Does substantial matter?

2013-12-03 Thread Marty Lederman
Doug may well be right that for most lower courts (but not all -- see
Michael Masinter's post), whether the term burden is modified by
substantial will not matter, because such courts inevitably end up
balancing the degree (or nature) of the burden on religious exercise --
indeed, the degree of religious significance -- against the strength of the
government's interest in denying an exemption.

From where we stand today, however, that's a somewhat odd argument to make,
for two reasons.  The first is that the terms of RFRA (and most state
analogues) don't ask courts to do any such balancing:  Instead, the court
is asked in the first instance to assess whether there is a substantial
burden -- on the face of it, what appears to be a binary, yes or no
question -- and then (in theory) is not supposed to further assess the
importance/substantiality/centrality/degree/etc. of that burden when moving
on to the second step, which merely asks whether the government interest is
compelling and can otherwise be advanced, even with a religious exemption.

The second reason that we can't so easily dismiss substantial is, of
course, that the Supreme Court has just granted cert. in a landmark case
that will likely turn on precisely what the word substantial means.  (At
the very least, that question will get a thorough workout in the briefing
and argument.)

Many of those who are supporting Hobby Lobby will presumably argue that the
adjective substantial refers only to the degree of coercion resulting
from the government action (criminal sanctions being most coercive and thus
creating the most substantial burden; denial of unemployment benefits also
substantial (cf. Sherbert); denial of highly discretionary, rarely
awarded benefits much less substantial, etc.).

The government and its amici will no doubt argue, by contrast, that the
court must also assess the degree of importance of the religious exercise
to the plaintiff.

My understanding from Doug's previous writings is that he agrees that some
such assessment of religious significance (a continuous variable in
Doug's terms -- not an on/off switch) is necessary, or at least inevitable
(as his post here suggests).  For example, he wrote this in a 2009 piece in
Rutgers J. L  Rel.:

The text of the Constitution applies to all forms of religious practice,
central or peripheral. Still, *the argument against oppression is strongest
with respect to the most important religious practices, and weaker with
respect to marginal practices that believers might be willing to give
up.*But the importance of religious practices varies from person to
person, and
is difficult for courts to assess. The Court is right that it would be a
mistake to hold that practices central to a religion are constitutionally
protected and that practices below some threshold of centrality are not
constitutionally protected. A far better rule is that all exercise of
religion is constitutionally protected, but that *less weighty government
interests can justify burdens on less weighty religious practices*. A
threshold requirement of centrality would be an all-or-nothing rule; it
would treat a continuous variable--religious significance--as though it
were a dichotomous variable, and it would thereby greatly magnify the
consequences of the inevitable errors in assessing religious significance.
Such a threshold requirement would wholly deny protection, instead of
according somewhat less protection, when religious significance is somewhat
underestimated. But *the impossibility of fairly administering a threshold
requirement of centrality does not mean that the courts should wholly
ignore the importance of the religious practice when they are asked to
decide a claim to exemption*. The compelling interest test is best
understood as a balancing test with the thumb on the scale in favor of
protecting constitutional rights. The best way to formulate the question is
whether the government interest compellingly outweighs the religious
interest. *The compelling interest test is not often formulated that way,
but I think that it must operate that way in practice, and sometimes in the
course of applying the test, the Court seems to say as much*. To borrow and
correct Justice Scalia's example, it is easier for the government to
justify a ban on throwing rice at weddings than to justify a ban on getting
married in church.

On Mon, Dec 2, 2013 at 12:28 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 Apologies to anyone getting this twice; I think it bounced the first time.



 What I said is in the second letter (link below) and summarized in the
 e-mail to which Marci responded. We supported the bill as drafted, without
 “substantial;” I also suggested that the committee restore “substantial” if
 it were bothered by the omission. I think most of my co-signers would have
 agreed with that suggestion, but I don’t know that, because they were not
 asked to sign the second letter. I said it didn’t matter much because the
 

RE: Does substantial matter?

2013-12-03 Thread Douglas Laycock
I stand by what Marty quotes, which is why I think the facts of cases, and
the judge's attitude towards the statute and religious liberty, generally
make far more difference than the presence or absence of the word
substantial. No doubt there are some cases where, given the facts and the
judge's attitude, the presence or absence of substantial makes the
difference. I don't think there are many. 

 

Michael Masinter's example is clearly not such a case; more on that
shortly,.

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 8:45 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Does substantial matter?

 

Doug may well be right that for most lower courts (but not all -- see
Michael Masinter's post), whether the term burden is modified by
substantial will not matter, because such courts inevitably end up
balancing the degree (or nature) of the burden on religious exercise --
indeed, the degree of religious significance -- against the strength of the
government's interest in denying an exemption.

From where we stand today, however, that's a somewhat odd argument to make,
for two reasons.  The first is that the terms of RFRA (and most state
analogues) don't ask courts to do any such balancing:  Instead, the court is
asked in the first instance to assess whether there is a substantial burden
-- on the face of it, what appears to be a binary, yes or no question -- and
then (in theory) is not supposed to further assess the
importance/substantiality/centrality/degree/etc. of that burden when moving
on to the second step, which merely asks whether the government interest is
compelling and can otherwise be advanced, even with a religious exemption.

The second reason that we can't so easily dismiss substantial is, of
course, that the Supreme Court has just granted cert. in a landmark case
that will likely turn on precisely what the word substantial means.  (At
the very least, that question will get a thorough workout in the briefing
and argument.)

Many of those who are supporting Hobby Lobby will presumably argue that the
adjective substantial refers only to the degree of coercion resulting from
the government action (criminal sanctions being most coercive and thus
creating the most substantial burden; denial of unemployment benefits also
substantial (cf. Sherbert); denial of highly discretionary, rarely awarded
benefits much less substantial, etc.).  

The government and its amici will no doubt argue, by contrast, that the
court must also assess the degree of importance of the religious exercise to
the plaintiff.

My understanding from Doug's previous writings is that he agrees that some
such assessment of religious significance (a continuous variable in
Doug's terms -- not an on/off switch) is necessary, or at least inevitable
(as his post here suggests).  For example, he wrote this in a 2009 piece in
Rutgers J. L  Rel.:

The text of the Constitution applies to all forms of religious practice,
central or peripheral. Still, the argument against oppression is strongest
with respect to the most important religious practices, and weaker with
respect to marginal practices that believers might be willing to give up.
But the importance of religious practices varies from person to person, and
is difficult for courts to assess. The Court is right that it would be a
mistake to hold that practices central to a religion are constitutionally
protected and that practices below some threshold of centrality are not
constitutionally protected. A far better rule is that all exercise of
religion is constitutionally protected, but that less weighty government
interests can justify burdens on less weighty religious practices. A
threshold requirement of centrality would be an all-or-nothing rule; it
would treat a continuous variable--religious significance--as though it were
a dichotomous variable, and it would thereby greatly magnify the
consequences of the inevitable errors in assessing religious significance.
Such a threshold requirement would wholly deny protection, instead of
according somewhat less protection, when religious significance is somewhat
underestimated. But the impossibility of fairly administering a threshold
requirement of centrality does not mean that the courts should wholly ignore
the importance of the religious practice when they are asked to decide a
claim to exemption. The compelling interest test is best understood as a
balancing test with the thumb on the scale in favor of protecting
constitutional rights. The best way to formulate the question is whether the
government interest compellingly outweighs the religious interest. The
compelling interest test is not often formulated that way, but I think that
it must operate that way in 

Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

2013-12-03 Thread Ira Lupu
The reason not to construe RFRA to apply to all secular philosophical
objectors is that it's just plain crazy as a matter of policy.  RFRA (which
we would have to rename FRA after such a construction) applies to all of
federal law.  So this construction would give the holder of every crackpot
philosophy about the limited role of government the legal leverage of
requiring strict scrutiny as to why he or she should not be exempted from
the reach of federal law.  (Title VII is only about the employment
relation, and the duty of accommodation is limited to de minimis burdens on
employers.  RFRA, or your FRA, would extend to everything.)  So if
construction to avoid constitutional doubt is what we are looking for, the
only sensible move is to keep the R -- that is what Congress was doing in
1993 -- and to construe RFRA so as to avoid significant third party harms
(in this case, to employees).


On Mon, Dec 2, 2013 at 11:43 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 I appreciate Jim’s argument, and also the arguments that
 the problem with the exemption isn’t discrimination in favor of religion,
 but rather the burden on third parties, regardless of whether the exemption
 is only for the religious.  (I hope to respond to those arguments soon.)



 But as to the point below -- and assuming that a RFRA
 employer mandate exemption that covers secular conscientious objectors is
 as constitutional as the conscientious objector draft exemption -- wouldn’t
 the canon of interpreting statutes to avoid unconstitutionality (even
 setting aside constitutional “doubt”) be relevant here?  It’s true that
 RFRA generally endorses *Sherbert *and *Yoder* and other federal cases,
 and in the absence of an Establishment Clause objection it might well be
 interpreted to apply only to religious objectors.  But if indeed such an
 interpretation would lead to a finding that RFRA is unconstitutional,
 wouldn’t that cut pretty strongly in favor of avoiding that interpretation,
 and including secular philosophical objectors?  The language isn’t as
 clearly hostile to such an interpretation as the language in the draft law
 was in *Welsh*.  And, as I noted, the other broad federal religious
 accommodation regime -- the Title VII religious accommodation provision --
 has largely been read by lower courts as covering secular philosophical
 objectors as well as religious ones.  Why wouldn’t that, coupled with the
 avoidance of unconstitutionality canon, counsel in favor of a
 constitutionally permissible interpretation rather than a constitutionally
 impermissible one?



 Eugene



 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *James Oleske
 *Sent:* Monday, December 02, 2013 8:11 AM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: The Establishment Clause, burden on others, the employer
 mandate, and the draft



 Eugene -- One question about this passage from your message:

 I take it that RFRA could likewise be interpreted to apply to
 philosophical conscientious beliefs.

 Could such an interpretation of RFRA be squared with its stated purpose of
 restoring the protection of free exercise as set forth in Yoder, which said
 that philosophic beliefs were not protected under the Free Exercise Clause?

 [I]if the Amish asserted their claims because of their subjective
 evaluation and rejection of the contemporary secular values accepted by the
 majority, much as Thoreau rejected the social values of his time and
 isolated himself at Walden Pond, their claims would not rest on a religious
 basis. Thoreau's choice was philosophical and personal rather than
 religious, and such belief does not rise to the demands of the Religion
 Clauses. - Yoder at 216.


