.  Instead it is merely a nexis of a large number of 
implicit and explicit contracts among investors, managers, employees, suppliers 
and customers that define their relative rights.  Alito says at pg. 18:

A corporation is simply a form of organization used by human beings to achieve 
desired ends. An established body of law specifies the rights and obligations 
of the people (including shareholders, officers, and employees) who are 
associated with a corporation in one way or another. When rights, whether 
constitutional or statutory, are extended to corporations, the purpose is to 
protect the rights of these people. [P]rotecting the free-exercise rights 
of corporations like Hobby Lobby, Conestoga, and Mardel protects the religious 
liberty of the humans who own and control those companies.

Indeed many small businesses involved in other cases challenging the 
contraceptive mandate are organized as Limited Liability Companies instead of 
closely held corporations. LLC's are more clearly creatures of contract.  It 
will be interesting to see whether this nexis of contracts approach will be 
used in other corporate cases having nothing to do with RFRA.

Howard Friedman

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Volokh, Eugene [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 7:11 PM
To: Paul Finkelman; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; Douglas Laycock; 
Scarberry, Mark
Subject: RE: On a different strand of the seamless web

   Paul:  Are you seriously claiming that Doug believes a 
corporation has a soul?  Or even that he believes it is a person (the singular 
of “people”) in the lay sense of the word “person,” as opposed to the 
Dictionary Act sense of the person?

   Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Paul Finkelman
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 1:48 PM
To: Douglas Laycock; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; Scarberry, Mark
Subject: Re: On a different strand of the seamless web


unlike Doug, I do not believe corporations are people, that they have religious 
believes or that they have souls (that is of course an understatement); 
corporations are legal vehicles designed to make money for the investors and to 
shield the investors from having to use their own assets to cover losses and 
debts.

I do not believe any faith thinks Hobby Lobby has an immortal soul, can go to 
heaven or hell, or that it prays.  So, I guess I am unpersuaded that there can 
be an exemption issue for a corporation


From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: Paul Finkelman paul.finkel...@yahoo.commailto:paul.finkel...@yahoo.com; 
Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu; Scarberry, 
Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu
Sent: Sunday, July 6, 2014 11:36 AM
Subject: Re: On a different strand of the seamless web

Unlike Paul, I think the exemption issues and the government-sponsored prayer 
issues are very different.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Hobby Lobby Question

2014-07-06 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
Mark may well be right, but why would a clearly constitutional single payer 
system elicit such disobedience (and arguments about complicity) but the 
funding of deeply immoral wars and complicity with a number of terrible regimes 
do not?  This is meant as a serious question. Abortion has become like the 
Stamp Tax, a perfectly reasonable effort by the UK to recover from the costs of 
the Seven Years War, but  (we now know) the trigger for the American 
Revolution.  Or is the better analogy to slavery, where compromise was 
ultimately impossible (for better or worse)?

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Jul 6, 2014, at 4:14 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

And then we would have massive resistance that would make our largely voluntary 
tax system unworkable and create civil division at extreme levels.

Think, as mentioned at AALS, peasants with pitchforks.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine University School of Law

Sent from my Verizon Wireless 4G LTE Smartphone


 Original message 
From: Levinson, Sanford V
Date:07/06/2014 11:13 AM (GMT-08:00)
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Hobby Lobby Question

I suppose that Jon's is the 64 billion dollar question. I think the answer 
would depend on the degree to which the single payer system was exclusive. If 
one could still purchase supplemental coverage (for heart transplants, say), 
then I assume the US could treat abortion as special. But if single-payer 
really did in all private insurance, then I assume that abortion would have to 
be covered.

