Re: Report on Draft Language of Indiana Fix

2015-04-01 Thread Ira Lupu
That is not an adequate fix.  What if an employer in Indianapolis, relying
on RFRA, refuses to provide spousal benefits for a same sex spouse?  What
if a vendor in Indianapolis refuses on religious grounds to serve a Muslim
or an atheist?

If the state legislature wants to assure everyone that the RFRA cannot be a
defense to a discrimination claim or charge, they have to carve out all
relevant anti-discrimination laws.  That is not difficult to do.  See this
story out of Georgia, where the same fight is taking place, this week:
http://politics.blog.ajc.com/2015/03/30/defusing-the-religious-liberty-fight-part-ii/


On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 11:38 AM, James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu wrote:

 From the Indianapolis Star, which says it has obtained the language that
 is being presented to the Governor today:

 ***

 The clarification would say that the new religious freedom law does not
 authorize a provider – including businesses or individuals -- to refuse to
 offer or provide its services, facilities, goods, or public accommodation
 to any member of the public based on sexual orientation or gender identity.



 The proposed language exempts churches or other nonprofit religious
 organizations -- including affiliated schools – from the definition of
 provider.



 http://www.indystar.com/story/news/politics/2015/04/01/indiana-rfra-deal-sets-limited-protections-for-lgbt/70766920/

 ***


 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.




-- 
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
Co-author (with Professor Robert Tuttle) of Secular Government, Religious
People ( Wm. B. Eerdmans Pub. Co., 2014))
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Report on Draft Language of Indiana Fix

2015-04-01 Thread Marty Lederman
Based on that account, the fix would not cover, e.g., employment
discrimination, even by for-profit employers.  And even in the context of
customers, it might allow employers to assert the right to discriminate not
on the basis of an individual's sexual orientation or gender identity,
but instead because the person married a person of the same sex.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 11:38 AM, James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu wrote:

 From the Indianapolis Star, which says it has obtained the language that
 is being presented to the Governor today:

 ***

 The clarification would say that the new religious freedom law does not
 authorize a provider – including businesses or individuals -- to refuse to
 offer or provide its services, facilities, goods, or public accommodation
 to any member of the public based on sexual orientation or gender identity.



 The proposed language exempts churches or other nonprofit religious
 organizations -- including affiliated schools – from the definition of
 provider.



 http://www.indystar.com/story/news/politics/2015/04/01/indiana-rfra-deal-sets-limited-protections-for-lgbt/70766920/

 ***


 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Report on Draft Language of Indiana Fix

2015-04-01 Thread James Oleske
From the Indianapolis Star, which says it has obtained the language that is
being presented to the Governor today:

***

The clarification would say that the new religious freedom law does not
authorize a provider – including businesses or individuals -- to refuse to
offer or provide its services, facilities, goods, or public accommodation
to any member of the public based on sexual orientation or gender identity.



The proposed language exempts churches or other nonprofit religious
organizations -- including affiliated schools – from the definition of
provider.


http://www.indystar.com/story/news/politics/2015/04/01/indiana-rfra-deal-sets-limited-protections-for-lgbt/70766920/

***
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Ira Lupu
I think the compelled speech issues, re: communicative work like
photography, are interesting and sometimes difficult. I address those in an
article I will post later this month.  All I want to say now is that
religious motivation is irrelevant to the compelled speech argument.  (See
W Va Bd of Educ v. Barnette.)

But Mark also say If [harm] depends on the message sent by the refusal,
then we have an interesting viewpoint discrimination issue.  If, in 1965,
Ollie's BBQ had put up a sign in the window that read Federal law says we
must serve all, so we will, but n-s are not sincerely welcome, then he
would have violated the Public Accommodations title of the Civil Rights Act
(he would not have provided full and equal enjoyment of his restaurant
without discrimination on the basis of race.)  Does Mark or anyone on
this list really think that presents a serious First Amendment problem?
Ollie can write letters to Congress, and to the newspapers, and put signs
on his lawn, all railing against the oppressive Civil Rights Act, but he
cannot communicate that directly to customers on his business premises. If
it were otherwise, the Act would be gutted entirely.  I think that no
Justice who has served in the last 50 years would take such a First A claim
seriously.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:53 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 I also think the florist and baker examples are weaker for the religious
 claimant, especially where the flowers and cakes are generic. But what if
 custom floral arrangements involve artistic choices by the florist? What if
 the cake is (as some are) a truly creative work of art? And do only
 high-end bakers get protection from violation of conscience? What if the
 florist or baker is asked to include particular words or other expressive
 content in the arrangement or the cake? (This from someone who argued
 against licensing requirements for sellers of flowers – protectionist
 provisions for florists who fear grocery stores’ selling of flowers – on
 the basis that flower arranging is a kind of art that the government has no
 right to license, other than for health purposes.) What if the custom
 florist decides to include a lot of black roses in the arrangements? Or
 just puts the flowers together without using any creativity (so that they
 look like flowers you would get through 1-800-Flowers)? Can the florist be
 required to enter into the contract to provide flowers and then be required
 to follow some sort of industry standard of artistry in arranging the
 flowers?



 In the photography example, if the photographer must photograph a ceremony
 that he or she believes wrong, may the photographer refuse to use the
 creative skills that would ordinarily be used? (E.g., posing the couple in
 a particular way, using filters to get a romantic look, telling them to
 kiss for the photograph, etc.) I suppose that goes with my view that
 wedding photography is creation of celebratory art, and the First Amendment
 compelled speech cases prohibit the government from requiring the
 photographer to create art.



 On the harm question, of course there is a matter of baseline. Do I harm
 you by not photographing your ceremony? Or do I benefit you by doing it? If
 that depends on the message sent by the refusal, then we have an
 interesting viewpoint discrimination issue.



 Mark



 Mark S. Scarberry

 Professor of Law

 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law









 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Levinson, Sanford V
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 3:18 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 I think Prof. Chen is substantially correct, but I believe, more than
 ever, that it's the kind of problem that can ( and should) be handled
 outside legal constraints. Why would I want to hire a wedding photographer
 who so clearly won't view the day as affirmatively special?  Ditto the
 band?  But I really can't work up much sympathy for the florist or baker.
 They should be treated under the general rubric of public accommodations
 and the Civil Rights Act of 1964. I'm sure there were florists and bakers
 who objected to mixes-race marriages and could cite the purported curse on
 Ham. It really doesn't (and shouldn't) matter.



 Sandy

 Sent from my iPhone


 On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:56 PM, K Chen tzn...@gmail.com wrote:

 As someone putting a wedding together, I can't explain the lack of
 sympathy for the wedding photographer as anything but thinking that their
 work is essentially interchangeable. It is not, unfortunately, and it is
 priced accordingly. Every single photographer of them seems to take their
 business very, very personally. More to the point, it is a personal,
 professional service which is by its nature selective compared to the harm
 done by impersonal corporations excluding goods and services when they
 otherwise 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Ira Lupu
If the compelled speech argument is constitutionally sufficient, permission
to post a disclaiming sign may solve the problem. (It would be like letting
a student say aloud I don't mean it after forcing her to recite the
Pledge of Allegiance.)

If the compelled speech argument is NOT constitutionally sufficient, I
think the photographers have no First A right to put up such a sign, though
of course the NM legislature could permissibly accommodate the religious
objection by permitting a vendor to post such a sign.  Away from the
business site (on line or physical), the photographer of course is free to
express her views on same sex marriage.



On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 7:37 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 I don’t have time right now to respond in a substantial way to Chip’s
 post. Let me just quote this language from the New Mexico Supreme Court’s
 decision in Elane Photography:



 “Businesses that choose to be public accommodations must comply with the
 NMHRA, although such businesses retain their First Amendment rights to
 express their religious or political beliefs. They may, for example, post a
 disclaimer on their website or in their studio advertising that they oppose
 same-sex marriage but that they comply with applicable antidiscrimination
 laws.”



 That’s not quite the same as saying that gay couples aren’t welcome, but
 it’s pretty close. Is the NM court right that the photographers have a 1st
 Am right to do so?



 On the question whether religious liberty claims have anything to do with
 the compelled speech issue, if we believe that the “hybrid rights” part of
 Smith means anything, it might apply in this kind of case so that the
 combination of the claims to constitutional protection might create some
 synergy.



 Mark



 Mark S. Scarberry

 Professor of Law

 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law



















 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Ira Lupu
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 4:22 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 I think the compelled speech issues, re: communicative work like
 photography, are interesting and sometimes difficult. I address those in an
 article I will post later this month.  All I want to say now is that
 religious motivation is irrelevant to the compelled speech argument.  (See
 W Va Bd of Educ v. Barnette.)



 But Mark also say If [harm] depends on the message sent by the refusal,
 then we have an interesting viewpoint discrimination issue.  If, in 1965,
 Ollie's BBQ had put up a sign in the window that read Federal law says we
 must serve all, so we will, but n-s are not sincerely welcome, then he
 would have violated the Public Accommodations title of the Civil Rights Act
 (he would not have provided full and equal enjoyment of his restaurant
 without discrimination on the basis of race.)  Does Mark or anyone on
 this list really think that presents a serious First Amendment problem?
 Ollie can write letters to Congress, and to the newspapers, and put signs
 on his lawn, all railing against the oppressive Civil Rights Act, but he
 cannot communicate that directly to customers on his business premises. If
 it were otherwise, the Act would be gutted entirely.  I think that no
 Justice who has served in the last 50 years would take such a First A claim
 seriously.



 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:53 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 I also think the florist and baker examples are weaker for the religious
 claimant, especially where the flowers and cakes are generic. But what if
 custom floral arrangements involve artistic choices by the florist? What if
 the cake is (as some are) a truly creative work of art? And do only
 high-end bakers get protection from violation of conscience? What if the
 florist or baker is asked to include particular words or other expressive
 content in the arrangement or the cake? (This from someone who argued
 against licensing requirements for sellers of flowers – protectionist
 provisions for florists who fear grocery stores’ selling of flowers – on
 the basis that flower arranging is a kind of art that the government has no
 right to license, other than for health purposes.) What if the custom
 florist decides to include a lot of black roses in the arrangements? Or
 just puts the flowers together without using any creativity (so that they
 look like flowers you would get through 1-800-Flowers)? Can the florist be
 required to enter into the contract to provide flowers and then be required
 to follow some sort of industry standard of artistry in arranging the
 flowers?



 In the photography example, if the photographer must photograph a ceremony
 that he or she believes wrong, may the photographer refuse to use the
 creative skills that would ordinarily be used? (E.g., posing the couple in
 a particular way, using 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Ira Lupu
No, I don't think that's OK.  But that's a real compelled speech problem,
where the student must first utter the Pledge.

The wedding vendors do not have to say anything approving about the
marriage, or affirm its validity in the eyes of the state or God.  They do
have to provide goods and services; in the photographer's case, the
services include making the wedding look authentic and beautiful, not ugly
or false.  So the compelled speech concern seems much weaker to me than in
Barnette.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 8:53 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 Apart from the other points with which I disagree:



 Wow, Chip. You really think it’s OK to make the student recite the Pledge,
 as long as the student is permitted at the end to say “I don’t mean it”?
 Can I be required to burn a pinch of incense to the emperor as long as I am
 permitted afterwards to say that the emperor isn’t really a god?



 Mark



 Mark S. Scarberry

 Professor of Law

 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law







 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Ira Lupu
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 5:32 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 If the compelled speech argument is constitutionally sufficient,
 permission to post a disclaiming sign may solve the problem. (It would be
 like letting a student say aloud I don't mean it after forcing her to
 recite the Pledge of Allegiance.)



 If the compelled speech argument is NOT constitutionally sufficient, I
 think the photographers have no First A right to put up such a sign, though
 of course the NM legislature could permissibly accommodate the religious
 objection by permitting a vendor to post such a sign.  Away from the
 business site (on line or physical), the photographer of course is free to
 express her views on same sex marriage.







 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 7:37 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 I don’t have time right now to respond in a substantial way to Chip’s
 post. Let me just quote this language from the New Mexico Supreme Court’s
 decision in Elane Photography:



 “Businesses that choose to be public accommodations must comply with the
 NMHRA, although such businesses retain their First Amendment rights to
 express their religious or political beliefs. They may, for example, post a
 disclaimer on their website or in their studio advertising that they oppose
 same-sex marriage but that they comply with applicable antidiscrimination
 laws.”



 That’s not quite the same as saying that gay couples aren’t welcome, but
 it’s pretty close. Is the NM court right that the photographers have a 1st
 Am right to do so?



 On the question whether religious liberty claims have anything to do with
 the compelled speech issue, if we believe that the “hybrid rights” part of
 Smith means anything, it might apply in this kind of case so that the
 combination of the claims to constitutional protection might create some
 synergy.