 Of course, as you note, the Court had to twist the language of the
 conscientious objector exemption to apply it to philosophic conscientious
 beliefs, but it's hard to imagine today's Court engaging in the same type
 of (non) textual analysis.



 - Jim



 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.




-- 
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 

Warner v. City of Boca Raton

2013-12-03 Thread Douglas Laycock
Michael cites Warner v. Boca Raton, 887 So.2d 1023 (Fla. 2004), as an
example of a case where the word “substantially” was critical to the result.
And that is what the court says. But it is quite obviously not true.

 

The Florida court read “substantially” to mean that only those practices
that were required by a faith were protected by Florida RFRA. The Florida
legislature had attempted to specifically negate any such requirement, as
the court recognized. The statute defined “exercise of religion” as “an act
or refusal to act that is substantially motivated by religious belief,
whether or not the religious exercise is compulsory or central to a larger
system of religious belief.” The Florida court’s interpretation of
“substantially burden” negated this definition and read back into the
statute a requirement that religious exercise be compulsory to be protected.
The statutory definition of religious exercise will never again matter to a
Florida RFRA case; only a subset of religious exercise as defined will ever
be protected. This opinion is plainly driven not by the word
“substantially,” but by the court’s disagreement with the scope of the
statute. Full disclosure: I argued the case for the plaintiffs.

 

Here is what the court said about the statutory definition, just before it
turned to the meaning of “substantially burden”:

 

“The FRFRA includes several important definitions:

 

* * *

 

(3) “Exercise of religion” means an act or refusal to act that is
substantially motivated by a religious belief, whether or not the religious
exercise is compulsory or central to a larger system of religious belief.

 

§ 761.02, Fla. Stat. (2003).

 

* * * The protection afforded to the free exercise of religiously motivated
activity under the FRFRA is broader than that afforded by the decisions of
the United States Supreme Court for two interrelated reasons. First, the
FRFRA expands the free exercise right as construed by the Supreme Court in
Smith because it reinstates the Court's pre-Smith holdings by applying the
compelling interest test to neutral laws of general application. Second,
under the FRFRA the definition of protected “exercise of religion” subject
to the compelling state interest test includes any act or refusal to act
whether or not compelled by or central to a system of religious belief. The
legislative history of the FRFRA suggests that in order to state a claim
that the government has infringed upon the free exercise of religion, a
plaintiff must only establish that the government has placed a substantial
burden on a practice motivated by a sincere religious belief.”

 

887 So.2d at 1031-32 (emphasis in original).

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Michael Masinter
Sent: Monday, December 02, 2013 8:44 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; Christopher Lund
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing
substantial as modifier of burden in state RFRAs

 

The adjective substantial must do some work. For one state case so
holding, see Warner v. City of Boca Raton, 807 So. 2d 1023, 1033-1034 (Fla.
2004):

 

Accordingly, we conclude that the narrow definition of substantial burden
adopted by the Fourth, Ninth, and Eleventh Circuits is most consistent with
the language and intent of the FRFRA. Thus, we hold that a substantial
burden on the free exercise of religion is one that either compels the
religious adherent to engage in conduct that his religion forbids or forbids
him to engage in conduct that his religion requires. See Mack, 80 F.3d at
1178. We acknowledge that our adoption of this definition may occasionally
place courts in the position of having to determine whether a particular
religious practice is obligatory or forbidden. However, we conclude that
this inquiry is preferable to one that requires the Court to question the
centrality of a particular religious belief or negates the legislative
requirement that only conduct that is substantially burdened be protected by
strict scrutiny.

 

By analogy, consider the word reasonable in the phrase reasonable  

accommodation as construed by U.S. Airways v. Barnett, 535 U.S. 391,

400-401 (2002):

 

These arguments [equating reasonable with effective] do not persuade us that
Barnett's legal interpretation of reasonable is correct. For one thing, in
ordinary English the word reasonable does not mean effective. It is the
word accommodation, not the word reasonable, that conveys the need for
effectiveness. An ineffective modification or adjustment will not
accommodate a disabled individual's limitations. Nor does an ordinary
English meaning of the term reasonable accommodation 

Re: Warner v. City of Boca Raton

2013-12-03 Thread Marci Hamilton
I find it interesting that Doug concedes in this thread that results in RFRA 
cases turn on the judge's predilections on religious liberty regardless of the 
law's language.  I have witnessed this lack of neutrality in several cases, 
most notably the ruling by Judge Randa in the Milwaukee bankruptcy case.  (Full 
disclosure-- I represent the creditors' committee composed mostly of sex abuse 
victims in that case.)

RFRA seems to invite a lack of neutrality despite its language saying the 
Establishment Clause is to be unaffected.   The results as described by Doug 
and Chris strike me as involving judges who are being encouraged to and who do 
violate the Establishment Clause and their code of judicial ethics. I am 
interested in others thoughts on this.

I would appreciate no ad hominem responses to these factual observations.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 3, 2013, at 10:46 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:

 Michael cites Warner v. Boca Raton, 887 So.2d 1023 (Fla. 2004), as an example 
 of a case where the word “substantially” was critical to the result. And that 
 is what the court says. But it is quite obviously not true.
  
 The Florida court read “substantially” to mean that only those practices that 
 were required by a faith were protected by Florida RFRA. The Florida 
 legislature had attempted to specifically negate any such requirement, as the 
 court recognized. The statute defined “exercise of religion” as “an act or 
 refusal to act that is substantially motivated by religious belief, whether 
 or not the religious exercise is compulsory or central to a larger system of 
 religious belief.” The Florida court’s interpretation of “substantially 
 burden” negated this definition and read back into the statute a requirement 
 that religious exercise be compulsory to be protected. The statutory 
 definition of religious exercise will never again matter to a Florida RFRA 
 case; only a subset of religious exercise as defined will ever be protected. 
 This opinion is plainly driven not by the word “substantially,” but by the 
 court’s disagreement with the scope of the statute. Full disclosure: I argued 
 the case for the plaintiffs.
  
 Here is what the court said about the statutory definition, just before it 
 turned to the meaning of “substantially burden”:
  
 “The FRFRA includes several important definitions:
  
 * * *
  
 (3) “Exercise of religion” means an act or refusal to act that is 
 substantially motivated by a religious belief, whether or not the religious 
 exercise is compulsory or central to a larger system of religious belief.
  
 § 761.02, Fla. Stat. (2003).
  
 * * * The protection afforded to the free exercise of religiously motivated 
 activity under the FRFRA is broader than that afforded by the decisions of 
 the United States Supreme Court for two interrelated reasons. First, the 
 FRFRA expands the free exercise right as construed by the Supreme Court in 
 Smith because it reinstates the Court's pre-Smith holdings by applying the 
 compelling interest test to neutral laws of general application. Second, 
 under the FRFRA the definition of protected “exercise of religion” subject to 
 the compelling state interest test includes any act or refusal to act whether 
 or not compelled by or central to a system of religious belief. The 
 legislative history of the FRFRA suggests that in order to state a claim that 
 the government has infringed upon the free exercise of religion, a plaintiff 
 must only establish that the government has placed a substantial burden on a 
 practice motivated by a sincere religious belief.”
  
 887 So.2d at 1031-32 (emphasis in original).
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
  
 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Michael Masinter
 Sent: Monday, December 02, 2013 8:44 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; Christopher Lund
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing substantial 
 as modifier of burden in state RFRAs
  
 The adjective substantial must do some work. For one state case so holding, 
 see Warner v. City of Boca Raton, 807 So. 2d 1023, 1033-1034 (Fla. 2004):
  
 Accordingly, we conclude that the narrow definition of substantial burden 
 adopted by the Fourth, Ninth, and Eleventh Circuits is most consistent with 
 the language and intent of the FRFRA. Thus, we hold that a substantial burden 
 on the free exercise of religion is one that either compels the religious 
 adherent to engage in conduct that his religion forbids or forbids him to 
 engage in conduct that his religion requires. See Mack, 80 F.3d at 1178. We 
 acknowledge that 

RE: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

2013-12-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Why is it so crazy?  If, for instance, religious objectors to 
abortion get exemptions from having to participate in abortion, conscientious 
secular philosophical objectors would get such exemptions, too.  That seems 
fair, and is indeed the rule both under various abortion-specific conscience 
clauses and, as I noted, as to Title VII -- which is narrower than RFRA in some 
ways, but broader in another very important way (since it applies to private 
employers).  Nor has the interpretation of Title VII to which I point been seen 
by courts as removing the religious from religious accommodation; it just 
follows cases such as Welsh in treating deeply held conscientious philosophical 
beliefs similar to religious beliefs, something that would often have to be 
done in any event given the large variety of religious views, including 
nontheistic ones.

As to crackpot philosoph[ies], crackpot religious 
objections -- including idiosyncratic ones -- are already covered under RFRA.  
Moreover, since the great majority of Americans consists of religious 
believers, most philosophical objections can be tied by at least some of the 
objectors to their religious beliefs, especially since all that is required is 
sincerity of belief and not the sharing of the belief by a larger group.  Yet 
RFRA has not  been terribly burdensome for the government, as best I can tell.  
Why would allowing similarly crackpot (or noncrackpot) secular philosophical 
objections to be covered suddenly cause much bigger problems?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:45 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

The reason not to construe RFRA to apply to all secular philosophical objectors 
is that it's just plain crazy as a matter of policy.  RFRA (which we would have 
to rename FRA after such a construction) applies to all of federal law.  So 
this construction would give the holder of every crackpot philosophy about the 
limited role of government the legal leverage of requiring strict scrutiny as 
to why he or she should not be exempted from the reach of federal law.  (Title 
VII is only about the employment relation, and the duty of accommodation is 
limited to de minimis burdens on employers.  RFRA, or your FRA, would extend to 
everything.)  So if construction to avoid constitutional doubt is what we are 
looking for, the only sensible move is to keep the R -- that is what Congress 
was doing in 1993 -- and to construe RFRA so as to avoid significant third 
party harms (in this case, to employees).

On Mon, Dec 2, 2013 at 11:43 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
I appreciate Jim's argument, and also the arguments that the 
problem with the exemption isn't discrimination in favor of religion, but 
rather the burden on third parties, regardless of whether the exemption is only 
for the religious.  (I hope to respond to those arguments soon.)