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

 On Jul 6, 2014, at 1:32 PM, mallamud 
 malla...@camden.rutgers.edumailto:malla...@camden.rutgers.edu wrote:

 Why wouldn't the Congress ban coverage of abortions under a single-payer 
 system?
   Jon

 On 2014-07-01 22:22, Levinson, Sanford V wrote:
 I do not understand why the complicity with evil rationale doesn't
 apply to taxpayers ( like Thoreau). The argument against is either
 that it would unduly burden the state to set up a c.o. system for tax
 protesters or that it would invite strategic misrepresentation. Are
 these sufficiently compelling interests to overcome undoubtedly
 sincere (and correct) beliefs that one's taxes are supporting
 oppression at home and around the world (as well as a lot of good
 things). As Uwe Reindhart points out, the craziest American
 exceptionalism is that workers are dependent on their employers for
 medical insurance. Hobby Lobby is another good argument for
 tax-financed single-payer coverage.

 Sandy

 Sent from my iPhone

 On Jun 30, 2014, at 11:48 PM, Steven Jamar 
 stevenja...@gmail.commailto:stevenja...@gmail.com
 [13] wrote:

 The court accepts without inquiry the assertion that the complicity
 with evil theory is the problem that leads to the substantial
 burden. It merely accepts the claim that the adherents cannot comply
 because of the complicity theory. It then bootstraps that there
 would be costs of non-compliance.
 At the core the court buys the argument that an attenuated
 complicity can be the basis of a substantial burden.

 Sent from Steve's iPhone

 On Jul 1, 2014, at 12:20 AM, Arthur Spitzer 
 artspit...@gmail.commailto:artspit...@gmail.com
 [10] wrote:

 I'm puzzled by Steve Jamar's statement that yesterday's decision
 arguably requires all courts to simply accept the religious
 adherent's claim that the burden is substantial. The majority
 analyzed whether the burden was substantial and found it was
 because the ACA would impose millions of dollars of financial
 penalties on the plaintiffs if they did not comply. Slip op. at
 32. I don't think the Court tells us whether a $100 fine would
 have been a substantial burden. I'm curious what in the opinion
 Steve points to in support of the proposition that courts may not
 evaluate the substantiality of a burden, especially considering
 that the Court did evaluate that question, as an empirical matter,
 in this case.

 Art Spitzer

 WARNING: this message is subject to monitoring by the NSA.

 On Mon, Jun 30, 2014 at 11:17 PM, Steven Jamar
 stevenja...@gmail.commailto:stevenja...@gmail.com [7] wrote:

 Brown eliminated the constitutional doctrine of separate but
 equal -- in the Brown decision just for education, but it was
 applied to all racial classifications. The 1964 Civil Rights Act
 accomplished much more, of course, but the Brown decision
 matters a lot.

 So it is with numerous decisions. Hobby Lobby's acceptance of
 the complicity with evil theory in this attenuated context and
 its ruling that arguably requires all courts to simply accept
 the religious adherent's claim that the burden is substantial,
 could dramatically change the landscape of RFRA interpretation
 federally and by example at the state level. These underlying
 principles could also be restricted by later decisions or
 expanded. It is a very troubling expansion of RFRA beyond what
 was intended 

RE: On a different strand of the seamless web

2014-07-06 Thread Brad Pardee
Hobby Lobby itself as a corporation may not have religious beliefs or an
immortal soul, but the decisions made for the corporation are made by people
who do, as is true for all corporations, large and small.  If a corporation
had, for instance, engaged int trade with South Africa during apartheid,
people wouldn't have simply condemned the corporation.  They would have
condemned the people who made the decision for the corporation to trade with
South Africa.  Similarly, it is people with religious beliefs who make the
decisions for Hobby Lobby.  It is people who establish the values that the
corporation operates under and it is people who make the decisions as to
what activities the corporation will engage in.  There are people who have
deeply held religious beliefs that govern the way they live in every aspect
of their lives, and to require them to act amorally, solely in pursuit of
money, in the office is to say that the law which is supposed to guarantee
religious liberty also mandates abject hypocrisy.  Either that, or
corporations should have on the board room door, Abandon faith, all ye who
enter here.