 Mark



 Mark S. Scarberry

 Professor of Law

 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law



















 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Ira Lupu
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 4:22 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 I think the compelled speech issues, re: communicative work like
 photography, are interesting and sometimes difficult. I address those in an
 article I will post later this month.  All I want to say now is that
 religious motivation is irrelevant to the compelled speech argument.  (See
 W Va Bd of Educ v. Barnette.)



 But Mark also say If [harm] depends on the message sent by the refusal,
 then we have an interesting viewpoint discrimination issue.  If, in 1965,
 Ollie's BBQ had put up a sign in the window that read Federal law says we
 must serve all, so we will, but n-s are not sincerely welcome, then he
 would have violated the Public Accommodations title of the Civil Rights Act
 (he would not have provided full and equal enjoyment of his restaurant
 without discrimination on the basis of race.)  Does Mark or anyone on
 this list really think that presents a serious First Amendment problem?
 Ollie can write letters to Congress, and to the newspapers, and put signs
 on his lawn, all railing against the oppressive Civil Rights Act, but he
 cannot communicate that directly to customers on his business premises. If
 it were otherwise, the Act would be gutted entirely.  I think that no
 Justice who has served in the last 50 years would take such a First A claim
 seriously.



 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:53 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 I also think the florist and baker examples are weaker for the religious
 claimant, especially where the flowers and cakes are 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Nelson Tebbe


Thanks, Alan. Speaking again only for myself, I am open to some balancing, not 
only as to this particular principle (against burden shifting to third parties) 
but also as a general methodology, as you know. But the conversation is not yet 
at that point. Right now, the main debate is over whether the principle even 
exists in constitutional law, and what its most basic applications might be, 
not over its contours. As a matter of doctrine, the Hobby Lobby Court 
reaffirmed the principle against burden-shifting in religion accommodations, 
and Justice Kennedy made it central to his vote, but there is some troubling 
language in the opinion (see, e.g., footnote 37 and the sharp division between 
RFRA and pre-Smith cases). As a matter of application, the Hobby Lobby Court 
did not make its ruling contingent on the absence of harm to third parties. And 
in fact employees of Hobby Lobby continue to be harmed right now. And as a 
matter of theory, finally, prominent scholars continue to deny that the 
principle exists and has legal status, under either free exercise or 
nonestablishment, despite the fact that the case law in both areas is lopsided 
in favor of the principle. But again my basic answer is yes, I am open to that 
approach.

On Apr 1, 2015, at 5:46 PM, Alan E Brownstein 
aebrownst...@ucdavis.edumailto:aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu wrote:


I appreciate your point, Nelson. And I think the principle that private 
citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with other citizens’ 
religious observance deserves respect. Standing alone, it would often be 
dispositive.  Where we disagree, I think, is that in religious exemption cases 
I see two principles here that deserve our respect. The one I just quoted above 
and the principle that the majority and government should not prohibit or 
burden another citizen's religious observance. I think, you can tell me if I'm 
wrong, that you would agree that this principle standing alone also deserves 
respect. If there is no harm to third parties, you would support religious 
exemptions.

Then the question becomes what do we do when these two principles are in 
conflict with each other. I don't think either trumps the other all of the 
time. I think as the harm to third parties increases, the principle that 
citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with the other citizen's 
religious observance outweighs the religious liberty principle. I understand 
you to be saying that the religious liberty principle is always trumped in 
these cases without regard to the magnitude of the costs involved.

There are a lot of religious accommodations that result in third parties 
incurring some cost.  A RLUIPA land use accommodation might result in some 
neighboring homeowner, business or farmer incurring some diminution of value in 
their property. A public university accommodation shifting move-in day so that 
it doesn't fall on the Jewish High Holy days may require a shift in the 
academic calendar that inconveniences the travel plans of specific faculty, 
students and their families. A court accommodating the religious obligations of 
a religious attorney or witness may delay or otherwise increase the cost of 
litigation. A law banning male circumcision exempts Jewish families from its 
requirements. Does the existence of harm to third parties in these situations 
and others require the invalidation of all of these accommodations without 
regard to the magnitude of the harm borne by third parties?

Alan



From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
on behalf of Nelson Tebbe 
nelson.te...@brooklaw.edumailto:nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu
Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 1:38 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



Alan, I can’t speak for others who have been defending a principle against 
burden-shifting to third parties, but I do not believe it prohibits religion 
accommodations that result in costs to the government or to the public. Rather, 
the principle prohibits government accommodations that shift meaningful costs 
from religious citizens to other identifiable private citizens. And the reason 
for this is easy to articulate and deeply rooted — private citizens should not 
have to bear the costs associated with other citizens’ religious observance.

On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:07 PM, Alan E Brownstein 
aebrownst...@ucdavis.edumailto:aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu wrote:

The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him correctly, is that 
it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be accepted if it causes 
any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim includes the general public or 
the public fisc in third party.) I think many liberals believe (or at least 
they used to believe) that rights are expensive political goods. We 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
You may be right. I was using the term more metaphorically to refer to any 
business that is open to the public.

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Apr 1, 2015, at 6:48 PM, Richard Friedman 
rdfrd...@umich.edumailto:rdfrd...@umich.edu wrote:

Hi, Sandy.  I hope all is well.  I'm writing to you off-list, because I haven't 
followed the entire conversation and may have missed something.  But my 
understanding is that florists and cake-makers (assuming the cakes are not 
meant to be eaten on premises) are not public accommodations within the meaning 
of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, though they're covered by many state civil 
rights acts.  Am I in fact missing something?

Best,

Rich

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:18 PM, Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edumailto:slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
I think Prof. Chen is substantially correct, but I believe, more than ever, 
that it's the kind of problem that can ( and should) be handled outside legal 
constraints. Why would I want to hire a wedding photographer who so clearly 
won't view the day as affirmatively special?  Ditto the band?  But I really 
can't work up much sympathy for the florist or baker. They should be treated 
under the general rubric of public accommodations and the Civil Rights Act of 
1964. I'm sure there were florists and bakers who objected to mixes-race 
marriages and could cite the purported curse on Ham. It really doesn't (and 
shouldn't) matter.

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:56 PM, K Chen tzn...@gmail.commailto:tzn...@gmail.com 
wrote:

As someone putting a wedding together, I can't explain the lack of sympathy for 
the wedding photographer as anything but thinking that their work is 
essentially interchangeable. It is not, unfortunately, and it is priced 
accordingly. Every single photographer of them seems to take their business 
very, very personally. More to the point, it is a personal, professional 
service which is by its nature selective compared to the harm done by 
impersonal corporations excluding goods and services when they otherwise serve 
the public.

A principled difference can be drawn between accommodating personal, inherently 
selective commercial businesses and businesses that are open to the public at 
large. The vast majority of commercial transactions are from businesses who 
sell to the public, or their business community, on a non-discriminatory basis. 
When such a business denies goods or services to a class of person, that is an 
inherently political act. Such a businesses is not just refusing the do 
business with an individual or class, they are making an attempt to exclude 
them from the definition of the public itself. They are thus doing harm to both 
individual and society by imposing their will on what constitutes the political 
community. This harm grows geometrically with each exclusionary actor.

Individual consumers on the other hand, are inherently selective. If you need 
one loaf of bread this week, you will patronize precisely one baker this week. 
If you need a salary, you will work one, maybe two jobs. The harm of being 
denied service by a consumer (or laborer) because of their beliefs has a 
societal harm, if any, nearly indistinguishable to being denied for any other 
reason.

Some services should fall in between. I'm not convinced for the florist and the 
and the baker, but I'm sympathetic to the photographer, the doctor, the lawyer 
(ethical obligations notwithstanding) , the political consultant, the ghost 
writer...

I don't know how far that gets liberals of course, but it is a difference 
beyond mere size and corporate form.

Kevin Chen

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek 
dgaub...@imb.orgmailto:dgaub...@imb.org wrote:
“[l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including 
liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to 
support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of 
such exemptions to commercial businesses.

I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many individuals 
depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do liberals see the 
conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy of protection, but the 
conscience of an individual photographer, florist, baker, or bed and breakfast 
owner less worthy of protection?Justice Kagan, at least back in 1996 when 
she was in the Clinton White House, appeared to recognize that the consciences 
of individuals operating small commercial businesses was worthy of protection 
under a RFRA regime.   Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a 
Evelyn Smith who, for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units 
to a co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was 
“outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold that a 
state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because the 
complainant is free to move to another 

RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
   Sandy:  I appreciate your point, but should it be relevant that 
Title II of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 actually covered a comparatively 
narrow set of places of public accommodation, and (as best I can tell) didn't 
apply to retail establishments or service providers such as florists or bakers? 
 Many state laws are broader, to be sure, but if the appeal is to the seminal 
nature of the federal Civil Rights Act, I'm not sure how far that appeal would 
take us as to these sorts of businesses.

   Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Levinson, Sanford V
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 3:18 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

I think Prof. Chen is substantially correct, but I believe, more than ever, 
that it's the kind of problem that can ( and should) be handled outside legal 
constraints. Why would I want to hire a wedding photographer who so clearly 
won't view the day as affirmatively special?  Ditto the band?  But I really 
can't work up much sympathy for the florist or baker. They should be treated 
under the general rubric of public accommodations and the Civil Rights Act of 
1964. I'm sure there were florists and bakers who objected to mixes-race 
marriages and could cite the purported curse on Ham. It really doesn't (and 
shouldn't) matter.

Sandy

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: So much for Arkansas RFRA?

2015-04-01 Thread James Oleske
The Arkansas Senate passed a new bill tonight, and the House is expected to
take it up tomorrow. The text is here:
http://www.arkleg.state.ar.us/assembly/2015/2015R/Amendments/sb975-S1.pdf

My guess is that the new version of the Arkansas RFRA bill -- which is
intended to more closely mirror the federal RFRA than the earlier version
of the Arkansas RFRA bill -- will not satisfy most opponents of the earlier
bill. A principal source of concern about adopting new state RFRAs today is
the Hobby Lobby interpretation of the federal RFRA extending exemption
rights to commercial businesses, so mirroring the federal RFRA doesn't do
much for the opponents. The question is whether it does enough for Gov.
Hutchinson to avoid the Indiana firestorm moving to Arkansas if Indiana
adds a civil rights carve-out and Arkansas does not ...

- Jim

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 10:53 AM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com
wrote:


 http://www.nytimes.com/2015/04/02/us/arkansas-indiana-religious-freedom-hutchinson-pence.html



 On Tue, Mar 31, 2015 at 9:39 PM, Friedman, Howard M. 
 howard.fried...@utoledo.edu wrote:

  The Arkansas legislature today passed a state RFRA. While national
 media is reporting that the bill is similar to Indiana's, in fact it is
 broader in several ways. See
 http://religionclause.blogspot.com/2015/03/arkansas-legislature-passes-rfra-law.html

 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.



 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
Although it may be awkward to put it this way, my point was not that of the 
careful lawyer (though I think I can be one when need be :) ), but, rather, 
appealing to the aspirations underlying the Act. If we were debating the 
meaning of the 14th Amendment, most (though not all) of us would pay almost no 
attention to the specific views of the Framers, beginning, of course, with 
their carefully delineated differentiation of civil, political, and social 
rights or the assumptions about the continuing validity of segregation, etc. 
Constitutive statutes like the Civil Rights Act take on a similar life if 
their own in shaping consciousness, even if there may be a specific exemption 
for Mrs. Murphy and her boardinghouse. There is a reason that state civil 
rights statutes are broader. The limitations of 1964 were raw compromises to 
pick up votes. They scarcely rested on deep principles that were generally 
accepted.

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Apr 1, 2015, at 8:47 PM, Richard Friedman 
rdfrd...@umich.edumailto:rdfrd...@umich.edu wrote:

But given the way you wrote your post, I don't think you really can, because 
the decision was pretty deliberate to limit the 1964 Act to a carefully defined 
list of public accommodations that didn't involve intimate contact -- so no 
boarding houses, no barbershops, not even most types of retail stores.  
Somebody (can't remember who) wrote ap iece several years ago emphasizing this. 
 I don't know how universally state laws have filled the gap -- they certainly 
have to some extent, though I imagine not with respect to boarding houses -- 
and I suppose there's a national consensus that a barber can't decline to cut a 
person's hair on account of race, but I don't think you can cite the '64 Act in 
support of it.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 8:58 PM, Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edumailto:slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
You may be right. I was using the term more metaphorically to refer to any 
business that is open to the public.

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Apr 1, 2015, at 6:48 PM, Richard Friedman 
rdfrd...@umich.edumailto:rdfrd...@umich.edu wrote:

Hi, Sandy.  I hope all is well.  I'm writing to you off-list, because I haven't 
followed the entire conversation and may have missed something.  But my 
understanding is that florists and cake-makers (assuming the cakes are not 
meant to be eaten on premises) are not public accommodations within the meaning 
of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, though they're covered by many state civil 
rights acts.  Am I in fact missing something?