But as to the point below -- and assuming that a RFRA employer 
mandate exemption that covers secular conscientious objectors is as 
constitutional as the conscientious objector draft exemption -- wouldn't the 
canon of interpreting statutes to avoid unconstitutionality (even setting aside 
constitutional doubt) be relevant here?  It's true that RFRA generally 
endorses Sherbert and Yoder and other federal cases, and in the absence of an 
Establishment Clause objection it might well be interpreted to apply only to 
religious objectors.  But if indeed such an interpretation would lead to a 
finding that RFRA is unconstitutional, wouldn't that cut pretty strongly in 
favor of avoiding that interpretation, and including secular philosophical 
objectors?  The language isn't as clearly hostile to such an interpretation as 
the language in the draft law was in Welsh.  And, as I noted, the other broad 
federal religious accommodation regime -- the Title VII religious accommodation 
provision -- has largely been read by lower courts as covering secular 
philosophical objectors as well as religious ones.  Why wouldn't that, coupled 
with the avoidance of unconstitutionality canon, counsel in favor of a 
constitutionally permissible interpretation rather than a constitutionally 
impermissible one?

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of James Oleske
Sent: Monday, December 02, 2013 8:11 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The Establishment Clause, burden on others, the employer mandate, 
and the draft

Eugene -- One question about this passage from your message:

I take it that RFRA could likewise be interpreted to 

Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

2013-12-03 Thread Ira Lupu
I'm happy to let others answer the question of why Eugene's FRA would be
crazy (and profoundly contrary to the statute Congress enacted in 1993).
 If Eugene is not persuaded, so be it.


On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 10:57 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 Why is it so crazy?  If, for instance, religious objectors
 to abortion get exemptions from having to participate in abortion,
 conscientious secular philosophical objectors would get such exemptions,
 too.  That seems fair, and is indeed the rule both under various
 abortion-specific conscience clauses and, as I noted, as to Title VII --
 which is narrower than RFRA in some ways, but broader in another very
 important way (since it applies to private employers).  Nor has the
 interpretation of Title VII to which I point been seen by courts as
 removing the “religious” from “religious accommodation”; it just follows
 cases such as Welsh in treating deeply held conscientious philosophical
 beliefs similar to religious beliefs, something that would often have to be
 done in any event given the large variety of religious views, including
 nontheistic ones.



 As to “crackpot philosoph[ies],” “crackpot” religious
 objections -- including idiosyncratic ones -- are already covered under
 RFRA.  Moreover, since the great majority of Americans consists of
 religious believers, most philosophical objections can be tied by at least
 some of the objectors to their religious beliefs, especially since all that
 is required is sincerity of belief and not the sharing of the belief by a
 larger group.  Yet RFRA has not  been terribly burdensome for the
 government, as best I can tell.  Why would allowing similarly crackpot (or
 noncrackpot) secular philosophical objections to be covered suddenly cause
 much bigger problems?



 Eugene



 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Ira Lupu
 *Sent:* Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:45 AM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions



 The reason not to construe RFRA to apply to all secular philosophical
 objectors is that it's just plain crazy as a matter of policy.  RFRA (which
 we would have to rename FRA after such a construction) applies to all of
 federal law.  So this construction would give the holder of every crackpot
 philosophy about the limited role of government the legal leverage of
 requiring strict scrutiny as to why he or she should not be exempted from
 the reach of federal law.  (Title VII is only about the employment
 relation, and the duty of accommodation is limited to de minimis burdens on
 employers.  RFRA, or your FRA, would extend to everything.)  So if
 construction to avoid constitutional doubt is what we are looking for, the
 only sensible move is to keep the R -- that is what Congress was doing in
 1993 -- and to construe RFRA so as to avoid significant third party harms
 (in this case, to employees).



 On Mon, Dec 2, 2013 at 11:43 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu
 wrote:

 I appreciate Jim’s argument, and also the arguments that
 the problem with the exemption isn’t discrimination in favor of religion,
 but rather the burden on third parties, regardless of whether the exemption
 is only for the religious.  (I hope to respond to those arguments soon.)



 But as to the point below -- and assuming that a RFRA
 employer mandate exemption that covers secular conscientious objectors is
 as constitutional as the conscientious objector draft exemption -- wouldn’t
 the canon of interpreting statutes to avoid unconstitutionality (even
 setting aside constitutional “doubt”) be relevant here?  It’s true that
 RFRA generally endorses *Sherbert *and *Yoder* and other federal cases,
 and in the absence of an Establishment Clause objection it might well be
 interpreted to apply only to religious objectors.  But if indeed such an
 interpretation would lead to a finding that RFRA is unconstitutional,
 wouldn’t that cut pretty strongly in favor of avoiding that interpretation,
 and including secular philosophical objectors?  The language isn’t as
 clearly hostile to such an interpretation as the language in the draft law
 was in *Welsh*.  And, as I noted, the other broad federal religious
 accommodation regime -- the Title VII religious accommodation provision --
 has largely been read by lower courts as covering secular philosophical
 objectors as well as religious ones.  Why wouldn’t that, coupled with the
 avoidance of unconstitutionality canon, counsel in favor of a
 constitutionally permissible interpretation rather than a constitutionally
 impermissible one?



 Eugene



 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *James Oleske
 *Sent:* Monday, December 02, 2013 8:11 AM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for 

Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

2013-12-03 Thread Marci Hamilton
Chip has cut to the chase (thank you)  

i would add that Eugene's reasoning further underscores how RFRA is in fact a 
non-ratified amendment to the First Amendment, as the Court pointed out in a 
footnote in Boerne.   Advocates for it like Eugene cannot build in all the 
rules they like by borrowing from Supreme Court First Amendment doctrine but 
then say it is just a statute.As a statute, the plain language rule, the 
very title and the use of free exercise and the reference to religious cases 
means, yes, legislators are constrained to apply it only to religious 
believers.  If its application to only the religious makes it a violation of 
the Establishment Clause, we have a constitutional violation. 

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 3, 2013, at 11:03 AM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

 I'm happy to let others answer the question of why Eugene's FRA would be 
 crazy (and profoundly contrary to the statute Congress enacted in 1993).  If 
 Eugene is not persuaded, so be it.  
 
 
 On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 10:57 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 Why is it so crazy?  If, for instance, religious objectors 
 to abortion get exemptions from having to participate in abortion, 
 conscientious secular philosophical objectors would get such exemptions, 
 too.  That seems fair, and is indeed the rule both under various 
 abortion-specific conscience clauses and, as I noted, as to Title VII -- 
 which is narrower than RFRA in some ways, but broader in another very 
 important way (since it applies to private employers).  Nor has the 
 interpretation of Title VII to which I point been seen by courts as removing 
 the “religious” from “religious accommodation”; it just follows cases such 
 as Welsh in treating deeply held conscientious philosophical beliefs similar 
 to religious beliefs, something that would often have to be done in any 
 event given the large variety of religious views, including nontheistic ones.
 
  
 
 As to “crackpot philosoph[ies],” “crackpot” religious 
 objections -- including idiosyncratic ones -- are already covered under 
 RFRA.  Moreover, since the great majority of Americans consists of religious 
 believers, most philosophical objections can be tied by at least some of the 
 objectors to their religious beliefs, especially since all that is required 
 is sincerity of belief and not the sharing of the belief by a larger group.  
 Yet RFRA has not  been terribly burdensome for the government, as best I can 
 tell.  Why would allowing similarly crackpot (or noncrackpot) secular 
 philosophical objections to be covered suddenly cause much bigger problems?
 
  
 
 Eugene
 
  
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
 Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:45 AM
 
 
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions
  
 
 The reason not to construe RFRA to apply to all secular philosophical 
 objectors is that it's just plain crazy as a matter of policy.  RFRA (which 
 we would have to rename FRA after such a construction) applies to all of 
 federal law.  So this construction would give the holder of every crackpot 
 philosophy about the limited role of government the legal leverage of 
 requiring strict scrutiny as to why he or she should not be exempted from 
 the reach of federal law.  (Title VII is only about the employment relation, 
 and the duty of accommodation is limited to de minimis burdens on employers. 
  RFRA, or your FRA, would extend to everything.)  So if construction to 
 avoid constitutional doubt is what we are looking for, the only sensible 
 move is to keep the R -- that is what Congress was doing in 1993 -- and to 
 construe RFRA so as to avoid significant third party harms (in this case, to 
 employees).
 
  
 
 On Mon, Dec 2, 2013 at 11:43 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 
 I appreciate Jim’s argument, and also the arguments that the 
 problem with the exemption isn’t discrimination in favor of religion, but 
 rather the burden on third parties, regardless of whether the exemption is 
 only for the religious.  (I hope to respond to those arguments soon.)
 
  
 
 But as to the point below -- and assuming that a RFRA 
 employer mandate exemption that covers secular conscientious objectors is as 
 constitutional as the conscientious objector draft exemption -- wouldn’t the 
 canon of interpreting statutes to avoid unconstitutionality (even setting 
 aside constitutional “doubt”) be relevant here?  It’s true that RFRA 
 generally endorses Sherbert and Yoder and other federal cases, and in the 
 absence of an Establishment Clause objection it might well be interpreted to 
 apply only to religious objectors.  But if indeed such an 

Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

2013-12-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
So I take it the EEOC and the great majority of courts that 
have considered the meaning of “religion” in Title VII are wrong, too?  Here 
are the citations I had when I last researched the matter in 1999:  Protos v. 
Volkswagen of Am., Inc., 797 F.2d 129, 137 n.4 (3d Cir. 1986) (The breadth of 
the 'exemption' afforded by Title VII is underscored by the fact that in 
defining religion, the EEOC has used the same broad definition as the Selective 
Service employs for conscientious objector purposes.); Nottelson v. Smith 
Steel Workers, 643 F.2d 445, 454 n.12 (7th Cir. 1981) (noting the same broad 
definition); Redmond v. GAF Corp., 574 F.2d 897, 901 n.12 (7th Cir. 1978) (We 
believe the proper test to be applied to the determination of what is 
'religious' under § 2000e(j) can be derived from the Supreme Court decisions in 
[Welsh] and [United States v. Seeger, 380 U.S. 163 (1969)], i.e., (1) is the 
'belief' for which protection is sought 'religious' in person's own scheme of 
things, and (2) is it 'sincerely held.'); Ali v. Southeast Neighborhood House, 
519 F. Supp. 489, 490 (D.D.C. 1981) (Sincere beliefs, meaningful to the 
believer, need not be confined in either source or content to traditional or 
parochial concepts of religion. [Welsh.] See also [Seeger] for the definition 
of 'religious training and belief' as applied to a conscientious objector 
claim, which definition is no less appropriate here.); Wondzell v. Alaska Wood 
Prods., Inc., 583 P.2d 860, 866 n.12 (Alaska 1978) (In order to avoid the 
danger of unconstitutionality we would interpret [the state statute] to accord 
the same privileges to all sincere conscientious beliefs, whether or not they 
are accompanied by a belief in a supreme being.); Kolodziej v. Smith, 682 
N.E.2d 604, 607 (Mass. 1997).