 

Brad

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Paul Finkelman
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 3:48 PM
To: Douglas Laycock; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; Scarberry,
Mark
Subject: Re: On a different strand of the seamless web

 

 

unlike Doug, I do not believe corporations are people, that they have
religious believes or that they have souls (that is of course an
understatement); corporations are legal vehicles designed to make money for
the investors and to shield the investors from having to use their own
assets to cover losses and debts. 

 

I do not believe any faith thinks Hobby Lobby has an immortal soul, can go
to heaven or hell, or that it prays.  So, I guess I am unpersuaded that
there can be an exemption issue for a corporation

 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: On a different strand of the seamless web

2014-07-06 Thread J. Mallory
The boat for equitable treatment in chaplaincy practices sailed in 2005. 
Simpson v. Chesterfield County Bd. of Supervisors (4th Cir.) explicitly taught 
that a local government may favor Judeo-Christian practices and prayers over 
others, but also implicitly taught that other practices may be refused even if 
offered and otherwise consistent with the rules simply because they are 
disliked. Cyndi Simpson was told she could not participate as a chaplain 
because she was Wiccan, and for no other reason. (One wonders whether cert 
would be denied now as it was back then.)

I would mildly disagree, however, with characterizing chaplaincy practices 
uniformly as shov[ing] prayer in the face of citizens. That is surely 
characteristic of one type of practice--where the prayergiver is outward 
facing and preaches more at the gallery than the legislators--but it is not 
characteristic of the quieter, more inward-facing practices found in the houses 
of Congress. Town of Greece's fatal flaw is that it blessed the historical 
practice encompassed by Marsh without realizing that said historical practice 
was pretty much only the latter type, not the former. 

The liberty for me but not for thee scent has been in the air for a while and 
should come as no surprise. The question in my mind is whether the Court will 
be willing to incorporate elements of religious ethics from other traditions 
into their decisions as they did with Hobby Lobby and the doctrine of 
cooperation with evil. My wager is no, but I will allow myself to be surprised.

Jeremy

On Jul 6, 2014, at 1:10 PM, Alan Brownstein aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu wrote:

 I think Chips and Doug's key points in their posts are worth emphasizing. 
 Many briefs supporting the town of Greece and the Court's opinion in that 
 case treated the religious liberty arguments of plaintiffs with complete 
 distain. The authors of many of those briefs and the same justices who wrote 
 the opinion upholding coercive and discriminatory prayer practices  in Town 
 of Greece insisted that the religious liberty of Hobby Lobby must be 
 protected.
  
 As Chip suggests, a tradition, or support for a legal regime, of religious 
 liberty for me but not for you cannot be fairly described as a commitment to 
 religious liberty.
  
 An incidental, but not insignificant, result of this kind one-sided support 
 for religious liberty is the burden it places on those of us who try to 
 defend and promote religious liberty and equality for people on both sides of 
 the culture wars.
  
 Alan
  
   
  
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
 on behalf of Ira Lupu [icl...@law.gwu.edu]
 Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 9:51 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: On a different strand of the seamless web
 
 I very much appreciate Doug's post and his reference to Town of Greece.  The 
 Becket Fund, which has very ably represented Hobby Lobby and others in the 
 contraceptive cases, insists that it is committed to religious liberty.  
 (Likewise many on this list.) But in Town of Greece, the Becket Fund filed an 
 amicus brief on the side of the Town; it was aligned not with religious 
 liberty, but rather with the power of government to shove prayer in the face 
 of citizens who wanted to interact with elected officials without having to 
 endure a worship exercise for someone else's faith.   If this is our 
 constitutional tradition, as many argued, it is not a tradition of religious 
 liberty.
 
 
 On Sun, Jul 6, 2014 at 1:01 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
 On Sat, 5 Jul 2014 11:02:00 -0700
  Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
 
 
 * * * *
 Christians died rather than burn a pinch of incense to the emperor.
 