Best,

Rich

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:18 PM, Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edumailto:slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
I think Prof. Chen is substantially correct, but I believe, more than ever, 
that it's the kind of problem that can ( and should) be handled outside legal 
constraints. Why would I want to hire a wedding photographer who so clearly 
won't view the day as affirmatively special?  Ditto the band?  But I really 
can't work up much sympathy for the florist or baker. They should be treated 
under the general rubric of public accommodations and the Civil Rights Act of 
1964. I'm sure there were florists and bakers who objected to mixes-race 
marriages and could cite the purported curse on Ham. It really doesn't (and 
shouldn't) matter.

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:56 PM, K Chen tzn...@gmail.commailto:tzn...@gmail.com 
wrote:

As someone putting a wedding together, I can't explain the lack of sympathy for 
the wedding photographer as anything but thinking that their work is 
essentially interchangeable. It is not, unfortunately, and it is priced 
accordingly. Every single photographer of them seems to take their business 
very, very personally. More to the point, it is a personal, professional 
service which is by its nature selective compared to the harm done by 
impersonal corporations excluding goods and services when they otherwise serve 
the public.

A principled difference can be drawn between accommodating personal, inherently 
selective commercial businesses and businesses that are open to the public at 
large. The vast majority of commercial transactions are from businesses who 
sell to the public, or their business community, on a non-discriminatory basis. 
When such a business denies goods or services to a class of person, that is an 
inherently political act. Such a businesses is not just refusing the do 
business with an individual or class, they are making an attempt to exclude 
them from the definition of the public itself. They are thus doing harm to both 
individual and society by imposing their will on what constitutes the political 
community. This harm grows geometrically with each exclusionary actor.

Individual consumers on the other hand, are inherently selective. If you need 
one loaf of bread this week, you will patronize precisely one baker this week. 
If you need a salary, you will work one, maybe two jobs. The 

RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Scarberry, Mark
I don’t have time right now to respond in a substantial way to Chip’s post. Let 
me just quote this language from the New Mexico Supreme Court’s decision in 
Elane Photography:

“Businesses that choose to be public accommodations must comply with the NMHRA, 
although such businesses retain their First Amendment rights to express their 
religious or political beliefs. They may, for example, post a disclaimer on 
their website or in their studio advertising that they oppose same-sex marriage 
but that they comply with applicable antidiscrimination laws.”

That’s not quite the same as saying that gay couples aren’t welcome, but it’s 
pretty close. Is the NM court right that the photographers have a 1st Am right 
to do so?

On the question whether religious liberty claims have anything to do with the 
compelled speech issue, if we believe that the “hybrid rights” part of Smith 
means anything, it might apply in this kind of case so that the combination of 
the claims to constitutional protection might create some synergy.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law









From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 4:22 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

I think the compelled speech issues, re: communicative work like photography, 
are interesting and sometimes difficult. I address those in an article I will 
post later this month.  All I want to say now is that religious motivation is 
irrelevant to the compelled speech argument.  (See W Va Bd of Educ v. Barnette.)

But Mark also say If [harm] depends on the message sent by the refusal, then 
we have an interesting viewpoint discrimination issue.  If, in 1965, Ollie's 
BBQ had put up a sign in the window that read Federal law says we must serve 
all, so we will, but n-s are not sincerely welcome, then he would have 
violated the Public Accommodations title of the Civil Rights Act (he would not 
have provided full and equal enjoyment of his restaurant without 
discrimination on the basis of race.)  Does Mark or anyone on this list really 
think that presents a serious First Amendment problem?  Ollie can write letters 
to Congress, and to the newspapers, and put signs on his lawn, all railing 
against the oppressive Civil Rights Act, but he cannot communicate that 
directly to customers on his business premises. If it were otherwise, the Act 
would be gutted entirely.  I think that no Justice who has served in the last 
50 years would take such a First A claim seriously.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:53 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
I also think the florist and baker examples are weaker for the religious 
claimant, especially where the flowers and cakes are generic. But what if 
custom floral arrangements involve artistic choices by the florist? What if the 
cake is (as some are) a truly creative work of art? And do only high-end bakers 
get protection from violation of conscience? What if the florist or baker is 
asked to include particular words or other expressive content in the 
arrangement or the cake? (This from someone who argued against licensing 
requirements for sellers of flowers – protectionist provisions for florists who 
fear grocery stores’ selling of flowers – on the basis that flower arranging is 
a kind of art that the government has no right to license, other than for 
health purposes.) What if the custom florist decides to include a lot of black 
roses in the arrangements? Or just puts the flowers together without using any 
creativity (so that they look like flowers you would get through 
1-800-Flowers)? Can the florist be required to enter into the contract to 
provide flowers and then be required to follow some sort of industry standard 
of artistry in arranging the flowers?

In the photography example, if the photographer must photograph a ceremony that 
he or she believes wrong, may the photographer refuse to use the creative 
skills that would ordinarily be used? (E.g., posing the couple in a particular 
way, using filters to get a romantic look, telling them to kiss for the 
photograph, etc.) I suppose that goes with my view that wedding photography is 
creation of celebratory art, and the First Amendment compelled speech cases 
prohibit the government from requiring the photographer to create art.

On the harm question, of course there is a matter of baseline. Do I harm you by 
not photographing your ceremony? Or do I benefit you by doing it? If that 
depends on the message sent by the refusal, then we have an interesting 
viewpoint discrimination issue.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Will Esser
Chip,
Thanks for the explanation, which is helpful.  But I want to push a little 
farther on this concept of dignitary injury.
You state that the dignitary injury is more serious because it has wounded 
the couple with this disrespect.  But how far can that argument really go?  
Are you saying that public non-discrimination laws not only require the 
provisions of goods and services to all comers, but also require that those 
services be provided in a way that will be viewed as respectful of the 
particular beliefs of the customers?  
If that is the case, does the photographer who has the Piss Christ photograph 
by Andres Serrano hanging on the wall of their shop (i.e. a photograph which 
very clearly singles out Christians for disrespect and dignitary injury) also 
run afoul of public non-discrimination laws even if the photographer is 
otherwise willing to perform photography services for Christians?  Or use the 
same example but substitute in the cover of the Charlie Hebdo magazine 
depicting the Prophet Muhammad?  
Mark pointed it out in several of his later posts, but I'm troubled about how 
this concept of dignitary injury logically plays out and whether your 
argument essentially means that anyone involved in businesses which provide 
public services are required to check their free speech and opinions at the 
door.  There are, after all, many categories of things that a business owner 
could say which would be gravely disrespectful and injure the dignity of 
customers (e.g. My are you fat.  You are so ugly I can't stand to look at 
you etc.).  The marketplace (particularly in this age of social media) would 
quickly penalize such disrespect in an economic manner, but I had never viewed 
it as within the purview of non-discrimination laws to protect citizens from 
speech that they found disrespectful.  
I welcome your thoughts.  
Will

Will Esser 
Charlotte, North Carolina
   From: Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu
 To: Will Esser willes...@yahoo.com; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu 
 Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 6:35 PM
 Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights
   
Thanks for the question, Will. If the kosher butcher gets that exemption, he 
will sell pork to no one.  He never has and never will carry pork in his shop.  
He also does not sell soda, cars, or wedding cakes.  If you want that stuff, 
you must go elsewhere.  Is that a cost to third parties?''  No more than that 
imposed by any (that is, every) other merchant who sells less than everything.
Compare that to a discriminatory refusal to sell.  Baker A does sell wedding 
cakes, but not to same sex couples.  Two injuries -- material and dignitary.  
The material injury is the lost opportunity to buy a cake at the quality and 
price offered by that baker.  Maybe you can do as well or better elsewhere, 
nearby, or maybe not.  The dignitary injury is more serious -- the couple is 
seeking goods to celebrate one of the most important and special days of their 
lives. And the baker says, in effect, I do not respect your marriage as a 
marriage.  In my belief system, it is not a marriage at all, because you are of 
the same sex. (The baker might also think or say that in his view the 
relationship is disordered, or an abomination, and/or against God's plan, but 
let's assume he says nothing like that all.)  The baker has wounded the couple 
with this disrespect, and done so in regard to a day that has significant 
meaning in their lives.
Those are the focused, third party harms in the refusal to sell goods or 
services to some that you sell to others, especially (though not only) for a 
wedding reception.
On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 4:38 PM, Will Esser willes...@yahoo.com wrote:



Chip,
Can you expound on your argument that wedding vendor exemptions from public 
accommodations laws allow material and dignitary injury to potential 
customers and that liberals only oppose exemptions that impinge on the 
welfare of third parties?  It seems that both sides agree that the kosher 
butcher deserves a religious exemption, and yet granting that exemption imposes 
some cost on third parties (i.e. anyone who wishes to purchase pork must go 
elsewhere, which could involve multiple trips to different butchers, or may 
mean spending more time and money to go to a butcher further away).  So it's 
not really that there is no cost to third parties, but perhaps simply a cost 
which society is more ready to accept (i.e. Go buy your pork somewhere else.)
As I understood the third-party harm argument in Hobby Lobby, the argument 
was that without insurance coverage, female Hobby Lobby employees would be 
unable to afford coverage of the particular, objectionable contraceptives and 
therefore the third party harm was equivalent to total lack of access.  

Given modern changes in societal perspectives, I have not heard the same 
argument about a total lack of access when it comes to wedding vendors for 
same-sex 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Marty Lederman
Sandy:  the florist who refuses to sell a bouquet for use at a same-sex
marriage, who is necessarily condoning the presumptively sinful conduct?

I assume you meant to say that the florist would necessarily condone the
presumptively sinful conduct if she *did* sell the bouquet to the same-sex
couple.  If so -- really?!  I would think that such a sale would *not*
reasonably
be viewed as condoning the same-sex marriage even in the absence of an
antidiscrimination law requirement . . . and certainly not if it were done
solely in order to comply with such a law.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 5:17 PM, Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:

  Non-Jews are under no obligation not to eat pork (or adhere to almost
 all of the other 612 mitzvot). So there is no stigma attached to any
 non-Jew who wants to buy a ham at a kosher butchery. That can't be said
 with regard to the florist who refuses to sell a bouquet for use at a
 same-sex marriage, who is necessarily condoning the presumptively sinful
 conduct. Ironically or not, the only person a Jewish butcher might be upset
 with is another Jew. This underscores the fact that very few Jewish laws
 are universal.  This is not true of most purported Christian precepts
 (beginning with the widely shared view among many a Evangelicals that I'm
 damned for failure to accept the teaching of John 3:16 (which I know by
 heart having memorized it some 65 years ago in order to earn a Bible
 certificate from the state of North Carolina).

  Sandy

 Sent from my iPhone

 On Apr 1, 2015, at 3:44 PM, Will Esser willes...@yahoo.com wrote:

   Chip,

  Can you expound on your argument that wedding vendor exemptions from
 public accommodations laws allow material and dignitary injury to
 potential customers and that liberals only oppose exemptions that impinge
 on the welfare of third parties?  It seems that both sides agree that the
 kosher butcher deserves a religious exemption, and yet granting that
 exemption imposes *some* cost on third parties (i.e. anyone who wishes to
 purchase pork must go elsewhere, which could involve multiple trips to
 different butchers, or may mean spending more time and money to go to a
 butcher further away).  So it's not really that there is * no* cost to
 third parties, but perhaps simply a cost which society is more ready to
 accept (i.e. Go buy your pork somewhere else.)

  As I understood the third-party harm argument in Hobby Lobby, the
 argument was that without insurance coverage, female Hobby Lobby employees
 would be unable to afford coverage of the particular, objectionable
 contraceptives and therefore the third party harm was equivalent to total
 lack of access.

  Given modern changes in societal perspectives, I have not heard the same
 argument about a total lack of access when it comes to wedding vendors for
 same-sex wedding ceremonies.  Under the assumption the goods and services
 are otherwise generally available in the marketplace (i.e. there are plenty
 of wedding photographers, bakers, etc. who would be happy for the business
 of same-sex weddings), what is the distinguishing factor which causes
 material and dignitary injury in the wedding vendor exemptions scenario
 but not in the kosher butcher example?  In both, the customers want a
 service which they can get in the marketplace (although perhaps not from
 the exact person or place they want it).  And in both, the reason for not
 providing the service is the same (i.e. violation of a sincerely held
 religious belief).

  Thanks in advance for clarification.

  Will

  Will Esser
 Charlotte, North Carolina


   --
 *From:* James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 1, 2015 3:22 PM
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

   The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the
 Court might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but
 rather, a strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm
 that can be overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the
 presumption (a third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead
 simply discarded the Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further
 than the pre-Smith law.