Even in the face of this caselaw, and the argument that such preference for 
religion makes the statute unconstitutional, the Court can’t read RFRA the same 
way, but is instead compelled to read it in a way that makes it 
unconstitutional?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 8:14 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

Chip has cut to the chase (thank you)

i would add that Eugene's reasoning further underscores how RFRA is in fact a 
non-ratified amendment to the First Amendment, as the Court pointed out in a 
footnote in Boerne.   Advocates for it like Eugene cannot build in all the 
rules they like by borrowing from Supreme Court First Amendment doctrine but 
then say it is just a statute.As a statute, the plain language rule, the 
very title and the use of free exercise and the reference to religious cases 
means, yes, legislators are constrained to apply it only to religious 
believers.  If its application to only the religious makes it a violation of 
the Establishment Clause, we have a constitutional violation.

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton



On Dec 3, 2013, at 11:03 AM, Ira Lupu 
icl...@law.gwu.edumailto:icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
I'm happy to let others answer the question of why Eugene's FRA would be crazy 
(and profoundly contrary to the statute Congress enacted in 1993).  If Eugene 
is not persuaded, so be it.

On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 10:57 AM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
Why is it so crazy?  If, for instance, religious objectors to 
abortion get exemptions from having to participate in abortion, conscientious 
secular philosophical objectors would get such exemptions, too.  That seems 
fair, and is indeed the rule both under various abortion-specific conscience 
clauses and, as I noted, as to Title VII -- which is narrower than RFRA in some 
ways, but broader in another very important way (since it applies to private 
employers).  Nor has the interpretation of Title VII to which I point been seen 
by courts as removing the “religious” from “religious accommodation”; it just 
follows cases such as Welsh in treating deeply held conscientious philosophical 
beliefs similar to religious beliefs, something that would often have to be 
done in any event given the large variety of religious views, including 
nontheistic ones.

As to “crackpot philosoph[ies],” “crackpot” religious 
objections -- including idiosyncratic ones -- are already covered under RFRA.  
Moreover, since the great majority of Americans consists of religious 
believers, most philosophical objections can be tied by at least some of the 
objectors to their religious beliefs, especially since all that is required is 
sincerity of belief and not the sharing of the belief by a larger group.  Yet 
RFRA has not  been terribly burdensome for the government, as best I 

Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

2013-12-03 Thread Marci Hamilton
Religion is in the title.   The only testimony supporting it or RLUIPA was by 
religious folks.   Congress had no basis to enact and NEVER would
have enacted a law subjecting every law in the country to strict scrutiny 
triggered by every imaginable belief.   That statute is actually irrational.

It is a statute and its title is clear.   If this is to be its interpretation 
repeal should not be far behind. 

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 3, 2013, at 11:22 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 So I take it the EEOC and the great majority of courts that 
 have considered the meaning of “religion” in Title VII are wrong, too?  Here 
 are the citations I had when I last researched the matter in 1999:  Protos v. 
 Volkswagen of Am., Inc., 797 F.2d 129, 137 n.4 (3d Cir. 1986) (The breadth 
 of the 'exemption' afforded by Title VII is underscored by the fact that in 
 defining religion, the EEOC has used the same broad definition as the 
 Selective Service employs for conscientious objector purposes.); Nottelson 
 v. Smith Steel Workers, 643 F.2d 445, 454 n.12 (7th Cir. 1981) (noting the 
 same broad definition); Redmond v. GAF Corp., 574 F.2d 897, 901 n.12 (7th 
 Cir. 1978) (We believe the proper test to be applied to the determination of 
 what is 'religious' under § 2000e(j) can be derived from the Supreme Court 
 decisions in [Welsh] and [United States v. Seeger, 380 U.S. 163 (1969)], 
 i.e., (1) is the 'belief' for which protection is sought 'religious' in 
 person's own scheme of things, and (2) is it 'sincerely held.'); Ali v. 
 Southeast Neighborhood House, 519 F. Supp. 489, 490 (D.D.C. 1981) (Sincere 
 beliefs, meaningful to the believer, need not be confined in either source or 
 content to traditional or parochial concepts of religion. [Welsh.] See also 
 [Seeger] for the definition of 'religious training and belief' as applied to 
 a conscientious objector claim, which definition is no less appropriate 
 here.); Wondzell v. Alaska Wood Prods., Inc., 583 P.2d 860, 866 n.12 (Alaska 
 1978) (In order to avoid the danger of unconstitutionality we would 
 interpret [the state statute] to accord the same privileges to all sincere 
 conscientious beliefs, whether or not they are accompanied by a belief in a 
 supreme being.); Kolodziej v. Smith, 682 N.E.2d 604, 607 (Mass. 1997). 
  
 Even in the face of this caselaw, and the argument that such preference for 
 religion makes the statute unconstitutional, the Court can’t read RFRA the 
 same way, but is instead compelled to read it in a way that makes it 
 unconstitutional?
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 8:14 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions
  
 Chip has cut to the chase (thank you)  
  
 i would add that Eugene's reasoning further underscores how RFRA is in fact a 
 non-ratified amendment to the First Amendment, as the Court pointed out in a 
 footnote in Boerne.   Advocates for it like Eugene cannot build in all the 
 rules they like by borrowing from Supreme Court First Amendment doctrine but 
 then say it is just a statute.As a statute, the plain language rule, 
 the very title and the use of free exercise and the reference to religious 
 cases means, yes, legislators are constrained to apply it only to religious 
 believers.  If its application to only the religious makes it a violation of 
 the Establishment Clause, we have a constitutional violation. 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
  
  
 
 On Dec 3, 2013, at 11:03 AM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
 
 I'm happy to let others answer the question of why Eugene's FRA would be 
 crazy (and profoundly contrary to the statute Congress enacted in 1993).  If 
 Eugene is not persuaded, so be it.  
  
 
 On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 10:57 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 Why is it so crazy?  If, for instance, religious objectors to 
 abortion get exemptions from having to participate in abortion, conscientious 
 secular philosophical objectors would get such exemptions, too.  That seems 
 fair, and is indeed the rule both under various abortion-specific conscience 
 clauses and, as I noted, as to Title VII -- which is narrower than RFRA in 
 some ways, but broader in another very important way (since it applies to 
 private employers).  Nor has the interpretation of Title VII to which I point 
 been seen by courts as removing the “religious” from “religious 
 accommodation”; it just follows cases such as Welsh in treating deeply held 
 conscientious philosophical beliefs similar to religious beliefs, something 
 that 

Re: Warner v. City of Boca Raton

2013-12-03 Thread Paul Horwitz
Hopefully this is not ad hominem! I don't see anything unique about this in 
RFRA. It is a standard concern with any legal test that involves the use of 
standards, balancing, and other questions of judicial application in the case. 
It is true of vast swaths of constitutional law and common law. See, e.g., 
Posner's discussion in Reflections on Judging of the difficulties of framing 
legal tests given the plasticity and imprecision of language. It is what leads 
some legal thinkers--but not Posner, in all cases--to favor the use of rules 
and formalism. But it's not unique to religion, religious freedom, or RFRA.

To this I would add that 1) rules and formalism front-load but do not eliminate 
the problem of judicial discretion; 2) although the problem Marci raises is 
quite genuine, not everyone agrees that eliminating balancing or judicial 
discretion root and branch are necessary and indefeasible elements of whatever 
the rule of law is; 3) whether rules or standards are preferable in 
particular areas is better analyzed, in my view, as a matter of pragmatic 
weighing and institutional analysis than by invoking the charged and protean 
terms of the rule of law; and 4) whether such decisions constitute a violation 
of the oath is contestable for similar reasons, and we're better off just 
asking whether particular decisions are right or wrong given the legal and 
factual materials in play. (Just as we would in asking whether, say, a court 
soundly decided a case involving a clear and present danger or proximate cause 
or reasonable person inquiry). 

Regards, 

Paul Horwitz

 On Dec 3, 2013, at 10:13 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 
 I find it interesting that Doug concedes in this thread that results in RFRA 
 cases turn on the judge's predilections on religious liberty regardless of 
 the law's language.  I have witnessed this lack of neutrality in several 
 cases, most notably the ruling by Judge Randa in the Milwaukee bankruptcy 
 case.  (Full disclosure-- I represent the creditors' committee composed 
 mostly of sex abuse victims in that case.)
 
 RFRA seems to invite a lack of neutrality despite its language saying the 
 Establishment Clause is to be unaffected.   The results as described by Doug 
 and Chris strike me as involving judges who are being encouraged to and who 
 do violate the Establishment Clause and their code of judicial ethics. I am 
 interested in others thoughts on this.
 
 I would appreciate no ad hominem responses to these factual observations.
 
 Marci
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 
 
 
 On Dec 3, 2013, at 10:46 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
 
 Michael cites Warner v. Boca Raton, 887 So.2d 1023 (Fla. 2004), as an 
 example of a case where the word “substantially” was critical to the result. 
 And that is what the court says. But it is quite obviously not true.
  
 The Florida court read “substantially” to mean that only those practices 
 that were required by a faith were protected by Florida RFRA. The Florida 
 legislature had attempted to specifically negate any such requirement, as 
 the court recognized. The statute defined “exercise of religion” as “an act 
 or refusal to act that is substantially motivated by religious belief, 
 whether or not the religious exercise is compulsory or central to a larger 
 system of religious belief.” The Florida court’s interpretation of 
 “substantially burden” negated this definition and read back into the 
 statute a requirement that religious exercise be compulsory to be protected. 
 The statutory definition of religious exercise will never again matter to a 
 Florida RFRA case; only a subset of religious exercise as defined will ever 
 be protected. This opinion is plainly driven not by the word 
 “substantially,” but by the court’s disagreement with the scope of the 
 statute. Full disclosure: I argued the case for the plaintiffs.
  
