Hobby Lobby was a RFRA case, so I’m puzzled below by the references below to 
the First Amendment (point 1) and a “constitutionally protected right” (point 
6).

David B. Cruz
Professor of Law
University of Southern California Gould School of Law
Los Angeles, CA 90089-0071
U.S.A.


From: "Daniel J. Greenwood" 
<daniel.greenw...@hofstra.edu<mailto:daniel.greenw...@hofstra.edu>>
Reply-To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics 
<religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu<mailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu>>
Date: Tuesday, July 1, 2014 at 1:40 PM
To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics 
<religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu<mailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu>>
Subject: RE: Hobby Lobby Question


1.       Rhetorically, it was probably overdetermined that the Court grant the 
rights to the corporation and not its “owners”.



By claiming that it was protecting the corporation, the Court avoided the 
curious problem of why the FA should protect a particular, and peculiarly 
absolutist, view of corporate governance – “an economic theory which a large 
part of the country does not entertain.”



2.       Non-profits clearly don’t have owners.  Neither (less clearly) do 
for-profit corporations, at least where they have more than one shareholder: no 
one has the most basic right of ownership, the right to waste.  Neither does 
Hobby Lobby, if I understand correctly: its sole shareholder is a trust and the 
trustees are barred from exercising independent judgment on a number of 
important issues.



3.       Accordingly, had the Court based its new right in the rights of the 
“owners” it would have been forced to make a clear and decisive distinction 
between closely-held, shareholder-controlled corporations – the only form of 
corporation that has owners in anything resembling the ordinary sense of 
ownership (and even then, only if you take corporate law procedure to override 
its substance) –and all other corporations.  That, of course, would make the 
Court’s reliance on the Dictionary Act silly.



4.       Moreover, had it given the right to the “owners”, it would have to 
confront the problem that we no longer allow ownership of employees.  Whatever 
the “owners” own (the Greens, apparently, own nothing at all, but are instead 
the beneficiaries of a trust that owns Hobby Lobby’s shares), they do not own 
the bodies or the medical care or the contract rights of the firm’s employees.  
The issue here is the relative power of different claimants to speak for the 
corporation under the rules of corporate governance:  whether employees, 
managers, shareholders or the People get to decide the terms on which corporate 
medical insurance is written.



5.       Who determines the corporate position on controversial issues ought to 
be an issue of corporate law, contract law and the ACA, perhaps even 
Federalism.  It has next to nothing to do with religious freedom, except to the 
extent that general principles (not our law) suggest allowing different 
individuals to follow their conscience with a minimum of interference from 
other individuals or power structures.



6.       The Greens have won the right to impose their religious views on the 
corporation and its unwilling participants despite the ACA’s rule that they 
must share this corporate decisionmaking role with their employees.  The ACA 
decentralized the corporate decision about contraceptives, allowing each 
corporate participant to follow her or his own conscience.  The Court holds, 
instead, that contraceptive decisions may be made instead by directors or 
shareholders or trust beneficiaries of the shareholder(it’s not entirely clear 
which role now has a constitutionally protected right to override ordinary 
corporate law and impose its views on the other corporate participants) and 
imposed on corporate employees and customers.  Those people are put to the 
“difficult choice” of giving up the benefits of corporate form or accepting the 
fiat of the newly empowered corporate elite.  The issue resolved here is not 
state vs citizen or majority religion vs minority religion but rather the 
internal decisionmaking structure of the firm.





7.       Following an ancient tradition, the Court claims that granting rights 
to the organization protects the “people (including shareholders, officers, and 
employees) who are associated with [it]”.  In US constitutional law, this 
argument goes back at least to Letson, the first 
corporation-and-the-Constitution case.  Repetition and age, however, have not 
made the argument sound.



The claim, as should be clear to anyone familiar with the social contract 
tradition, is false.  Protecting the organization protects the incumbent 
officeholders against upstarts and dissidents who might want to share the 
decisionmaking power or disagree with the decisions officeholders seek to 
impose on them.  Thus, minority and democratic rights in international and 
constitutional law begin by reducing the protection the “state” has (inherited 
royal prerogative, established church, sovereign immunity, comity, etc).   To 
bring basic civil rights to Americans living in the former slave states, the 
first step had to be to limit, not enhance, states’ rights; the same was true 
to protect subjects from their dictatorial governments.  To allow married women 
control of their property or abolish husbands’ spousal rape privileges, it was 
essential to violate, not protect, the privacy and autonomy of the family.  
Protecting the “privacy” of the corporation prevents employees and customers 
and shareholders from learning what managers are doing, let alone influencing 
it – that is the opposite of protecting them.  To protect non-officeholders, we 
always limit the rights of the office -- and they always complain that 
carpetbaggers are interfering with the rights of the institution.



Protecting the corporation’s religious rights can only mean protecting the 
rights of its incumbent decisionmakers to use their power to impose their 
religious views on other participants.  This is substantively if not 
technically “establishment,” not “free exercise.”  If the goal were to protect 
the religious freedom of corporate participants other than the board of 
directors and those who vote for them, we’d have to restrict the corporation’s 
freedom of action, much as we do in civil rights law, labor law, contract law, 
consumer protection, environmental and safety law, human rights law, etc.


DG
_______________________________________________
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Reply via email to