  - Jim




  On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

  I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se --
 imagine a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with
 religious dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.
 Liberals oppose exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties --
 Hobby Lobby (those female employees still do not have contraceptive
 coverage) or wedding vendor exemptions from public accommodations laws
 (those exemptions allow material and dignitary injury to potential
 customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other family members of Amish
 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
State law definitions of public accommodations are far broader than the federal 
definition (basically hotels and restaurants) and often do include pretty much 
any business open to the public.

On Thu, 2 Apr 2015 00:58:02 +
 Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
You may be right. I was using the term more metaphorically to refer to any 
business that is open to the public.

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Apr 1, 2015, at 6:48 PM, Richard Friedman 
rdfrd...@umich.edumailto:rdfrd...@umich.edu wrote:

Hi, Sandy.  I hope all is well.  I'm writing to you off-list, because I 
haven't followed the entire conversation and may have missed something.  But 
my understanding is that florists and cake-makers (assuming the cakes are not 
meant to be eaten on premises) are not public accommodations within the 
meaning of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, though they're covered by many state 
civil rights acts.  Am I in fact missing something?

Best,

Rich

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:18 PM, Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edumailto:slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
I think Prof. Chen is substantially correct, but I believe, more than ever, 
that it's the kind of problem that can ( and should) be handled outside legal 
constraints. Why would I want to hire a wedding photographer who so clearly 
won't view the day as affirmatively special?  Ditto the band?  But I really 
can't work up much sympathy for the florist or baker. They should be treated 
under the general rubric of public accommodations and the Civil Rights Act of 
1964. I'm sure there were florists and bakers who objected to mixes-race 
marriages and could cite the purported curse on Ham. It really doesn't (and 
shouldn't) matter.

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:56 PM, K Chen tzn...@gmail.commailto:tzn...@gmail.com 
wrote:

As someone putting a wedding together, I can't explain the lack of sympathy 
for the wedding photographer as anything but thinking that their work is 
essentially interchangeable. It is not, unfortunately, and it is priced 
accordingly. Every single photographer of them seems to take their business 
very, very personally. More to the point, it is a personal, professional 
service which is by its nature selective compared to the harm done by 
impersonal corporations excluding goods and services when they otherwise serve 
the public.

A principled difference can be drawn between accommodating personal, 
inherently selective commercial businesses and businesses that are open to the 
public at large. The vast majority of commercial transactions are from 
businesses who sell to the public, or their business community, on a 
non-discriminatory basis. When such a business denies goods or services to a 
class of person, that is an inherently political act. Such a businesses is not 
just refusing the do business with an individual or class, they are making an 
attempt to exclude them from the definition of the public itself. They are 
thus doing harm to both individual and society by imposing their will on what 
constitutes the political community. This harm grows geometrically with each 
exclusionary actor.

Individual consumers on the other hand, are inherently selective. If you need 
one loaf of bread this week, you will patronize precisely one baker this week. 
If you need a salary, you will work one, maybe two jobs. The harm of being 
denied service by a consumer (or laborer) because of their beliefs has a 
societal harm, if any, nearly indistinguishable to being denied for any other 
reason.

Some services should fall in between. I'm not convinced for the florist and 
the and the baker, but I'm sympathetic to the photographer, the doctor, the 
lawyer (ethical obligations notwithstanding) , the political consultant, the 
ghost writer...

I don't know how far that gets liberals of course, but it is a difference 
beyond mere size and corporate form.

Kevin Chen

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek 
dgaub...@imb.orgmailto:dgaub...@imb.org wrote:
“[l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including 
liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to 
support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of 
such exemptions to commercial businesses.

I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many individuals 
depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do liberals see 
the conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy of protection, 
but the conscience of an individual photographer, florist, baker, or bed and 
breakfast owner less worthy of protection?Justice Kagan, at least back in 
1996 when she was in the Clinton White House, appeared to recognize that the 
consciences of individuals operating small commercial businesses was worthy of 
protection under a RFRA regime.   Commenting on the short shrift given to the 
claim of a Evelyn Smith who, for religious reasons, did not want to rent 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Richard Friedman
Well, I thought I was doing this off list and wasn't.  Sorry about that!
(Could have been worse.)

Rich

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 9:43 PM, Richard Friedman rdfrd...@umich.edu wrote:

 But given the way you wrote your post, I don't think you really can,
 because the decision was pretty deliberate to limit the 1964 Act to a
 carefully defined list of public accommodations that didn't involve
 intimate contact -- so no boarding houses, no barbershops, not even most
 types of retail stores.  Somebody (can't remember who) wrote ap iece
 several years ago emphasizing this.  I don't know how universally state
 laws have filled the gap -- they certainly have to some extent, though I
 imagine not with respect to boarding houses -- and I suppose there's a
 national consensus that a barber can't decline to cut a person's hair on
 account of race, but I don't think you can cite the '64 Act in support of
 it.

 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 8:58 PM, Levinson, Sanford V 
 slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:

  You may be right. I was using the term more metaphorically to refer to
 any business that is open to the public.

  Sandy

 Sent from my iPhone

 On Apr 1, 2015, at 6:48 PM, Richard Friedman rdfrd...@umich.edu wrote:

Hi, Sandy.  I hope all is well.  I'm writing to you off-list, because
 I haven't followed the entire conversation and may have missed something.
 But my understanding is that florists and cake-makers (assuming the cakes
 are not meant to be eaten on premises) are not public accommodations within
 the meaning of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, though they're covered by many
 state civil rights acts.  Am I in fact missing something?

  Best,

  Rich

 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:18 PM, Levinson, Sanford V 
 slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:

  I think Prof. Chen is substantially correct, but I believe, more than
 ever, that it's the kind of problem that can ( and should) be handled
 outside legal constraints. Why would I want to hire a wedding photographer
 who so clearly won't view the day as affirmatively special?  Ditto the
 band?  But I really can't work up much sympathy for the florist or baker.
 They should be treated under the general rubric of public accommodations
 and the Civil Rights Act of 1964. I'm sure there were florists and bakers
 who objected to mixes-race marriages and could cite the purported curse on
 Ham. It really doesn't (and shouldn't) matter.

  Sandy

 Sent from my iPhone

 On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:56 PM, K Chen tzn...@gmail.com wrote:

   As someone putting a wedding together, I can't explain the lack of
 sympathy for the wedding photographer as anything but thinking that their
 work is essentially interchangeable. It is not, unfortunately, and it is
 priced accordingly. Every single photographer of them seems to take their
 business very, very personally. More to the point, it is a personal,
 professional service which is by its nature selective compared to the harm
 done by impersonal corporations excluding goods and services when they
 otherwise serve the public.

  A principled difference can be drawn between accommodating personal,
 inherently selective commercial businesses and businesses that are open to
 the public at large. The vast majority of commercial transactions are from
 businesses who sell to the public, or their business community, on a
 non-discriminatory basis. When such a business denies goods or services to
 a class of person, that is an inherently political act. Such a businesses
 is not just refusing the do business with an individual or class, they are
 making an attempt to exclude them from *the definition of the public
 itself. * They are thus doing harm to both individual and society by
 imposing their will on what constitutes the political community. This harm
 grows geometrically with each exclusionary actor.

  Individual consumers on the other hand, are inherently selective. If
 you need one loaf of bread this week, you will patronize precisely one
 baker this week. If you need a salary, you will work one, maybe two jobs.
 The harm of being denied service by a consumer (or laborer) because of
 their beliefs has a societal harm, if any, nearly indistinguishable to
 being denied for any other reason.

  Some services should fall in between. I'm not convinced for the
 florist and the and the baker, but I'm sympathetic to the photographer, the
 doctor, the lawyer (ethical obligations notwithstanding) , the political
 consultant, the ghost writer...

  I don't know how far that gets liberals of course, but it *is* a
 difference beyond mere size and corporate form.

  Kevin Chen

 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org wrote:

  “[l]iberals who opposed *Smith* in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 —
 including liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely
 continue to support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing
 the extension of such exemptions to commercial businesses.



 I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled 

RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Scarberry, Mark
Apart from the other points with which I disagree:

Wow, Chip. You really think it’s OK to make the student recite the Pledge, as 
long as the student is permitted at the end to say “I don’t mean it”? Can I be 
required to burn a pinch of incense to the emperor as long as I am permitted 
afterwards to say that the emperor isn’t really a god?

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 5:32 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

If the compelled speech argument is constitutionally sufficient, permission to 
post a disclaiming sign may solve the problem. (It would be like letting a 
student say aloud I don't mean it after forcing her to recite the Pledge of 
Allegiance.)

If the compelled speech argument is NOT constitutionally sufficient, I think 
the photographers have no First A right to put up such a sign, though of course 
the NM legislature could permissibly accommodate the religious objection by 
permitting a vendor to post such a sign.  Away from the business site (on line 
or physical), the photographer of course is free to express her views on same 
sex marriage.



On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 7:37 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
I don’t have time right now to respond in a substantial way to Chip’s post. Let 
me just quote this language from the New Mexico Supreme Court’s decision in 
Elane Photography:

“Businesses that choose to be public accommodations must comply with the NMHRA, 
although such businesses retain their First Amendment rights to express their 
religious or political beliefs. They may, for example, post a disclaimer on 
their website or in their studio advertising that they oppose same-sex marriage 
but that they comply with applicable antidiscrimination laws.”

That’s not quite the same as saying that gay couples aren’t welcome, but it’s 
pretty close. Is the NM court right that the photographers have a 1st Am right 
to do so?

On the question whether religious liberty claims have anything to do with the 
compelled speech issue, if we believe that the “hybrid rights” part of Smith 
means anything, it might apply in this kind of case so that the combination of 
the claims to constitutional protection might create some synergy.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law









From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 4:22 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

I think the compelled speech issues, re: communicative work like photography, 
are interesting and sometimes difficult. I address those in an article I will 
post later this month.  All I want to say now is that religious motivation is 
irrelevant to the compelled speech argument.  (See W Va Bd of Educ v. Barnette.)

But Mark also say If [harm] depends on the message sent by the refusal, then 
we have an interesting viewpoint discrimination issue.  If, in 1965, Ollie's 
BBQ had put up a sign in the window that read Federal law says we must serve 
all, so we will, but n-s are not sincerely welcome, then he would have 
violated the Public Accommodations title of the Civil Rights Act (he would not 
have provided full and equal enjoyment of his restaurant without 
discrimination on the basis of race.)  Does Mark or anyone on this list really 
think that presents a serious First Amendment problem?  Ollie can write letters 
to Congress, and to the newspapers, and put signs on his lawn, all railing 
against the oppressive Civil Rights Act, but he cannot communicate that 
directly to customers on his business premises. If it were otherwise, the Act 
would be gutted entirely.  I think that no Justice who has served in the last 
50 years would take such a First A claim seriously.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:53 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
I also think the florist and baker examples are weaker for the religious 
claimant, especially where the flowers and cakes are generic. But what if 
custom floral arrangements involve artistic choices by the florist? What if the 
cake is (as some are) a truly creative work of art? And do only high-end bakers 
get protection from violation of conscience? What if the florist or baker is 
asked to include particular words or other expressive content in the 
arrangement or the cake? (This from someone who argued against licensing 
requirements for sellers of flowers – protectionist provisions for florists who 
fear grocery stores’ selling of flowers – on the 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Richard Friedman
But given the way you wrote your post, I don't think you really can,
because the decision was pretty deliberate to limit the 1964 Act to a
carefully defined list of public accommodations that didn't involve
intimate contact -- so no boarding houses, no barbershops, not even most
types of retail stores.  Somebody (can't remember who) wrote ap iece
several years ago emphasizing this.  I don't know how universally state
laws have filled the gap -- they certainly have to some extent, though I
imagine not with respect to boarding houses -- and I suppose there's a
national consensus that a barber can't decline to cut a person's hair on
account of race, but I don't think you can cite the '64 Act in support of
it.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 8:58 PM, Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:

  You may be right. I was using the term more metaphorically to refer to
 any business that is open to the public.

  Sandy

 Sent from my iPhone

 On Apr 1, 2015, at 6:48 PM, Richard Friedman rdfrd...@umich.edu wrote:

Hi, Sandy.  I hope all is well.  I'm writing to you off-list, because
 I haven't followed the entire conversation and may have missed something.
 But my understanding is that florists and cake-makers (assuming the cakes
 are not meant to be eaten on premises) are not public accommodations within
 the meaning of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, though they're covered by many
 state civil rights acts.  Am I in fact missing something?