 Here is what the court said about the statutory definition, just before it 
 turned to the meaning of “substantially burden”:
  
 “The FRFRA includes several important definitions:
  
 * * *
  
 (3) “Exercise of religion” means an act or refusal to act that is 
 substantially motivated by a religious belief, whether or not the religious 
 exercise is compulsory or central to a larger system of religious belief.
  
 § 761.02, Fla. Stat. (2003).
  
 * * * The protection afforded to the free exercise of religiously motivated 
 activity under the FRFRA is broader than that afforded by the decisions of 
 the United States Supreme Court for two interrelated reasons. First, the 
 FRFRA expands the free exercise right as construed by the Supreme Court in 
 Smith because it reinstates the Court's pre-Smith holdings by applying the 
 compelling interest test to neutral laws of general application. Second, 
 under the FRFRA the definition of protected “exercise of religion” subject 
 to 

Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

2013-12-03 Thread Marty Lederman
Eugene writes:  Even in the face of this caselaw, and the argument that
such preference for religion makes the statute unconstitutional, the Court
can’t read RFRA the same way [as courts have read the title VII and
conscientious objector statutes], but is instead compelled to read it in a
way that makes it unconstitutional?

No, the argument is not that the preference for religion makes it
unconstitutional -- Cutter already rejected that argument  -- but that if
RFRA were construed to allow religious accommodations *that imposed
significant burdens on third parties*, that would raise a serious
constitutional question.  Eugene, you're right that *expanding* RFRA to
include nonreligious objections would eliminate that particular
constitutional concern -- ironically, by expanding the harm to third
parties.  But for the reasons Chip has offered -- plus the glaring point
that the one thing everyone agrees on is that RFRA was intended to codify
the FEC doctrine of the Sherbert-through-Hernandez quarter-century, a
doctrine that did not recognize nonreligious claims for exemption -- that
reading of RFRA is fairly untenable (in contrast to the conscientious
objector and title VII accommodations) . . . and would, indeed, only
exacerbate the employee-burden problems.

The much, much more natural way to avoid the third-party burden
constitutional concerns is simply to construe RFRA to provide that avoiding
significant third-party harms is a compelling government interest, under
the terms of RFRA itself.  Indeed, doubly compelling -- the government has
an interest both on the merits in not denying this particular category of
women a social benefit to which virtually all other women are entitled, *and
*in avoiding serious EC concerns.


On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 11:22 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 So I take it the EEOC and the great majority of courts
 that have considered the meaning of “religion” in Title VII are wrong,
 too?  Here are the citations I had when I last researched the matter in
 1999:  Protos v. Volkswagen of Am., Inc., 797 F.2d 129, 137 n.4 (3d Cir.
 1986) (The breadth of the 'exemption' afforded by Title VII is underscored
 by the fact that in defining religion, the EEOC has used the same broad
 definition as the Selective Service employs for conscientious objector
 purposes.); Nottelson v. Smith Steel Workers, 643 F.2d 445, 454 n.12 (7th
 Cir. 1981) (noting the same broad definition); Redmond v. GAF Corp., 574
 F.2d 897, 901 n.12 (7th Cir. 1978) (We believe the proper test to be
 applied to the determination of what is 'religious' under § 2000e(j) can be
 derived from the Supreme Court decisions in [Welsh] and [United States v.
 Seeger, 380 U.S. 163 (1969)], i.e., (1) is the 'belief' for which
 protection is sought 'religious' in person's own scheme of things, and (2)
 is it 'sincerely held.'); Ali v. Southeast Neighborhood House, 519 F.
 Supp. 489, 490 (D.D.C. 1981) (Sincere beliefs, meaningful to the believer,
 need not be confined in either source or content to traditional or
 parochial concepts of religion. [Welsh.] See also [Seeger] for the
 definition of 'religious training and belief' as applied to a conscientious
 objector claim, which definition is no less appropriate here.); Wondzell
 v. Alaska Wood Prods., Inc., 583 P.2d 860, 866 n.12 (Alaska 1978) (In
 order to avoid the danger of unconstitutionality we would interpret [the
 state statute] to accord the same privileges to all sincere conscientious
 beliefs, whether or not they are accompanied by a belief in a supreme
 being.); Kolodziej v. Smith, 682 N.E.2d 604, 607 (Mass. 1997).



 Even in the face of this caselaw, and the argument that such preference
 for religion makes the statute unconstitutional, the Court can’t read RFRA
 the same way, but is instead compelled to read it in a way that makes it
 unconstitutional?



 Eugene



 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marci Hamilton
 *Sent:* Tuesday, December 03, 2013 8:14 AM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Cc:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

 *Subject:* Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions



 Chip has cut to the chase (thank you)



 i would add that Eugene's reasoning further underscores how RFRA is in
 fact a non-ratified amendment to the First Amendment, as the Court pointed
 out in a footnote in Boerne.   Advocates for it like Eugene cannot build in
 all the rules they like by borrowing from Supreme Court First Amendment
 doctrine but then say it is just a statute.As a statute, the plain
 language rule, the very title and the use of free exercise and the
 reference to religious cases means, yes, legislators are constrained to
 apply it only to religious believers.  If its application to only the
 religious makes it a violation of the Establishment Clause, we have a
 constitutional violation.


 Marci A. Hamilton

 Verkuil Chair in 

Re: Warner v. City of Boca Raton

2013-12-03 Thread Marc DeGirolami
I agree with these points. I would also add that there are many ambiguities and 
uncertainties in a test like that announced in Employment Division v. Smith, 
both because of the express carve-outs within Smith itself (whatever their 
motivation) and because of implicit questions about legislative intention that 
are features (not bugs) of many other laws. The ambiguities in putatively 
clear, bright line rules also at times have the effect of making one's 
perception of the rule-like quality of the rule outrun its reality.

Best wishes,

Marc

From: Paul Horwitz phorw...@hotmail.commailto:phorw...@hotmail.com
Reply-To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Date: Tuesday, December 3, 2013 11:38 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Warner v. City of Boca Raton

Hopefully this is not ad hominem! I don't see anything unique about this in 
RFRA. It is a standard concern with any legal test that involves the use of 
standards, balancing, and other questions of judicial application in the case. 
It is true of vast swaths of constitutional law and common law. See, e.g., 
Posner's discussion in Reflections on Judging of the difficulties of framing 
legal tests given the plasticity and imprecision of language. It is what leads 
some legal thinkers--but not Posner, in all cases--to favor the use of rules 
and formalism. But it's not unique to religion, religious freedom, or RFRA.

To this I would add that 1) rules and formalism front-load but do not eliminate 
the problem of judicial discretion; 2) although the problem Marci raises is 
quite genuine, not everyone agrees that eliminating balancing or judicial 
discretion root and branch are necessary and indefeasible elements of whatever 
the rule of law is; 3) whether rules or standards are preferable in 
particular areas is better analyzed, in my view, as a matter of pragmatic 
weighing and institutional analysis than by invoking the charged and protean 
terms of the rule of law; and 4) whether such decisions constitute a violation 
of the oath is contestable for similar reasons, and we're better off just 
asking whether particular decisions are right or wrong given the legal and 
factual materials in play. (Just as we would in asking whether, say, a court 
soundly decided a case involving a clear and present danger or proximate cause 
or reasonable person inquiry).

Regards,

Paul Horwitz

On Dec 3, 2013, at 10:13 AM, Marci Hamilton 
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com wrote:

I find it interesting that Doug concedes in this thread that results in RFRA 
cases turn on the judge's predilections on religious liberty regardless of the 
law's language.  I have witnessed this lack of neutrality in several cases, 
most notably the ruling by Judge Randa in the Milwaukee bankruptcy case.  (Full 
disclosure-- I represent the creditors' committee composed mostly of sex abuse 
victims in that case.)

RFRA seems to invite a lack of neutrality despite its language saying the 
Establishment Clause is to be unaffected.   The results as described by Doug 
and Chris strike me as involving judges who are being encouraged to and who do 
violate the Establishment Clause and their code of judicial ethics. I am 
interested in others thoughts on this.

I would appreciate no ad hominem responses to these factual observations.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton



On Dec 3, 2013, at 10:46 AM, Douglas Laycock 
dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:


Michael cites Warner v. Boca Raton, 887 So.2d 1023 (Fla. 2004), as an example 
of a case where the word “substantially” was critical to the result. And that 
is what the court says. But it is quite obviously not true.



The Florida court read “substantially” to mean that only those practices that 
were required by a faith were protected by Florida RFRA. The Florida 
legislature had attempted to specifically negate any such requirement, as the 
court recognized. The statute defined “exercise of religion” as “an act or 
refusal to act that is substantially motivated by religious belief, whether or 
not the religious exercise is compulsory or central to a larger system of 
religious belief.” The Florida court’s interpretation of “substantially burden” 
negated this definition and read back into the statute a requirement that 
religious exercise be compulsory to be protected. The statutory definition of 
religious exercise will never again matter to a Florida RFRA case; only a 
subset of religious exercise as defined will ever be protected. This opinion is 
plainly driven not by the word “substantially,” but by the court’s disagreement 
with the scope of the statute. Full disclosure: I argued the case for the 
plaintiffs.



Here is what the court said about the statutory definition, just before 

Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

2013-12-03 Thread James Oleske
Two additional thoughts:

1. While the Court certainly could take the approach Eugene suggests, does
anyone think the Court will do so? In light of the fact that the Court
recently and unanimously embraced the position in Hosanna-Tabor that
religion gets special treatment under the Constitution, and also
unanimously upheld RLUIPA against a facial challenge with the observation
that [r]eligious accommodations ... need not come packaged with benefits
to secular entities, I find it very difficult to imagine the Court now
interpreting the Religious Freedom Restoration Act as not providing
religion with special treatment. And I tend to doubt that the current Court
will be at all persuaded by a smattering of relatively old lower court
decisions relying upon the selective service cases to interpret Title VII.

2. As Marty notes, the argument that Fred and others are making is not that
preference for religion for religion makes the statute unconstitutional
in general, but rather, that specific applications of RFRA that impose
significant burdens on third parties may be unconstitutional. Cutter
explicitly contemplates such challenges under RLUIPA, and the Court gave no
indication that it would reinterpret RLUIPA in such cases to package
religious accommodations with secular accommodations in order to deflect as
applied challenges.