 
 Yes they did. A point they entirely forget as they impose brief Christian 
 prayer services on their fellow citizens at public meetings, and insist that 
 it's no big deal to go through of motions of praying to a God you don't 
 believe in.
 
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
 
 
 
 -- 
 Ira C. Lupu
 F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
 George Washington University Law School
 2000 H St., NW 
 Washington, DC 20052
 (202)994-7053
 Co-author (with Professor Robert Tuttle) of Secular Government, Religious 
 People (forthcoming, summer 2014, Wm. B. Eerdmans Pub. Co.)
 

RE: On a different strand of the seamless web

2014-07-06 Thread Volokh, Eugene
   Sandy:  I appreciate your point, and it is certainly a view held 
by many serious scholars.  But my point is simply that it isn't at all obvious 
that this indeed involves an Establishment Clause violation - and that, 
especially it isn't obvious that this involves religious liberty (Alan's 
phrase, to which I was specifically responding), and indeed many serious 
scholars think the two are quite different.  Among other things, being ordered 
to do (or not do) something strikes me as more clearly a matter of liberty 
than hearing things from the government.

   Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Levinson, Sanford V
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 1:31 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: On a different strand of the seamless web

I think that once one is hearing from government offensive theological views, 
the Establishment Clause is fully implicated. It is prudence, and nothing else, 
that legitimizes In God We Trust.  (That's why the court had to invent an 
implausible standing doctrine to avoid deciding in Newdow's favor.)  But I 
think there's a role for prudence, as against all principle all the time.

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Jul 6, 2014, at 2:26 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
   I take it that the authors of those briefs saw a law requiring 
someone to do something that they thought was sinful as different from a 
practice under which people end up hearing things from the government that they 
might find offensive or alienating.

   Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 11:10 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: On a different strand of the seamless web


I think Chips and Doug's key points in their posts are worth emphasizing. Many 
briefs supporting the town of Greece and the Court's opinion in that case 
treated the religious liberty arguments of plaintiffs with complete distain. 
The authors of many of those briefs and the same justices who wrote the opinion 
upholding coercive and discriminatory prayer practices  in Town of Greece 
insisted that the religious liberty of Hobby Lobby must be protected.



As Chip suggests, a tradition, or support for a legal regime, of religious 
liberty for me but not for you cannot be fairly described as a commitment to 
religious liberty.



An incidental, but not insignificant, result of this kind one-sided support for 
religious liberty is the burden it places on those of us who try to defend and 
promote religious liberty and equality for people on both sides of the culture 
wars.



Alan


___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: On a different strand of the seamless web

2014-07-06 Thread Douglas Laycock
Even in the rare case of government-sponsored prayer where no one is coerced to 
participate, the government is gratuitously telling citizens that its religion 
is true and their religion is false. Telling people what religious beliefs are 
true was one important element of the classic establishments.

But apart from all that, in the real world citizens who attend the meeting are 
forced to participate in the prayer. The government pressures religious 
dissenters directly in these situatins, and it creates the occasion for intense 
pressure on religious dissenters from their fellow citrizens. To deny or ignore 
all this, as the Court did in Greece, is simply out of touch with human 
reality. 

On Sun, 6 Jul 2014 21:57:27 -0700
 Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
   Sandy:  I appreciate your point, and it is certainly a view 
 held by many serious scholars.  But my point is simply that it isn't at all 
 obvious that this indeed involves an Establishment Clause violation - and 
 that, especially it isn't obvious that this involves religious liberty 
 (Alan's phrase, to which I was specifically responding), and indeed many 
 serious scholars think the two are quite different.  Among other things, 
 being ordered to do (or not do) something strikes me as more clearly a matter 
 of liberty than hearing things from the government.

   Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Levinson, Sanford V
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 1:31 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: On a different strand of the seamless web

I think that once one is hearing from government offensive theological 
views, the Establishment Clause is fully implicated. It is prudence, and 
nothing else, that legitimizes In God We Trust.  (That's why the court had 
to invent an implausible standing doctrine to avoid deciding in Newdow's 
favor.)  But I think there's a role for prudence, as against all principle all 
the time.

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Jul 6, 2014, at 2:26 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
   I take it that the authors of those briefs saw a law requiring 
 someone to do something that they thought was sinful as different from a 
 practice under which people end up hearing things from the government that 
 they might find offensive or alienating.

   Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Sunday, July 06, 2014 11:10 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: On a different strand of the seamless web


I think Chips and Doug's key points in their posts are worth emphasizing. 
Many briefs supporting the town of Greece and the Court's opinion in that case 
treated the religious liberty arguments of plaintiffs with complete distain. 
The authors of many of those briefs and the same justices who wrote the 
opinion upholding coercive and discriminatory prayer practices  in Town of 
Greece insisted that the religious liberty of Hobby Lobby must be protected.



As Chip suggests, a tradition, or support for a legal regime, of religious 
liberty for me but not for you cannot be fairly described as a commitment to 
religious liberty.



An incidental, but not insignificant, result of this kind one-sided support 
for religious liberty is the burden it places on those of us who try to defend 
and promote religious liberty and equality for people on both sides of the 
culture wars.



Alan


___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private. 
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people 
can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward 
the messages to others.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: On a different strand of the seamless web

2014-07-06 Thread Douglas Laycock
I think individual humans, who believe that they have souls, do not forfeit 
their right to religious liberty when they incorporate their business. I 
believe that exemptions are about letting them live their lives, and 
restricting or prohibiting government-sponsored prayer is about letting 
everyone else live theirs.

On Sun, 6 Jul 2014 13:47:49 -0700
 Paul Finkelman paul.finkel...@yahoo.com wrote:
unlike Doug, I do not believe corporations are people, that they have 
religious believes or that they have souls (that is of course an 
understatement); corporations are legal vehicles designed to make money for 
the investors and to shield the investors from having to use their own assets 
to cover losses and debts. 


I do not believe any faith thinks Hobby Lobby has an immortal soul, can go to 
heaven or hell, or that it prays.  So, I guess I am unpersuaded that there can 
be an exemption issue for a corporation




 From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: Paul Finkelman paul.finkel...@yahoo.com; Law  Religion issues for Law 
Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu; Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu 
Sent: Sunday, July 6, 2014 11:36 AM
Subject: Re: On a different strand of the seamless web
 

Unlike Paul, I think the exemption issues and the government-sponsored prayer 
issues are very different.

On Sun, 6 Jul 2014 01:36:45 -0700
Paul Finkelman paul.finkel...@yahoo.com wrote:
Doug's point here seems to encapsulate what is the problem for so many of us. 
 Those in the majority would make the rest of us burn incense, or listen to 
their prayers, or pay for their prayers or pray with them, or obey their 
views on sex and marriage and children, and we can go on and on.  And many in 
the majority forget that they were once persecuted, whether it was Christians 
killed in Rome or Baptists whipped in Virginia, and now that they have the 
power, they would impose it on us, whether it is health care if you are 
unfortunate enough to have to work for Hobby Lobby or prayers if you are 
unfortunate enough to need something form the government of the Town of 
Greece.

Paul Finkelman (writing from Granada, where the evidence and reminders of 
religious intolerance and persecution is everywhere)




 From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu; 
Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu 
Sent: Sunday, July 6, 2014 1:01 AM
Subject: On a different strand of the seamless web
 

On Sat, 5 Jul 2014 11:02:00 -0700
Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:


* * * *
Christians died rather than burn a pinch of incense to the emperor. 


Yes they did. A point they entirely forget as they impose brief Christian 
prayer services on their fellow citizens at public meetings, and insist that 
it's no big deal to go through of motions of praying to a God you don't 
believe in.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
     434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
forward the messages to others.




Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
     434-243-8546

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.