  Best,

  Rich

 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:18 PM, Levinson, Sanford V 
 slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:

  I think Prof. Chen is substantially correct, but I believe, more than
 ever, that it's the kind of problem that can ( and should) be handled
 outside legal constraints. Why would I want to hire a wedding photographer
 who so clearly won't view the day as affirmatively special?  Ditto the
 band?  But I really can't work up much sympathy for the florist or baker.
 They should be treated under the general rubric of public accommodations
 and the Civil Rights Act of 1964. I'm sure there were florists and bakers
 who objected to mixes-race marriages and could cite the purported curse on
 Ham. It really doesn't (and shouldn't) matter.

  Sandy

 Sent from my iPhone

 On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:56 PM, K Chen tzn...@gmail.com wrote:

   As someone putting a wedding together, I can't explain the lack of
 sympathy for the wedding photographer as anything but thinking that their
 work is essentially interchangeable. It is not, unfortunately, and it is
 priced accordingly. Every single photographer of them seems to take their
 business very, very personally. More to the point, it is a personal,
 professional service which is by its nature selective compared to the harm
 done by impersonal corporations excluding goods and services when they
 otherwise serve the public.

  A principled difference can be drawn between accommodating personal,
 inherently selective commercial businesses and businesses that are open to
 the public at large. The vast majority of commercial transactions are from
 businesses who sell to the public, or their business community, on a
 non-discriminatory basis. When such a business denies goods or services to
 a class of person, that is an inherently political act. Such a businesses
 is not just refusing the do business with an individual or class, they are
 making an attempt to exclude them from *the definition of the public
 itself. * They are thus doing harm to both individual and society by
 imposing their will on what constitutes the political community. This harm
 grows geometrically with each exclusionary actor.

  Individual consumers on the other hand, are inherently selective. If
 you need one loaf of bread this week, you will patronize precisely one
 baker this week. If you need a salary, you will work one, maybe two jobs.
 The harm of being denied service by a consumer (or laborer) because of
 their beliefs has a societal harm, if any, nearly indistinguishable to
 being denied for any other reason.

  Some services should fall in between. I'm not convinced for the florist
 and the and the baker, but I'm sympathetic to the photographer, the doctor,
 the lawyer (ethical obligations notwithstanding) , the political
 consultant, the ghost writer...

  I don't know how far that gets liberals of course, but it *is* a
 difference beyond mere size and corporate form.

  Kevin Chen

 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org wrote:

  “[l]iberals who opposed *Smith* in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 —
 including liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely
 continue to support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing
 the extension of such exemptions to commercial businesses.



 I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many
 individuals depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do
 liberals see the conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy
 of protection, 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Richard Friedman
Hi, Sandy.  I hope all is well.  I'm writing to you off-list, because I
haven't followed the entire conversation and may have missed something.
But my understanding is that florists and cake-makers (assuming the cakes
are not meant to be eaten on premises) are not public accommodations within
the meaning of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, though they're covered by many
state civil rights acts.  Am I in fact missing something?

Best,

Rich

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:18 PM, Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:

  I think Prof. Chen is substantially correct, but I believe, more than
 ever, that it's the kind of problem that can ( and should) be handled
 outside legal constraints. Why would I want to hire a wedding photographer
 who so clearly won't view the day as affirmatively special?  Ditto the
 band?  But I really can't work up much sympathy for the florist or baker.
 They should be treated under the general rubric of public accommodations
 and the Civil Rights Act of 1964. I'm sure there were florists and bakers
 who objected to mixes-race marriages and could cite the purported curse on
 Ham. It really doesn't (and shouldn't) matter.

  Sandy

 Sent from my iPhone

 On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:56 PM, K Chen tzn...@gmail.com wrote:

   As someone putting a wedding together, I can't explain the lack of
 sympathy for the wedding photographer as anything but thinking that their
 work is essentially interchangeable. It is not, unfortunately, and it is
 priced accordingly. Every single photographer of them seems to take their
 business very, very personally. More to the point, it is a personal,
 professional service which is by its nature selective compared to the harm
 done by impersonal corporations excluding goods and services when they
 otherwise serve the public.

  A principled difference can be drawn between accommodating personal,
 inherently selective commercial businesses and businesses that are open to
 the public at large. The vast majority of commercial transactions are from
 businesses who sell to the public, or their business community, on a
 non-discriminatory basis. When such a business denies goods or services to
 a class of person, that is an inherently political act. Such a businesses
 is not just refusing the do business with an individual or class, they are
 making an attempt to exclude them from *the definition of the public
 itself. * They are thus doing harm to both individual and society by
 imposing their will on what constitutes the political community. This harm
 grows geometrically with each exclusionary actor.

  Individual consumers on the other hand, are inherently selective. If you
 need one loaf of bread this week, you will patronize precisely one baker
 this week. If you need a salary, you will work one, maybe two jobs. The
 harm of being denied service by a consumer (or laborer) because of their
 beliefs has a societal harm, if any, nearly indistinguishable to being
 denied for any other reason.

  Some services should fall in between. I'm not convinced for the florist
 and the and the baker, but I'm sympathetic to the photographer, the doctor,
 the lawyer (ethical obligations notwithstanding) , the political
 consultant, the ghost writer...

  I don't know how far that gets liberals of course, but it *is* a
 difference beyond mere size and corporate form.

  Kevin Chen

 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org wrote:

  “[l]iberals who opposed *Smith* in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 —
 including liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely
 continue to support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing
 the extension of such exemptions to commercial businesses.



 I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many
 individuals depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do
 liberals see the conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy
 of protection, but the conscience of an individual photographer, florist,
 baker, or bed and breakfast owner less worthy of protection?Justice
 Kagan, at least back in 1996 when she was in the Clinton White House,
 appeared to recognize that the consciences of individuals operating small
 commercial businesses was worthy of protection under a RFRA regime.
 Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a Evelyn Smith who,
 for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units to a
 co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was
 “outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold
 that a state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because
 the complainant is free to move to another state.”
 http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers





 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *James Oleske
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 

So much for Arkansas RFRA?

2015-04-01 Thread Marty Lederman
http://www.nytimes.com/2015/04/02/us/arkansas-indiana-religious-freedom-hutchinson-pence.html



On Tue, Mar 31, 2015 at 9:39 PM, Friedman, Howard M. 
howard.fried...@utoledo.edu wrote:

  The Arkansas legislature today passed a state RFRA. While national media
 is reporting that the bill is similar to Indiana's, in fact it is broader
 in several ways. See
 http://religionclause.blogspot.com/2015/03/arkansas-legislature-passes-rfra-law.html

 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread James Oleske
Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’
(sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious
exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full,
but I want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of
Eugene's analysis:

Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions from
antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the same
under the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long
championed.


http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/

Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial
marketplace, which is the context generating almost all of the liberal
concerns about exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's
characterization of the law in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely
the opposite argument at length in Part II of the following piece:
http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/
(The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the
Commercial Realm).

Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee,
which is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed
the issue of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court
dismissed a commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an
antidiscrimination law as patently frivolous. Instead, Eugene refers to
Justice Brennan's pre-Sherbert dissenting opinion in Crown. Whatever
Justice Brennan's views in 1961, it is difficult to understand how they are
a better representation of the Sherbert-era law than the following explicit
statement of the Court in Lee, which was joined by Justice Brennan (as was
Piggie Park):

When followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as a
matter of choice, the limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter
of conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on the statutory schemes
which are binding on others in that activity. Granting an exemption from
social security taxes to an employer operates to impose the employer's
religious faith on the employees.

Accordingly, I don't think the ACLU's current position can be accurately
described as a retreat from their support of Sherbert-era exemption
rights. As Eugene notes in his post, the ACLU still opposes Smith and
supports exemption rights outside the commercial context. As I note in my
piece, this is also true of Americans United and the Brennan Center. The
strong opposition of those organizations to extending exemption rights into
the for-profit commercial realm has sometimes been misread as a reversal of
their position on exemption rights in general (indeed, I myself have made
that mistake in the past), but as I detail in the piece cited above, an
examination of the full record shows that [l]iberals who opposed *Smith*
in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including liberal organizations,
professors, and politicians — largely continue to support religious
exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of such exemptions
to commercial businesses.

- Jim
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
“[l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including 
liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to 
support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of 
such exemptions to commercial businesses.

I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many individuals 
depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do liberals see the 
conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy of protection, but the 
conscience of an individual photographer, florist, baker, or bed and breakfast 
owner less worthy of protection?Justice Kagan, at least back in 1996 when 
she was in the Clinton White House, appeared to recognize that the consciences 
of individuals operating small commercial businesses was worthy of protection 
under a RFRA regime.   Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a 
Evelyn Smith who, for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units 
to a co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was 
“outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold that a 
state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because the 
complainant is free to move to another state.”   
http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of James Oleske
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’ 
(sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious 
exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full, but I 
want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of Eugene's 
analysis:
Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions from 
antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the same under 
the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long championed.

http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/

Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial marketplace, 
which is the context generating almost all of the liberal concerns about 
exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's characterization of the law 
in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely the opposite argument at length 
in Part II of the following piece: 
http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/ 
(The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the 
Commercial Realm).

Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee, which 
is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed the issue 
of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court dismissed a 
commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an antidiscrimination law as 
patently frivolous. Instead, Eugene refers to Justice Brennan's pre-Sherbert 
dissenting opinion in Crown. Whatever Justice Brennan's views in 1961, it is 
difficult to understand how they are a better representation of the 
Sherbert-era law than the following explicit statement of the Court in Lee, 
which was joined by Justice Brennan (as was Piggie Park):
When followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as a matter 
of choice, the limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter of 
conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on the statutory schemes which 
are binding on others in that activity. Granting an exemption from social 
security taxes to an employer operates to impose the employer's religious faith 
on the employees.

Accordingly, I don't think the ACLU's current position can be accurately 
described as a retreat from their support of Sherbert-era exemption rights. 
As Eugene notes in his post, the ACLU still opposes Smith and supports 
exemption rights outside the commercial context. As I note in my piece, this is 
also true of Americans United and the Brennan Center. The strong opposition of 
those organizations to extending exemption rights into the for-profit 
commercial realm has sometimes been misread as a reversal of their position on 
exemption rights in general (indeed, I myself have made that mistake in the 
past), but as I detail in the piece cited above, an examination of the full 
record shows that [l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 
1993 — including liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely 
continue to support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the 
extension of such exemptions to commercial businesses.
- Jim

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Greg Lipper
Beyond the question of commerce/non-commerce, there is a broader distinction 
between accommodations that harm others and accommodations that do not. This 
distinction was reflected in the Supreme Court’s opinions in United States v. 
Lee (among other pre-Smith cases), Cutter v. Wilkinson (upholding RLUIPA 
against Establishment Clause challenge), and in Justice Ginsburg’s dissent in 
Hobby Lobby and concurrence in Holt v. Hobbs.

Quite apart from Hobby Lobby’s status as a for-profit corporation, we 
(Americans United) opposed the Hobby Lobby exemption because it had the effect 
of stripping otherwise available healthcare coverage from employees’ 
compensation. We would have opposed that exemption even if the company was not 
a for-profit corporation – there were innocent third parties who were losing an 
important part of their employment compensation as a result of the exemption.

There are some accommodations (a prisoner who wants to wear a beard, an 
individual who wants to use peyote (or wine, for that matter) as part of a 
religious ceremony, etc. etc.) that do not harm third parties. There are others 
(withholding healthcare from others, exemptions from antidiscrimination law) 
that harm third parties directly. That distinction was respected in the 
pre-Smith cases and highlighted again in Cutter, but it has come under attack 
in recent rounds of RFRA litigation.



On Apr 1, 2015, at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek 
dgaub...@imb.orgmailto:dgaub...@imb.org wrote:

“[l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including 
liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to 
support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of 
such exemptions to commercial businesses.

I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many individuals 
depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do liberals see the 
conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy of protection, but the 
conscience of an individual photographer, florist, baker, or bed and breakfast 
owner less worthy of protection?Justice Kagan, at least back in 1996 when 
she was in the Clinton White House, appeared to recognize that the consciences 
of individuals operating small commercial businesses was worthy of protection 
under a RFRA regime.   Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a 
Evelyn Smith who, for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units 
to a co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was 
“outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold that a 
state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because the 
complainant is free to move to another state.”  
http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers


From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of James Oleske
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’ 
(sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious 
exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full, but I 
want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of Eugene's 
analysis:
Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions from 
antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the same under 
the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long championed.

http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/

Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial marketplace, 
which is the context generating almost all of the liberal concerns about 
exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's characterization of the law 
in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely the opposite argument at length 
in Part II of the following 
piece:http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/
 (The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the 
Commercial Realm).

Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee, which 
is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed the issue 
of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court dismissed a 
commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an antidiscrimination law as 
patently frivolous. Instead, Eugene refers to Justice Brennan's pre-Sherbert 
dissenting opinion in Crown. Whatever Justice Brennan's views in 1961, it is 
difficult to understand how they are a better representation of the 
Sherbert-era law than the following explicit statement of the Court in Lee, 
which was joined by Justice Brennan 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread James Oleske
I discuss this question -- which is about the merits of the Sherbert-era
distinction between commercial and non-commercial, not the existence of the
distinction -- in another recent piece:

There was very good reason, however, for the earlier consensus that owners
of for-profit businesses must comply with secular laws regardless of their
religious beliefs. In the commercial context, religious exemptions will
almost always impose burdens on third parties, whether employees,
customers, or business competitors. As a result, such exemptions implicate
a rule “with a long history in libertarian thought”— that rights are
limited by the need for “prevention of tangible harm to specifiable others
without their consent.” Even in its pre-*Smith *jurisprudence, which held
that exemptions from generally applicable laws were sometimes required, the
Supreme Court gave force to this limitation, refusing to exempt an employer
from the Social Security system because doing so would “operate[] to impose
the employer’s religious faith on the employees.” In so reasoning, the
Court was acting in accord with the general principle espoused by Justice
Jackson four decades earlier that the “limitations which of necessity bound
religious freedom . . . begin to operate whenever activities begin to
collide with liberties of others or of the public.” Or as Justice Ginsburg
has put it more recently, “with respect to free exercise claims no less
than free speech claims, ‘your right to swing your arms ends just where the
other man’s nose begins.’”


http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2400100 (pp. 39-40)

As I discuss in footnote 149 of the same piece, the Court has long made a
similar commercial/non-commercial distinction in its free association
jurisprudence.

- Jim

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 11:51 AM, Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org wrote:

  “[l]iberals who opposed *Smith* in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 —
 including liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely
 continue to support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing
 the extension of such exemptions to commercial businesses.



 I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many
 individuals depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do
 liberals see the conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy
 of protection, but the conscience of an individual photographer, florist,
 baker, or bed and breakfast owner less worthy of protection?Justice
 Kagan, at least back in 1996 when she was in the Clinton White House,
 appeared to recognize that the consciences of individuals operating small
 commercial businesses was worthy of protection under a RFRA regime.
 Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a Evelyn Smith who,
 for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units to a
 co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was
 “outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold
 that a state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because
 the complainant is free to move to another state.”
 http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers





 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *James Oleske
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’
 (sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious
 exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full,
 but I want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of
 Eugene's analysis:

 Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions
 from antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the
 same under the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long
 championed.




 http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/


 Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial
 marketplace, which is the context generating almost all of the liberal
 concerns about exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's
 characterization of the law in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely
 the opposite argument at length in Part II of the following piece:
 http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/
 (The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the
 Commercial Realm).

 Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee,
 which is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed
 the issue of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court
 dismissed a commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an
 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread James Oleske
The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the
Court might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but
rather, a strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm
that can be overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the
presumption (a third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead
simply discarded the Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further
than the pre-Smith law.

- Jim


On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

 I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se --
 imagine a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with
 religious dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.
 Liberals oppose exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties --
 Hobby Lobby (those female employees still do not have contraceptive
 coverage) or wedding vendor exemptions from public accommodations laws
 (those exemptions allow material and dignitary injury to potential
 customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other family members of Amish
 employees, as well as others in the social insurance pool.

 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org wrote:

  “[l]iberals who opposed *Smith* in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 —
 including liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely
 continue to support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing
 the extension of such exemptions to commercial businesses.



 I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many
 individuals depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do
 liberals see the conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy
 of protection, but the conscience of an individual photographer, florist,
 baker, or bed and breakfast owner less worthy of protection?Justice
 Kagan, at least back in 1996 when she was in the Clinton White House,
 appeared to recognize that the consciences of individuals operating small
 commercial businesses was worthy of protection under a RFRA regime.
 Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a Evelyn Smith who,
 for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units to a
 co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was
 “outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold
 that a state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because
 the complainant is free to move to another state.”
 http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers





 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *James Oleske
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’
 (sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious
 exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full,
 but I want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of
 Eugene's analysis:

 Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions
 from antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the
 same under the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long
 championed.




 http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/


 Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial
 marketplace, which is the context generating almost all of the liberal
 concerns about exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's
 characterization of the law in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely
 the opposite argument at length in Part II of the following piece:
 http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/
 (The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the
 Commercial Realm).

 Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee,
 which is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed
 the issue of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court
 dismissed a commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an
 antidiscrimination law as patently frivolous. Instead, Eugene refers to
 Justice Brennan's pre-Sherbert dissenting opinion in Crown. Whatever
 Justice Brennan's views in 1961, it is difficult to understand how they are
 a better representation of the Sherbert-era law than the following explicit
 statement of the Court in Lee, which was joined by Justice Brennan (as was
 Piggie Park):

 When followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as a
 matter of choice, the limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter
 of conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on the statutory schemes
 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Alan E Brownstein
I appreciate your point, Nelson. And I think the principle that private 
citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with other citizens’ 
religious observance deserves respect. Standing alone, it would often be 
dispositive.  Where we disagree, I think, is that in religious exemption cases 
I see two principles here that deserve our respect. The one I just quoted above 
and the principle that the majority and government should not prohibit or 
burden another citizen's religious observance. I think, you can tell me if I'm 
wrong, that you would agree that this principle standing alone also deserves 
respect. If there is no harm to third parties, you would support religious 
exemptions.


Then the question becomes what do we do when these two principles are in 
conflict with each other. I don't think either trumps the other all of the 
time. I think as the harm to third parties increases, the principle that 
citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with the other citizen's 
religious observance outweighs the religious liberty principle. I understand 
you to be saying that the religious liberty principle is always trumped in 
these cases without regard to the magnitude of the costs involved.


There are a lot of religious accommodations that result in third parties 
incurring some cost.  A RLUIPA land use accommodation might result in some 
neighboring homeowner, business or farmer incurring some diminution of value in 
their property. A public university accommodation shifting move-in day so that 
it doesn't fall on the Jewish High Holy days may require a shift in the 
academic calendar that inconveniences the travel plans of specific faculty, 
students and their families. A court accommodating the religious obligations of 
a religious attorney or witness may delay or otherwise increase the cost of 
litigation. A law banning male circumcision exempts Jewish families from its 
requirements. Does the existence of harm to third parties in these situations 
and others require the invalidation of all of these accommodations without 
regard to the magnitude of the harm borne by third parties?


Alan



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
on behalf of Nelson Tebbe nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu
Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 1:38 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



Alan, I can’t speak for others who have been defending a principle against 
burden-shifting to third parties, but I do not believe it prohibits religion 
accommodations that result in costs to the government or to the public. Rather, 
the principle prohibits government accommodations that shift meaningful costs 
from religious citizens to other identifiable private citizens. And the reason 
for this is easy to articulate and deeply rooted — private citizens should not 
have to bear the costs associated with other citizens’ religious observance.

On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:07 PM, Alan E Brownstein 
aebrownst...@ucdavis.edumailto:aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu wrote:

The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him correctly, is that 
it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be accepted if it causes 
any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim includes the general public or 
the public fisc in third party.) I think many liberals believe (or at least 
they used to believe) that rights are expensive political goods. We protect 
them even if we have to incur some cost or harm to third parties or the public 
in order to do so. Of course, that leaves open the difficult question of 
determining when the price for protecting a right is too high. (And when we are 
talking about the right to discriminate in employment or public accommodations, 
leaving religious institutions aside, the price is almost always too high.) But 
I see no historical consensus that we only protect freedom of speech or 
religious liberty when the cost of doing so is zero. That certainly wasn't the 
understanding of freedom of speech that Justice Brandeis defended in his famous 
dissents on which contemporary free speech doctrine is based.

Indeed, the argument that we should only accept zero cost religious 
accommodations is not only inconsistent with the way we generally understand 
rights, it seems inconsistent with the way we evaluate government regulations 
generally. It is one thing to argue that we should reject a religious exemption 
when the harm or cost of granting it is too high. That position is consistent 
with the general cost benefit analysis we use to discuss any government 
decision. But why should we only accept zero cost religious accommodations? We 
routinely allow government to enact laws that result in some costs, burdens, 
and harms to third parties or the general public that serve a variety of 
purposes.

Alan



___
To post, send message to 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread K Chen
As someone putting a wedding together, I can't explain the lack of sympathy
for the wedding photographer as anything but thinking that their work is
essentially interchangeable. It is not, unfortunately, and it is priced
accordingly. Every single photographer of them seems to take their business
very, very personally. More to the point, it is a personal, professional
service which is by its nature selective compared to the harm done by
impersonal corporations excluding goods and services when they otherwise
serve the public.

A principled difference can be drawn between accommodating personal,
inherently selective commercial businesses and businesses that are open to
the public at large. The vast majority of commercial transactions are from
businesses who sell to the public, or their business community, on a
non-discriminatory basis. When such a business denies goods or services to
a class of person, that is an inherently political act. Such a businesses
is not just refusing the do business with an individual or class, they are
making an attempt to exclude them from *the definition of the public
itself. *They are thus doing harm to both individual and society by
imposing their will on what constitutes the political community. This harm
grows geometrically with each exclusionary actor.

Individual consumers on the other hand, are inherently selective. If you
need one loaf of bread this week, you will patronize precisely one baker
this week. If you need a salary, you will work one, maybe two jobs. The
harm of being denied service by a consumer (or laborer) because of their
beliefs has a societal harm, if any, nearly indistinguishable to being
denied for any other reason.

Some services should fall in between. I'm not convinced for the florist and
the and the baker, but I'm sympathetic to the photographer, the doctor, the
lawyer (ethical obligations notwithstanding) , the political consultant,
the ghost writer...

I don't know how far that gets liberals of course, but it *is* a
difference beyond mere size and corporate form.

Kevin Chen

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org wrote:

  “[l]iberals who opposed *Smith* in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 —
 including liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely
 continue to support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing
 the extension of such exemptions to commercial businesses.



 I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many
 individuals depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do
 liberals see the conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy
 of protection, but the conscience of an individual photographer, florist,
 baker, or bed and breakfast owner less worthy of protection?Justice
 Kagan, at least back in 1996 when she was in the Clinton White House,
 appeared to recognize that the consciences of individuals operating small
 commercial businesses was worthy of protection under a RFRA regime.
 Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a Evelyn Smith who,
 for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units to a
 co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was
 “outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold
 that a state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because
 the complainant is free to move to another state.”
 http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers





 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *James Oleske
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’
 (sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious
 exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full,
 but I want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of
 Eugene's analysis:

 Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions
 from antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the
 same under the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long
 championed.




 http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/


 Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial
 marketplace, which is the context generating almost all of the liberal
 concerns about exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's
 characterization of the law in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely
 the opposite argument at length in Part II of the following piece:
 http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/
 (The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the
 Commercial Realm).

 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread K Chen
private citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with other
citizens’ religious observance. 

Except they do. When my co-workers take time off work to observe religious
restrictions, everyone else's work increases. Sometimes noticeably. And
trying to sort between meaningful costs and *de minimis* costs is going
to be tricky. The difference might be drawn between third parties being
forced to subsidize a religious belief (I cannot eat ham, so you all have
to chip in for a steak sandwich) and merely being asked to bear with it.

Kevin Chen

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 4:38 PM, Nelson Tebbe nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu
wrote:



  Alan, I can’t speak for others who have been defending a principle
 against burden-shifting to third parties, but I do not believe it prohibits
 religion accommodations that result in costs to the government or to the
 public. Rather, the principle prohibits government accommodations that
 shift meaningful costs from religious citizens to other identifiable
 private citizens. And the reason for this is easy to articulate and deeply
 rooted — private citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with
 other citizens’ religious observance.

  On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:07 PM, Alan E Brownstein aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu
 wrote:

  The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him
 correctly, is that it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be
 accepted if it causes any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim
 includes the general public or the public fisc in third party.) I think
 many liberals believe (or at least they used to believe) that rights are
 expensive political goods. We protect them even if we have to incur some
 cost or harm to third parties or the public in order to do so. Of course,
 that leaves open the difficult question of determining when the price for
 protecting a right is too high. (And when we are talking about the right to
 discriminate in employment or public accommodations, leaving religious
 institutions aside, the price is almost always too high.) But I see no
 historical consensus that we only protect freedom of speech or religious
 liberty when the cost of doing so is zero. That certainly wasn't the
 understanding of freedom of speech that Justice Brandeis defended in his
 famous dissents on which contemporary free speech doctrine is based.