- Jim

On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 8:39 AM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.comwrote:

 Eugene writes:  Even in the face of this caselaw, and the argument that
 such preference for religion makes the statute unconstitutional, the Court
 can’t read RFRA the same way [as courts have read the title VII and
 conscientious objector statutes], but is instead compelled to read it in a
 way that makes it unconstitutional?

 No, the argument is not that the preference for religion makes it
 unconstitutional -- Cutter already rejected that argument  -- but that if
 RFRA were construed to allow religious accommodations *that imposed
 significant burdens on third parties*, that would raise a serious
 constitutional question.  Eugene, you're right that *expanding* RFRA to
 include nonreligious objections would eliminate that particular
 constitutional concern -- ironically, by expanding the harm to third
 parties.  But for the reasons Chip has offered -- plus the glaring point
 that the one thing everyone agrees on is that RFRA was intended to codify
 the FEC doctrine of the Sherbert-through-Hernandez quarter-century, a
 doctrine that did not recognize nonreligious claims for exemption -- that
 reading of RFRA is fairly untenable (in contrast to the conscientious
 objector and title VII accommodations) . . . and would, indeed, only
 exacerbate the employee-burden problems.

 The much, much more natural way to avoid the third-party burden
 constitutional concerns is simply to construe RFRA to provide that avoiding
 significant third-party harms is a compelling government interest, under
 the terms of RFRA itself.  Indeed, doubly compelling -- the government has
 an interest both on the merits in not denying this particular category of
 women a social benefit to which virtually all other women are entitled, *and
 *in avoiding serious EC concerns.


 On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 11:22 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.eduwrote:

 So I take it the EEOC and the great majority of courts
 that have considered the meaning of “religion” in Title VII are wrong,
 too?  Here are the citations I had when I last researched the matter in
 1999:  Protos v. Volkswagen of Am., Inc., 797 F.2d 129, 137 n.4 (3d Cir.
 1986) (The breadth of the 'exemption' afforded by Title VII is underscored
 by the fact that in defining religion, the EEOC has used the same broad
 definition as the Selective Service employs for conscientious objector
 purposes.); Nottelson v. Smith Steel Workers, 643 F.2d 445, 454 n.12 (7th
 Cir. 1981) (noting the same broad definition); Redmond v. GAF Corp., 574
 F.2d 897, 901 n.12 (7th Cir. 1978) (We believe the proper test to be
 applied to the determination of what is 'religious' under § 2000e(j) can be
 derived from the Supreme Court decisions in [Welsh] and [United States v.
 Seeger, 380 U.S. 163 (1969)], i.e., (1) is the 'belief' for which
 protection is sought 'religious' in person's own scheme of things, and (2)
 is it 'sincerely held.'); Ali v. Southeast Neighborhood House, 519 F.
 Supp. 489, 490 (D.D.C. 1981) (Sincere beliefs, meaningful to the believer,
 need not be confined in either source or content to traditional or
 parochial concepts of religion. [Welsh.] See also [Seeger] for the
 definition of 'religious training and belief' as applied to a conscientious
 objector claim, which definition is no less appropriate here.); Wondzell
 v. Alaska Wood Prods., Inc., 583 P.2d 860, 866 n.12 (Alaska 1978) (In
 order to avoid the danger of unconstitutionality we would interpret [the
 state statute] to accord the same privileges to all sincere conscientious
 beliefs, whether or not they 

RE: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

2013-12-03 Thread Alan Brownstein
Marty's post focuses the discussion particularly well here. However, if we 
construe RFRA to provide that avoiding significant third-party harms is a 
compelling state interest, we are still left with the least restrictive means 
part of rigorous review. How does the least restrictive means analysis fit into 
the picture of avoiding constitutional concerns?

In Catholic Charities v. Superior Court, the California Supreme Court  
addressed a similar issue to the contraceptive mandate question currently 
before the U.S. Supreme Court - but under California constitutional law. The 
Court rejected the idea that the government taking over the cost of providing 
benefits to employees of exempt organizations could be a less restrictive 
alternative. Indeed, it's language seemed to suggest that no less restrictive 
alternative would be accepted that required any expenditure of government funds.

Do list members agree with that analysis? If less restrictive alternatives 
(that is alternatives that are less burdensome to religious exercise) are 
available to the government but require the expenditure of funds, must that 
alternative be rejected out of hand as irrelevant to the application of strict 
scrutiny review? Does this analysis apply only to RFRA or to strict scrutiny 
review more generally?

Alan



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 8:40 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

Eugene writes:  Even in the face of this caselaw, and the argument that such 
preference for religion makes the statute unconstitutional, the Court can't 
read RFRA the same way [as courts have read the title VII and conscientious 
objector statutes], but is instead compelled to read it in a way that makes it 
unconstitutional?
No, the argument is not that the preference for religion makes it 
unconstitutional -- Cutter already rejected that argument  -- but that if RFRA 
were construed to allow religious accommodations that imposed significant 
burdens on third parties, that would raise a serious constitutional question.  
Eugene, you're right that expanding RFRA to include nonreligious objections 
would eliminate that particular constitutional concern -- ironically, by 
expanding the harm to third parties.  But for the reasons Chip has offered -- 
plus the glaring point that the one thing everyone agrees on is that RFRA was 
intended to codify the FEC doctrine of the Sherbert-through-Hernandez 
quarter-century, a doctrine that did not recognize nonreligious claims for 
exemption -- that reading of RFRA is fairly untenable (in contrast to the 
conscientious objector and title VII accommodations) . . . and would, indeed, 
only exacerbate the employee-burden problems.
The much, much more natural way to avoid the third-party burden constitutional 
concerns is simply to construe RFRA to provide that avoiding significant 
third-party harms is a compelling government interest, under the terms of RFRA 
itself.  Indeed, doubly compelling -- the government has an interest both on 
the merits in not denying this particular category of women a social benefit 
to which virtually all other women are entitled, and in avoiding serious EC 
concerns.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Warner v. City of Boca Raton

2013-12-03 Thread Michael Masinter
Like Doug, I think the Florida supreme court misconstrued FRFRA (more  
full disclosure -- I chaired the ACLUFL legal panel that authorized  
Jim Green and Doug to represent Warner on behalf of the ACLUFL).  But  
it remains the case that the court devoted several critical paragraphs  
of its opinion to the meaning of the word substantial, and relied on  
its definition of substantial to decide the case.


I offered Warner in response to a specific question -- whether any  
court had regarded the presence or absence of the word substantial in  
a state RFRA as significant -- not whether the court that did so  
construed it properly.  So it seems to me reasonable to suggest that  
the inclusion of the word substantial within the statutory text does  
do some work, even if, as happens here, we agree that Warner does not  
accurately capture the work that it does.


Perhaps substantial was meant only to invoke a sincerity inquiry into  
the objector's claim that the burden was substantial, but that still  
seems to effectively edit the word our of the statute. Construing the  
statute to leave the determination of what is substantial entirely to  
the subjective assessment of the objector, subject only to a sincerity  
determination, means that in every case in which the objector invokes  
a RFRA, the court must either find the objection insincere or apply  
strict scrutiny.  It would be easy enough to write such a statute, but  
why in writing it would one include the word substantial?


Mike


Michael R. Masinter  3305 College Avenue
Professor of Law Fort Lauderdale, FL 33314
Nova Southeastern University 954.262.6151 (voice)
masin...@nova.edu954.262.3835 (fax)



Quoting Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu:


Michael cites Warner v. Boca Raton, 887 So.2d 1023 (Fla. 2004), as an
example of a case where the word “substantially” was critical to the result.
And that is what the court says. But it is quite obviously not true.



The Florida court read “substantially” to mean that only those practices
that were required by a faith were protected by Florida RFRA. The Florida
legislature had attempted to specifically negate any such requirement, as
the court recognized. The statute defined “exercise of religion” as “an act
or refusal to act that is substantially motivated by religious belief,
whether or not the religious exercise is compulsory or central to a larger
system of religious belief.” The Florida court’s interpretation of
“substantially burden” negated this definition and read back into the
statute a requirement that religious exercise be compulsory to be protected.
The statutory definition of religious exercise will never again matter to a
Florida RFRA case; only a subset of religious exercise as defined will ever
be protected. This opinion is plainly driven not by the word
“substantially,” but by the court’s disagreement with the scope of the
statute. Full disclosure: I argued the case for the plaintiffs.



Here is what the court said about the statutory definition, just before it
turned to the meaning of “substantially burden”:



“The FRFRA includes several important definitions:



* * *



(3) “Exercise of religion” means an act or refusal to act that is
substantially motivated by a religious belief, whether or not the religious
exercise is compulsory or central to a larger system of religious belief.



§ 761.02, Fla. Stat. (2003).



* * * The protection afforded to the free exercise of religiously motivated
activity under the FRFRA is broader than that afforded by the decisions of
the United States Supreme Court for two interrelated reasons. First, the
FRFRA expands the free exercise right as construed by the Supreme Court in
Smith because it reinstates the Court's pre-Smith holdings by applying the
compelling interest test to neutral laws of general application. Second,
under the FRFRA the definition of protected “exercise of religion” subject
to the compelling state interest test includes any act or refusal to act
whether or not compelled by or central to a system of religious belief. The
legislative history of the FRFRA suggests that in order to state a claim
that the government has infringed upon the free exercise of religion, a
plaintiff must only establish that the government has placed a substantial
burden on a practice motivated by a sincere religious belief.”



887 So.2d at 1031-32 (emphasis in original).



Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546



-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Michael Masinter
Sent: Monday, December 02, 2013 8:44 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; Christopher Lund
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: 

Burdens on others -- compelling interest vs. Establishment Clause

2013-12-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I sympathize with the argument that there is a compelling 
government interest in preventing costs on third parties, and that this may 
justify rejecting the RFRA claim.  I think the doctrine here is especially 
uncertain, but there's much to be said for that argument as a reason for 
rejecting Hobby Lobby's claim.

But the Establishment Clause argument would go further.  Among 
other things, it would mean that the Administration's accommodation for 
religious nonprofits is itself unconstitutional.  (As I read Gedicks  Van 
Tassell, that is indeed their position.)  Do list members who embrace the 
Establishment Clause argument agree with that result?