  Indeed, the argument that we should only accept zero cost religious
 accommodations is not only inconsistent with the way we generally
 understand rights, it seems inconsistent with the way we evaluate
 government regulations generally. It is one thing to argue that we should
 reject a religious exemption when the harm or cost of granting it is too
 high. That position is consistent with the general cost benefit analysis we
 use to discuss any government decision. But why should we only accept zero
 cost religious accommodations? We routinely allow government to enact laws
 that result in some costs, burdens, and harms to third parties or the
 general public that serve a variety of purposes.

  Alan


  --
 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu on behalf of James Oleske 
 jole...@lclark.edu
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 1, 2015 12:22 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

   The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the
 Court might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but
 rather, a strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm
 that can be overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the
 presumption (a third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead
 simply discarded the Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further
 than the pre-Smith law.

  - Jim


   On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

  I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se --
 imagine a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with
 religious dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.
 Liberals oppose exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties --
 Hobby Lobby (those female employees still do not have contraceptive
 coverage) or wedding vendor exemptions from public accommodations laws
 (those exemptions allow material and dignitary injury to potential
 customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other family members of Amish
 employees, as well as others in the social insurance pool.


 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
I think Prof. Chen is substantially correct, but I believe, more than ever, 
that it's the kind of problem that can ( and should) be handled outside legal 
constraints. Why would I want to hire a wedding photographer who so clearly 
won't view the day as affirmatively special?  Ditto the band?  But I really 
can't work up much sympathy for the florist or baker. They should be treated 
under the general rubric of public accommodations and the Civil Rights Act of 
1964. I'm sure there were florists and bakers who objected to mixes-race 
marriages and could cite the purported curse on Ham. It really doesn't (and 
shouldn't) matter.

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:56 PM, K Chen tzn...@gmail.commailto:tzn...@gmail.com 
wrote:

As someone putting a wedding together, I can't explain the lack of sympathy for 
the wedding photographer as anything but thinking that their work is 
essentially interchangeable. It is not, unfortunately, and it is priced 
accordingly. Every single photographer of them seems to take their business 
very, very personally. More to the point, it is a personal, professional 
service which is by its nature selective compared to the harm done by 
impersonal corporations excluding goods and services when they otherwise serve 
the public.

A principled difference can be drawn between accommodating personal, inherently 
selective commercial businesses and businesses that are open to the public at 
large. The vast majority of commercial transactions are from businesses who 
sell to the public, or their business community, on a non-discriminatory basis. 
When such a business denies goods or services to a class of person, that is an 
inherently political act. Such a businesses is not just refusing the do 
business with an individual or class, they are making an attempt to exclude 
them from the definition of the public itself. They are thus doing harm to both 
individual and society by imposing their will on what constitutes the political 
community. This harm grows geometrically with each exclusionary actor.

Individual consumers on the other hand, are inherently selective. If you need 
one loaf of bread this week, you will patronize precisely one baker this week. 
If you need a salary, you will work one, maybe two jobs. The harm of being 
denied service by a consumer (or laborer) because of their beliefs has a 
societal harm, if any, nearly indistinguishable to being denied for any other 
reason.

Some services should fall in between. I'm not convinced for the florist and the 
and the baker, but I'm sympathetic to the photographer, the doctor, the lawyer 
(ethical obligations notwithstanding) , the political consultant, the ghost 
writer...

I don't know how far that gets liberals of course, but it is a difference 
beyond mere size and corporate form.

Kevin Chen

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek 
dgaub...@imb.orgmailto:dgaub...@imb.org wrote:
“[l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including 
liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to 
support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of 
such exemptions to commercial businesses.

I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many individuals 
depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do liberals see the 
conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy of protection, but the 
conscience of an individual photographer, florist, baker, or bed and breakfast 
owner less worthy of protection?Justice Kagan, at least back in 1996 when 
she was in the Clinton White House, appeared to recognize that the consciences 
of individuals operating small commercial businesses was worthy of protection 
under a RFRA regime.   Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a 
Evelyn Smith who, for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units 
to a co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was 
“outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold that a 
state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because the 
complainant is free to move to another state.”   
http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers


From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of James Oleske
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’ 
(sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious 
exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full, but I 
want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of Eugene's 
analysis:
Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions from 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
Non-Jews are under no obligation not to eat pork (or adhere to almost all of 
the other 612 mitzvot). So there is no stigma attached to any non-Jew who wants 
to buy a ham at a kosher butchery. That can't be said with regard to the 
florist who refuses to sell a bouquet for use at a same-sex marriage, who is 
necessarily condoning the presumptively sinful conduct. Ironically or not, the 
only person a Jewish butcher might be upset with is another Jew. This 
underscores the fact that very few Jewish laws are universal.  This is not 
true of most purported Christian precepts (beginning with the widely shared 
view among many a Evangelicals that I'm damned for failure to accept the 
teaching of John 3:16 (which I know by heart having memorized it some 65 years 
ago in order to earn a Bible certificate from the state of North Carolina).

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Apr 1, 2015, at 3:44 PM, Will Esser 
willes...@yahoo.commailto:willes...@yahoo.com wrote:

Chip,

Can you expound on your argument that wedding vendor exemptions from public 
accommodations laws allow material and dignitary injury to potential 
customers and that liberals only oppose exemptions that impinge on the 
welfare of third parties?  It seems that both sides agree that the kosher 
butcher deserves a religious exemption, and yet granting that exemption imposes 
some cost on third parties (i.e. anyone who wishes to purchase pork must go 
elsewhere, which could involve multiple trips to different butchers, or may 
mean spending more time and money to go to a butcher further away).  So it's 
not really that there is no cost to third parties, but perhaps simply a cost 
which society is more ready to accept (i.e. Go buy your pork somewhere else.)

As I understood the third-party harm argument in Hobby Lobby, the argument 
was that without insurance coverage, female Hobby Lobby employees would be 
unable to afford coverage of the particular, objectionable contraceptives and 
therefore the third party harm was equivalent to total lack of access.

Given modern changes in societal perspectives, I have not heard the same 
argument about a total lack of access when it comes to wedding vendors for 
same-sex wedding ceremonies.  Under the assumption the goods and services are 
otherwise generally available in the marketplace (i.e. there are plenty of 
wedding photographers, bakers, etc. who would be happy for the business of 
same-sex weddings), what is the distinguishing factor which causes material 
and dignitary injury in the wedding vendor exemptions scenario but not in the 
kosher butcher example?  In both, the customers want a service which they can 
get in the marketplace (although perhaps not from the exact person or place 
they want it).  And in both, the reason for not providing the service is the 
same (i.e. violation of a sincerely held religious belief).

Thanks in advance for clarification.

Will

Will Esser
Charlotte, North Carolina



From: James Oleske jole...@lclark.edumailto:jole...@lclark.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 3:22 PM
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the Court 
might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but rather, a 
strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm that can be 
overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the presumption (a 
third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead simply discarded the 
Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further than the pre-Smith law.

- Jim




On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu 
icl...@law.gwu.edumailto:icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se -- imagine 
a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with religious 
dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.  Liberals oppose 
exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties -- Hobby Lobby (those 
female employees still do not have contraceptive coverage) or wedding vendor 
exemptions from public accommodations laws (those exemptions allow material and 
dignitary injury to potential customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other 
family members of Amish employees, as well as others in the social insurance 
pool.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek 
dgaub...@imb.orgmailto:dgaub...@imb.org wrote:
“[l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including 
liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to 
support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of 
such exemptions to commercial businesses.

I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many individuals 
depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do liberals see the 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Alan E Brownstein
The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him correctly, is that 
it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be accepted if it causes 
any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim includes the general public or 
the public fisc in third party.) I think many liberals believe (or at least 
they used to believe) that rights are expensive political goods. We protect 
them even if we have to incur some cost or harm to third parties or the public 
in order to do so. Of course, that leaves open the difficult question of 
determining when the price for protecting a right is too high. (And when we are 
talking about the right to discriminate in employment or public accommodations, 
leaving religious institutions aside, the price is almost always too high.) But 
I see no historical consensus that we only protect freedom of speech or 
religious liberty when the cost of doing so is zero. That certainly wasn't the 
understanding of freedom of speech that Justice Brandeis defended in his famous 
dissents on which contemporary free speech doctrine is based.


Indeed, the argument that we should only accept zero cost religious 
accommodations is not only inconsistent with the way we generally understand 
rights, it seems inconsistent with the way we evaluate government regulations 
generally. It is one thing to argue that we should reject a religious exemption 
when the harm or cost of granting it is too high. That position is consistent 
with the general cost benefit analysis we use to discuss any government 
decision. But why should we only accept zero cost religious accommodations? We 
routinely allow government to enact laws that result in some costs, burdens, 
and harms to third parties or the general public that serve a variety of 
purposes.


Alan



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
on behalf of James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu
Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 12:22 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the Court 
might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but rather, a 
strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm that can be 
overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the presumption (a 
third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead simply discarded the 
Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further than the pre-Smith law.

- Jim


On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu 
icl...@law.gwu.edumailto:icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se -- imagine 
a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with religious 
dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.  Liberals oppose 
exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties -- Hobby Lobby (those 
female employees still do not have contraceptive coverage) or wedding vendor 
exemptions from public accommodations laws (those exemptions allow material and 
dignitary injury to potential customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other 
family members of Amish employees, as well as others in the social insurance 
pool.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Nelson Tebbe


Alan, I can’t speak for others who have been defending a principle against 
burden-shifting to third parties, but I do not believe it prohibits religion 
accommodations that result in costs to the government or to the public. Rather, 
the principle prohibits government accommodations that shift meaningful costs 
from religious citizens to other identifiable private citizens. And the reason 
for this is easy to articulate and deeply rooted — private citizens should not 
have to bear the costs associated with other citizens’ religious observance.

On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:07 PM, Alan E Brownstein 
aebrownst...@ucdavis.edumailto:aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu wrote:

The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him correctly, is that 
it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be accepted if it causes 
any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim includes the general public or 
the public fisc in third party.) I think many liberals believe (or at least 
they used to believe) that rights are expensive political goods. We protect 
them even if we have to incur some cost or harm to third parties or the public 
in order to do so. Of course, that leaves open the difficult question of 
determining when the price for protecting a right is too high. (And when we are 
talking about the right to discriminate in employment or public accommodations, 
leaving religious institutions aside, the price is almost always too high.) But 
I see no historical consensus that we only protect freedom of speech or 
religious liberty when the cost of doing so is zero. That certainly wasn't the 
understanding of freedom of speech that Justice Brandeis defended in his famous 
dissents on which contemporary free speech doctrine is based.

Indeed, the argument that we should only accept zero cost religious 
accommodations is not only inconsistent with the way we generally understand 
rights, it seems inconsistent with the way we evaluate government regulations 
generally. It is one thing to argue that we should reject a religious exemption 
when the harm or cost of granting it is too high. That position is consistent 
with the general cost benefit analysis we use to discuss any government 
decision. But why should we only accept zero cost religious accommodations? We 
routinely allow government to enact laws that result in some costs, burdens, 
and harms to third parties or the general public that serve a variety of 
purposes.

Alan



From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
on behalf of James Oleske jole...@lclark.edumailto:jole...@lclark.edu
Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 12:22 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the Court 
might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but rather, a 
strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm that can be 
overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the presumption (a 
third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead simply discarded the 
Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further than the pre-Smith law.

- Jim


On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu 
icl...@law.gwu.edumailto:icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se -- imagine 
a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with religious 
dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.  Liberals oppose 
exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties -- Hobby Lobby (those 
female employees still do not have contraceptive coverage) or wedding vendor 
exemptions from public accommodations laws (those exemptions allow material and 
dignitary injury to potential customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other 
family members of Amish employees, as well as others in the social insurance 
pool.


___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Will Esser
Chip,
Can you expound on your argument that wedding vendor exemptions from public 
accommodations laws allow material and dignitary injury to potential 
customers and that liberals only oppose exemptions that impinge on the 
welfare of third parties?  It seems that both sides agree that the kosher 
butcher deserves a religious exemption, and yet granting that exemption imposes 
some cost on third parties (i.e. anyone who wishes to purchase pork must go 
elsewhere, which could involve multiple trips to different butchers, or may 
mean spending more time and money to go to a butcher further away).  So it's 
not really that there is no cost to third parties, but perhaps simply a cost 
which society is more ready to accept (i.e. Go buy your pork somewhere else.)
As I understood the third-party harm argument in Hobby Lobby, the argument 
was that without insurance coverage, female Hobby Lobby employees would be 
unable to afford coverage of the particular, objectionable contraceptives and 
therefore the third party harm was equivalent to total lack of access.  