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 8:40 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

Eugene writes:  Even in the face of this caselaw, and the argument that such 
preference for religion makes the statute unconstitutional, the Court can't 
read RFRA the same way [as courts have read the title VII and conscientious 
objector statutes], but is instead compelled to read it in a way that makes it 
unconstitutional?
No, the argument is not that the preference for religion makes it 
unconstitutional -- Cutter already rejected that argument  -- but that if RFRA 
were construed to allow religious accommodations that imposed significant 
burdens on third parties, that would raise a serious constitutional question.  
Eugene, you're right that expanding RFRA to include nonreligious objections 
would eliminate that particular constitutional concern -- ironically, by 
expanding the harm to third parties.  But for the reasons Chip has offered -- 
plus the glaring point that the one thing everyone agrees on is that RFRA was 
intended to codify the FEC doctrine of the Sherbert-through-Hernandez 
quarter-century, a doctrine that did not recognize nonreligious claims for 
exemption -- that reading of RFRA is fairly untenable (in contrast to the 
conscientious objector and title VII accommodations) . . . and would, indeed, 
only exacerbate the employee-burden problems.
The much, much more natural way to avoid the third-party burden constitutional 
concerns is simply to construe RFRA to provide that avoiding significant 
third-party harms is a compelling government interest, under the terms of RFRA 
itself.  Indeed, doubly compelling -- the government has an interest both on 
the merits in not denying this particular category of women a social benefit 
to which virtually all other women are entitled, and in avoiding serious EC 
concerns.

On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 11:22 AM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
So I take it the EEOC and the great majority of courts that 
have considered the meaning of religion in Title VII are wrong, too?  Here 
are the citations I had when I last researched the matter in 1999:  Protos v. 
Volkswagen of Am., Inc., 797 F.2d 129, 137 n.4 (3d Cir. 1986) (The breadth of 
the 'exemption' afforded by Title VII is underscored by the fact that in 
defining religion, the EEOC has used the same broad definition as the Selective 
Service employs for conscientious objector purposes.); Nottelson v. Smith 
Steel Workers, 643 F.2d 445, 454 n.12 (7th Cir. 1981) (noting the same broad 
definition); Redmond v. GAF Corp., 574 F.2d 897, 901 n.12 (7th Cir. 1978) (We 
believe the proper test to be applied to the determination of what is 
'religious' under § 2000e(j) can be derived from the Supreme Court decisions in 
[Welsh] and [United States v. Seeger, 380 U.S. 163 (1969)], i.e., (1) is the 
'belief' for which protection is sought 'religious' in person's own scheme of 
things, and (2) is it 'sincerely held.'); Ali v. Southeast Neighborhood House, 
519 F. Supp. 489, 490 (D.D.C. 1981) (Sincere beliefs, meaningful to the 
believer, need not be confined in either source or content to traditional or 
parochial concepts of religion. [Welsh.] See also [Seeger] for the definition 
of 'religious training and belief' as applied to a conscientious objector 
claim, which definition is no less appropriate here.); Wondzell v. Alaska Wood 
Prods., Inc., 583 P.2d 860, 866 n.12 (Alaska 1978) (In order to avoid the 
danger of unconstitutionality we would interpret [the state statute] to accord 
the same privileges to all sincere conscientious beliefs, whether or not they 
are accompanied by a belief in a supreme being.); Kolodziej v. Smith, 682 
N.E.2d 604, 607 (Mass. 1997).

Even in the face of this caselaw, and the argument that such preference for 
religion makes the statute unconstitutional, the Court can't read RFRA the same 
way, but is instead compelled to read it in a way that makes it 
unconstitutional?

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 

Re: Burdens on others -- compelling interest vs. Establishment Clause

2013-12-03 Thread Marty Lederman
Which HHS accommodation?  The first -- exempting churches altogether -- in
theory does not impose as much of a burden on their employees, because
those entities already have a right (under title VII) to prefer
coreligionists and insist that they comply with religious obligations --
that is to say, the employees there voluntarily took the jobs knowing
(probably intending) that they would have to abide by church tenets.

The second HHS accommodation, for other religious nonprofits, does not harm
the female employees, because they continue to receive cost-free
contraceptive coverage, albeit from the insurer rather than from the
employer.



On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 6:30 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 I sympathize with the argument that there is a compelling
 government interest in preventing costs on third parties, and that this may
 justify rejecting the RFRA claim.  I think the doctrine here is especially
 uncertain, but there’s much to be said for that argument as a reason for
 rejecting Hobby Lobby’s claim.



 But the Establishment Clause argument would go further.
 Among other things, it would mean that the Administration’s accommodation
 for religious nonprofits is itself unconstitutional.  (As I read Gedicks 
 Van Tassell, that is indeed their position.)  Do list members who embrace
 the Establishment Clause argument agree with that result?



 Eugene



 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marty Lederman
 *Sent:* Tuesday, December 03, 2013 8:40 AM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions



 Eugene writes:  Even in the face of this caselaw, and the argument that
 such preference for religion makes the statute unconstitutional, the Court
 can’t read RFRA the same way [as courts have read the title VII and
 conscientious objector statutes], but is instead compelled to read it in a
 way that makes it unconstitutional?

 No, the argument is not that the preference for religion makes it
 unconstitutional -- Cutter already rejected that argument  -- but that if
 RFRA were construed to allow religious accommodations *that imposed
 significant burdens on third parties*, that would raise a serious
 constitutional question.  Eugene, you're right that *expanding* RFRA to
 include nonreligious objections would eliminate that particular
 constitutional concern -- ironically, by expanding the harm to third
 parties.  But for the reasons Chip has offered -- plus the glaring point
 that the one thing everyone agrees on is that RFRA was intended to codify
 the FEC doctrine of the Sherbert-through-Hernandez quarter-century, a
 doctrine that did not recognize nonreligious claims for exemption -- that
 reading of RFRA is fairly untenable (in contrast to the conscientious
 objector and title VII accommodations) . . . and would, indeed, only
 exacerbate the employee-burden problems.

 The much, much more natural way to avoid the third-party burden
 constitutional concerns is simply to construe RFRA to provide that avoiding
 significant third-party harms is a compelling government interest, under
 the terms of RFRA itself.  Indeed, doubly compelling -- the government has
 an interest both on the merits in not denying this particular category of
 women a social benefit to which virtually all other women are entitled, *and
 *in avoiding serious EC concerns.



 On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 11:22 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu
 wrote:

 So I take it the EEOC and the great majority of courts
 that have considered the meaning of “religion” in Title VII are wrong,
 too?  Here are the citations I had when I last researched the matter in
 1999:  Protos v. Volkswagen of Am., Inc., 797 F.2d 129, 137 n.4 (3d Cir.
 1986) (The breadth of the 'exemption' afforded by Title VII is underscored
 by the fact that in defining religion, the EEOC has used the same broad
 definition as the Selective Service employs for conscientious objector
 purposes.); Nottelson v. Smith Steel Workers, 643 F.2d 445, 454 n.12 (7th
 Cir. 1981) (noting the same broad definition); Redmond v. GAF Corp., 574
 F.2d 897, 901 n.12 (7th Cir. 1978) (We believe the proper test to be
 applied to the determination of what is 'religious' under § 2000e(j) can be
 derived from the Supreme Court decisions in [Welsh] and [United States v.
 Seeger, 380 U.S. 163 (1969)], i.e., (1) is the 'belief' for which
 protection is sought 'religious' in person's own scheme of things, and (2)
 is it 'sincerely held.'); Ali v. Southeast Neighborhood House, 519 F.
 Supp. 489, 490 (D.D.C. 1981) (Sincere beliefs, meaningful to the believer,
 need not be confined in either source or content to traditional or
 parochial concepts of religion. [Welsh.] See also [Seeger] for the
 definition of 'religious training and belief' as applied to a conscientious
 objector claim, which 

The employer mandate and the draft

2013-12-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I read the Gedicks  Van Tassell article, which I found 
interesting but ultimately not quite persuasive as to the draft.

According to 
http://www.swarthmore.edu/library/peace/conscientiousobjection/co%20website/pages/HistoryNew.htm,
 there were 170,000 conscientious objector deferments awarded during the 
Vietnam War.  That means that likely about 170,000 people who otherwise 
wouldn't have been called up were indeed eligible to be called up instead, and 
presumably (I don't quite know how the numbers worked) at least tens of 
thousands of those were indeed called up.  That surely was a burden on third 
parties created as a result of accommodating objectors' religious beliefs.

To be sure, at the time the conscientious objector deferment was given, the 
particular person who had to serve in the objectors' place couldn't be easily 
identified.  And I agree that the law does sometimes treat burdens on easily 
identifiable third parties differently from burdens on harder-to-identify third 
parties.

But is such a distinction really mandated by the Establishment 
Clause?  Is it really the case that the government is free to impose such a 
massive burden -- conscription for years, the possibility of having to kill, 
and the possibility of dying -- on hard-to-identify but indubitably real third 
parties (tens of thousands of them), but the Establishment Clause blocks the 
government from imposing a several-hundred-dollar-per-year burden on more 
readily identifiable employees?  That seems quite odd.

Nor does the distinction urged by Gedicks  Van Tassell -- that 
the draft exemption wouldn't be a factor in the decision of nonpacifists to 
comply with or evade the draft, while the employer mandate exemption might be 
a factor in a person's decision whether to work for Hobby Lobby -- strike me as 
constitutionally significant, especially when the question is substantiality of 
burden.  Perhaps nonpacifists had to comply with the draft in any event, 
because they'd go to prison otherwise.  But if the essence of the harm is 
burdening non-beneficiar[ies], that legal compulsion doesn't at all diminish 
the burden on the tens of thousands of nonpacifists who had to serve in the 
conscientious objectors' stead.

I realize that there's a separate argument that the 
conscientious objector exemption was only upheld because it was interpreted to 
cover philosophical objectors, and that such an interpretation is unavailable 
for the employer mandate (though I'm still not persuaded by that interpretation 
argument).  But my point here is simply that the burden on the hard-to-identify 
vs. burden on the easy-to-identify distinction, as well as the Gedicks  Van 
Tassell distinction, seem unsound.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Micah Schwartzman
Sent: Monday, December 02, 2013 12:38 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The Establishment Clause, burden on others, the employer mandate, 
and the draft

Alan,

I think you're right that the problem of burdening non-beneficiary employees 
could be resolved by the government providing them with full coverage (as I 
think Nelson Tebbe said in an earlier post). But until that happens, those 
employees have a claim in this litigation that hasn't yet been fully presented 
-- and one that, as Gedicks argues, constrains permissive accommodations 
(including RFRA).