Given modern changes in societal perspectives, I have not heard the same 
argument about a total lack of access when it comes to wedding vendors for 
same-sex wedding ceremonies.  Under the assumption the goods and services are 
otherwise generally available in the marketplace (i.e. there are plenty of 
wedding photographers, bakers, etc. who would be happy for the business of 
same-sex weddings), what is the distinguishing factor which causes material 
and dignitary injury in the wedding vendor exemptions scenario but not in the 
kosher butcher example?  In both, the customers want a service which they can 
get in the marketplace (although perhaps not from the exact person or place 
they want it).  And in both, the reason for not providing the service is the 
same (i.e. violation of a sincerely held religious belief).  

Thanks in advance for clarification.  

Will
 Will Esser 
Charlotte, North Carolina

  From: James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu 
 Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 3:22 PM
 Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights
   
The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the Court 
might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but rather, a 
strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm that can be 
overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the presumption (a 
third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead simply discarded the 
Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further than the pre-Smith law.

- Jim




On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se -- imagine 
a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with religious 
dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.  Liberals oppose 
exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties -- Hobby Lobby (those 
female employees still do not have contraceptive coverage) or wedding vendor 
exemptions from public accommodations laws (those exemptions allow material and 
dignitary injury to potential customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other 
family members of Amish employees, as well as others in the social insurance 
pool.
On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org wrote:

“[l]iberals who opposedSmith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including 
liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to 
support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of 
such exemptions to commercial businesses. I’m not sure I’m seeing the 
principled distinction.   Do not many individuals depend for their livelihood 
on commercial businesses?   Why do liberals see the conscience of individuals 
like Sherbert or Thomas worthy of protection, but the conscience of an 
individual photographer, florist, baker, or bed and breakfast owner less worthy 
of protection?    Justice Kagan, at least back in 1996 when she was in the 
Clinton White House, appeared to recognize that the consciences of individuals 
operating small commercial businesses was worthy of protection under a RFRA 
regime.   Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a Evelyn Smith 
who, for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units to a 
co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was “outrageous.”  
 She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold that a state law does 
not impose a substantial burden on religion because the complainant is free to 
move to another state.”  
http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers  From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]On Behalf Of James Oleske
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread James Oleske
Following up on Alan and Nelson's discussion of third-party burdens, I
think it might be helpful to identify two separate legal issues that are
impacted by such burdens:

1. The issue of whether a party has a right to a religious exemption in a
given case.
2. The issue of whether a discretionary legislative decision to grant an
exemption in a given situation violates the Establishment Clause.

I only meant to be addressing Issue #1, and I think the Sherbert-era
decisions are best read as not requiring exemptions as a matter of right
when such exemptions would burden identifiable third parties. And I think
the Lee language is best explained as a recognition that exemptions for
commercial businesses will almost always impose burdens on third parties,
whether employees, customers, or business competitors. I don't think,
however, that burdens shouldered by the government or the public at large
qualified as a third-party burdens under the Sherbert-era decisions, as
evidenced by the exemption required in Sherbert itself.

As for Issue #2, my view of the Establishment Clause limitations on
exemptions is not as robust as Nelson's, and I think legislatures can
likely require burdens on third parties that go beyond the burdens that the
Sherbert-era Court would have imposed in granting exemptions as a matter of
right.

- Jim


On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:46 PM, Alan E Brownstein aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu
wrote:

   I appreciate your point, Nelson. And I think the principle
 that private citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with
 other citizens’ religious observance deserves respect. Standing alone, it
 would often be dispositive.  Where we disagree, I think, is that in
 religious exemption cases I see two principles here that deserve our
 respect. The one I just quoted above and the principle that the majority
 and government should not prohibit or burden another citizen's religious
 observance. I think, you can tell me if I'm wrong, that you would agree
 that this principle standing alone also deserves respect. If there is no
 harm to third parties, you would support religious exemptions.


  Then the question becomes what do we do when these two principles are in
 conflict with each other. I don't think either trumps the other all of the
 time. I think as the harm to third parties increases, the principle that
 citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with the other
 citizen's religious observance outweighs the religious liberty principle. I
 understand you to be saying that the religious liberty principle is always
 trumped in these cases without regard to the magnitude of the costs
 involved.


  There are a lot of religious accommodations that result in third parties
 incurring some cost.  A RLUIPA land use accommodation might result in some
 neighboring homeowner, business or farmer incurring some diminution of
 value in their property. A public university accommodation shifting move-in
 day so that it doesn't fall on the Jewish High Holy days may require a
 shift in the academic calendar that inconveniences the travel plans of
 specific faculty, students and their families. A court accommodating the
 religious obligations of a religious attorney or witness may delay or
 otherwise increase the cost of litigation. A law banning male circumcision
 exempts Jewish families from its requirements. Does the existence of harm
 to third parties in these situations and others require the invalidation of
 all of these accommodations without regard to the magnitude of the harm
 borne by third parties?


  Alan


  --
 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu on behalf of Nelson Tebbe 
 nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 1, 2015 1:38 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



  Alan, I can’t speak for others who have been defending a principle
 against burden-shifting to third parties, but I do not believe it prohibits
 religion accommodations that result in costs to the government or to the
 public. Rather, the principle prohibits government accommodations that
 shift meaningful costs from religious citizens to other identifiable
 private citizens. And the reason for this is easy to articulate and deeply
 rooted — private citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with
 other citizens’ religious observance.

  On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:07 PM, Alan E Brownstein aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu
 wrote:

  The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him
 correctly, is that it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be
 accepted if it causes any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim
 includes the general public or the public fisc in third party.) I think
 many liberals believe (or at least they used to believe) that rights are
 expensive political goods. We protect them even if we have to incur some
 cost or harm to 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Ira Lupu
Thanks for the question, Will. If the kosher butcher gets that exemption,
he will sell pork to no one.  He never has and never will carry pork in his
shop.  He also does not sell soda, cars, or wedding cakes.  If you want
that stuff, you must go elsewhere.  Is that a cost to third parties?''  No
more than that imposed by any (that is, every) other merchant who sells
less than everything.

Compare that to a discriminatory refusal to sell.  Baker A does sell
wedding cakes, but not to same sex couples.  Two injuries -- material and
dignitary.  The material injury is the lost opportunity to buy a cake at
the quality and price offered by that baker.  Maybe you can do as well or
better elsewhere, nearby, or maybe not.  The dignitary injury is more
serious -- the couple is seeking goods to celebrate one of the most
important and special days of their lives. And the baker says, in effect,
I do not respect your marriage as a marriage.  In my belief system, it is
not a marriage at all, because you are of the same sex. (The baker might
also think or say that in his view the relationship is disordered, or an
abomination, and/or against God's plan, but let's assume he says nothing
like that all.)  The baker has wounded the couple with this disrespect, and
done so in regard to a day that has significant meaning in their lives.

Those are the focused, third party harms in the refusal to sell goods or
services to some that you sell to others, especially (though not only) for
a wedding reception.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 4:38 PM, Will Esser willes...@yahoo.com wrote:

 Chip,

 Can you expound on your argument that wedding vendor exemptions from
 public accommodations laws allow material and dignitary injury to
 potential customers and that liberals only oppose exemptions that impinge
 on the welfare of third parties?  It seems that both sides agree that the
 kosher butcher deserves a religious exemption, and yet granting that
 exemption imposes *some* cost on third parties (i.e. anyone who wishes to
 purchase pork must go elsewhere, which could involve multiple trips to
 different butchers, or may mean spending more time and money to go to a
 butcher further away).  So it's not really that there is *no* cost to
 third parties, but perhaps simply a cost which society is more ready to
 accept (i.e. Go buy your pork somewhere else.)

 As I understood the third-party harm argument in Hobby Lobby, the
 argument was that without insurance coverage, female Hobby Lobby employees
 would be unable to afford coverage of the particular, objectionable
 contraceptives and therefore the third party harm was equivalent to total
 lack of access.

 Given modern changes in societal perspectives, I have not heard the same
 argument about a total lack of access when it comes to wedding vendors for
 same-sex wedding ceremonies.  Under the assumption the goods and services
 are otherwise generally available in the marketplace (i.e. there are plenty
 of wedding photographers, bakers, etc. who would be happy for the business
 of same-sex weddings), what is the distinguishing factor which causes
 material and dignitary injury in the wedding vendor exemptions scenario
 but not in the kosher butcher example?  In both, the customers want a
 service which they can get in the marketplace (although perhaps not from
 the exact person or place they want it).  And in both, the reason for not
 providing the service is the same (i.e. violation of a sincerely held
 religious belief).

 Thanks in advance for clarification.

 Will

 Will Esser
 Charlotte, North Carolina


   --
  *From:* James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 1, 2015 3:22 PM
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

 The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the
 Court might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but
 rather, a strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm
 that can be overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the
 presumption (a third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead
 simply discarded the Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further
 than the pre-Smith law.

 - Jim




 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

 I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se --
 imagine a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with
 religious dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.
 Liberals oppose exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties --
 Hobby Lobby (those female employees still do not have contraceptive
 coverage) or wedding vendor exemptions from public accommodations laws
 (those exemptions allow material and dignitary injury to potential
 customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other family members of Amish
 employees, as well as others in the 

RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Scarberry, Mark
I also think the florist and baker examples are weaker for the religious 
claimant, especially where the flowers and cakes are generic. But what if 
custom floral arrangements involve artistic choices by the florist? What if the 
cake is (as some are) a truly creative work of art? And do only high-end bakers 
get protection from violation of conscience? What if the florist or baker is 
asked to include particular words or other expressive content in the 
arrangement or the cake? (This from someone who argued against licensing 
requirements for sellers of flowers - protectionist provisions for florists who 
fear grocery stores' selling of flowers - on the basis that flower arranging is 
a kind of art that the government has no right to license, other than for 
health purposes.) What if the custom florist decides to include a lot of black 
roses in the arrangements? Or just puts the flowers together without using any 
creativity (so that they look like flowers you would get through 
1-800-Flowers)? Can the florist be required to enter into the contract to 
provide flowers and then be required to follow some sort of industry standard 
of artistry in arranging the flowers?

In the photography example, if the photographer must photograph a ceremony that 
he or she believes wrong, may the photographer refuse to use the creative 
skills that would ordinarily be used? (E.g., posing the couple in a particular 
way, using filters to get a romantic look, telling them to kiss for the 
photograph, etc.) I suppose that goes with my view that wedding photography is 
creation of celebratory art, and the First Amendment compelled speech cases 
prohibit the government from requiring the photographer to create art.

On the harm question, of course there is a matter of baseline. Do I harm you by 
not photographing your ceremony? Or do I benefit you by doing it? If that 
depends on the message sent by the refusal, then we have an interesting 
viewpoint discrimination issue.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law




From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Levinson, Sanford V
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 3:18 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

I think Prof. Chen is substantially correct, but I believe, more than ever, 
that it's the kind of problem that can ( and should) be handled outside legal 
constraints. Why would I want to hire a wedding photographer who so clearly 
won't view the day as affirmatively special?  Ditto the band?  But I really 
can't work up much sympathy for the florist or baker. They should be treated 
under the general rubric of public accommodations and the Civil Rights Act of 
1964. I'm sure there were florists and bakers who objected to mixes-race 
marriages and could cite the purported curse on Ham. It really doesn't (and 
shouldn't) matter.

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:56 PM, K Chen tzn...@gmail.commailto:tzn...@gmail.com 
wrote:
As someone putting a wedding together, I can't explain the lack of sympathy for 
the wedding photographer as anything but thinking that their work is 
essentially interchangeable. It is not, unfortunately, and it is priced 
accordingly. Every single photographer of them seems to take their business 
very, very personally. More to the point, it is a personal, professional 
service which is by its nature selective compared to the harm done by 
impersonal corporations excluding goods and services when they otherwise serve 
the public.

A principled difference can be drawn between accommodating personal, inherently 
selective commercial businesses and businesses that are open to the public at 
large. The vast majority of commercial transactions are from businesses who 
sell to the public, or their business community, on a non-discriminatory basis. 
When such a business denies goods or services to a class of person, that is an 
inherently political act. Such a businesses is not just refusing the do 
business with an individual or class, they are making an attempt to exclude 
them from the definition of the public itself. They are thus doing harm to both 
individual and society by imposing their will on what constitutes the political 
community. This harm grows geometrically with each exclusionary actor.

Individual consumers on the other hand, are inherently selective. If you need 
one loaf of bread this week, you will patronize precisely one baker this week. 
If you need a salary, you will work one, maybe two jobs. The harm of being 
denied service by a consumer (or laborer) because of their beliefs has a 
societal harm, if any, nearly indistinguishable to being denied for any other 
reason.

Some services should fall in between. I'm not convinced for the florist and the 
and the baker, but I'm sympathetic to the photographer, the doctor, the lawyer 
(ethical obligations notwithstanding)