I should add that government coverage for non-beneficiaries might not solve all 
the possible Establishment Clause problems with a religious exemption. If there 
are non-religious employers who object to covering, e.g., abortifacients, they 
might claim that a religious exemption treats them unfairly. And depending on 
how the costs sort out, I suppose it's possible that there might be complaints 
from non-exempted employers (as in Texas Monthly).

Micah

On Dec 2, 2013, at 2:49 PM, Alan Brownstein wrote:


Micah, if the issue is diffusing the burden so that it doesn't fall on a 
limited class of identifiable individuals, why isn't that problem solved by the 
government taking over the task of providing insurance coverage for the 
employees of exempt organizations. Isn't the government a sufficiently 
effective cost-spreader to resolve this concern?


Alan


Eugene's suggestion that the religious exemption from the contraception mandate 
be analogized to the draft protester cases is anticipated by Gedicks and Van 
Tassell in their article, RFRA Exemptions from the Contraception Mandate:  An 
Unconstitutional Accommodation of Religion 
(http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2328516).

Gedicks and Van Tassel argue that the burden of the exemption is not material 
because it would not affect the decision-making of non-pacificists in 
considering whether to participate in the draft. That is because the burden is 
minor and 

RE: Burdens on others -- compelling interest vs. Establishment Clause

2013-12-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Sorry, I should have limited this to churches, many of whom do 
not actually prefer coreligionists, even if Title VII lets them do so.  (I 
erred in saying that Gedicks  Van Tassell would hold this unconstitutional.)

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 3:44 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Burdens on others -- compelling interest vs. Establishment Clause

Which HHS accommodation?  The first -- exempting churches altogether -- in 
theory does not impose as much of a burden on their employees, because those 
entities already have a right (under title VII) to prefer coreligionists and 
insist that they comply with religious obligations -- that is to say, the 
employees there voluntarily took the jobs knowing (probably intending) that 
they would have to abide by church tenets.
The second HHS accommodation, for other religious nonprofits, does not harm the 
female employees, because they continue to receive cost-free contraceptive 
coverage, albeit from the insurer rather than from the employer.

On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 6:30 PM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
I sympathize with the argument that there is a compelling 
government interest in preventing costs on third parties, and that this may 
justify rejecting the RFRA claim.  I think the doctrine here is especially 
uncertain, but there's much to be said for that argument as a reason for 
rejecting Hobby Lobby's claim.

But the Establishment Clause argument would go further.  Among 
other things, it would mean that the Administration's accommodation for 
religious nonprofits is itself unconstitutional.  (As I read Gedicks  Van 
Tassell, that is indeed their position.)  Do list members who embrace the 
Establishment Clause argument agree with that result?

Eugene

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 8:40 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

Eugene writes:  Even in the face of this caselaw, and the argument that such 
preference for religion makes the statute unconstitutional, the Court can't 
read RFRA the same way [as courts have read the title VII and conscientious 
objector statutes], but is instead compelled to read it in a way that makes it 
unconstitutional?
No, the argument is not that the preference for religion makes it 
unconstitutional -- Cutter already rejected that argument  -- but that if RFRA 
were construed to allow religious accommodations that imposed significant 
burdens on third parties, that would raise a serious constitutional question.  
Eugene, you're right that expanding RFRA to include nonreligious objections 
would eliminate that particular constitutional concern -- ironically, by 
expanding the harm to third parties.  But for the reasons Chip has offered -- 
plus the glaring point that the one thing everyone agrees on is that RFRA was 
intended to codify the FEC doctrine of the Sherbert-through-Hernandez 
quarter-century, a doctrine that did not recognize nonreligious claims for 
exemption -- that reading of RFRA is fairly untenable (in contrast to the 
conscientious objector and title VII accommodations) . . . and would, indeed, 
only exacerbate the employee-burden problems.
The much, much more natural way to avoid the third-party burden constitutional 
concerns is simply to construe RFRA to provide that avoiding significant 
third-party harms is a compelling government interest, under the terms of RFRA 
itself.  Indeed, doubly compelling -- the government has an interest both on 
the merits in not denying this particular category of women a social benefit 
to which virtually all other women are entitled, and in avoiding serious EC 
concerns.

On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 11:22 AM, Volokh, Eugene 
vol...@law.ucla.edumailto:vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
So I take it the EEOC and the great majority of courts that 
have considered the meaning of religion in Title VII are wrong, too?  Here 
are the citations I had when I last researched the matter in 1999:  Protos v. 
Volkswagen of Am., Inc., 797 F.2d 129, 137 n.4 (3d Cir. 1986) (The breadth of 
the 'exemption' afforded by Title VII is underscored by the fact that in 
defining religion, the EEOC has used the same broad definition as the Selective 
Service employs for conscientious objector purposes.); Nottelson v. Smith 
Steel Workers, 643 F.2d 445, 454 n.12 (7th Cir. 1981) (noting the same broad 
definition); Redmond v. GAF Corp., 574 F.2d 897, 901 n.12 (7th Cir. 1978) (We 
believe the proper test to be applied to the determination of what is 

Rights to injure others

2013-12-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
My apologies for the delay responding to Alan’s point.  Alan 
raises an excellent argument, but my tentative thinking is that the force of 
the assault/theft hypotheticals stems precisely from the fact that they involve 
injury to long-recognized common-law private rights.  I’m not sure even that 
should make such hypotheticals into violations of the Establishment Clause, but 
if it does, I think it’s the longstanding tradition of legally protecting the 
rights -- even if the police don’t always enforce the law -- that is doing the 
work.

Indeed, I expect that the same would apply if the law allowed 
people to commandeer third parties’ property without compensation, and outside 
the traditional limitations on property rights.  (I recall Alan’s excellent 
Property Rights Genie article, which suggested that such laws may indeed be 
unconstitutional deprivations of property.)  Laws allowing people to assault 
third parties outside the traditional situations (such as self-defense) would, 
I think, be shocking regardless of whether the assaults were religiously 
motivated; it’s hard to point to specific cases considering this, though, since 
such laws are fortunately so rare.  (The closest analogy I could think was 
spousal rape laws, which were in some cases struck down even despite their 
history, though that is clouded by the Equal Protection Clause sex 
discrimination issue.)

In any case, I just thought I owed Alan an answer to his post.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
Sent: Wednesday, November 27, 2013 11:38 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Contraception Mandate

I have a lot of trouble with the argument that religious accommodations that 
effectively deny third parties government-mandated benefits to which they are 
otherwise entitled are not subject to Establishment Clause review. It is true 
that the government doesn’t have to protect anyone against employment 
discrimination and can decide how far it wants to extend such protection. It is 
also true that the government isn’t required to protect all people all the time 
against crimes like assault and battery (See Deshaney) or torts like conversion 
(See Flagg Brothers). But surely an exemption that allows religious individuals 
to assault third parties or commandeer their property violates the 
Establishment Clause.

I agree that the accommodation upheld in Amos burdened the employee who lost 
his job. I think the Court’s cases recognizing some Establishment Clause limit 
on accommodations involve some implied balancing. Implied balancing is 
necessary to determine whether an accommodation goes too far in burdening third 
parties and whether the accommodation does not impermissibly favor certain 
faiths over others. That’s one of the reasons I think Smith is unpersuasive 
when it rejects free exercise claims against neutral laws of general 
applicability in order to avoid subjective judicial balancing. When the job of 
granting accommodations is assigned to the legislature, court’s will have to 
engage in the same kind of balancing that they avoid in Free Exercise cases 
under Smith when they adjudicate Establishment Clause challenges to the 
accommodation because it allegedly impermissibly burdens third parties or 
favors certain religions over others.

Alan

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Tuesday, November 26, 2013 9:43 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Contraception Mandate

I do indeed think so.  The government doesn’t have to extend a 
government-mandated benefit to everyone; Title VII protections, for instance, 
aren’t extended to employees of small businesses, and are otherwise limited in 
various ways.  Indeed, a law can’t discriminate based on a beneficiary’s 
religion in extending such a benefit (except perhaps when the benefit is itself 
a religious accommodation).  But I don’t think that there should be an 
Establishment Clause  problem with a law saying that, for instance, those 
tenants who want to rent from religious objector landlords don’t get the 
protections of marital status discrimination law, those employees who work for 
religious vegetarian landlords don’t get the protections of the meaty lunch 
program, or those employees who work for employers who object to paying for 
contraceptives or abortifacents don’t get the protections of the relevant 
health care insurance program.

As to Cutter, the only way I can see of reconciling it with 
Amos is by not reading Thornton too broadly.  The accommodation in Amos did 
not, after all, at all “take adequate account of the burdens a requested 
accommodation may impose on nonbeneficiaries,” if “burdens” is viewed as 

Re: The Establishment Clause, burden on others, the employer mandate, and the draft

2013-12-03 Thread Micah Schwartzman
Alan,

Thanks for this response, and sorry for not replying sooner. I have been 
thinking about it since yesterday. If I understand correctly (and I'm not sure 
about this), you're saying that the government would violate RFRA if it did not 
act to avoid an as-applied Establishment Clause challenge by providing coverage 
to non-beneficiaries. 

But it is hard for me to see the Establishment Clause violation as stemming 
from anything other than RFRA. Providing a contraception mandate without 
government coverage for employees does not lead to a constitutional violation. 
Only if RFRA is construed to require a religious exemption do we reach the 
constitutional problem. 

As Marty suggested earlier today, one way to avoid that problem is by 
incorporating Establishment Clause concerns into the compelling interest 
analysis. But even if we don't do that, I don't think that government actions 
that fail to avoid potential Establishment Clause harms are themselves 
violations of RFRA. In Hobby Lobby, RFRA does not require the government to 
respond to a constitutional defect by compensating the non-beneficiaries.

Consider an example:  Suppose that the religious employers win their suit in 
Hobby Lobby. They get a religious exemption under RFRA from the contraception 
mandate. Suppose further (following Eugene's recent argument) that some 
non-religious employers seek a comparable exemption -- say, because they have 
moral objections to facilitating the use of abortifacients. These non-religious 
employers claim that RFRA violates the Establishment Clause because it provides 
exemptions to religious employers but not to them. Suppose for the sake of 
argument that a court agrees (perhaps following Justice Harlan's view in 
Welsh). Now the government has a choice:  either eliminate the exemption or 
broaden it to include non-religious objectors. 

If I understand your view correctly, the government would have to expand the 
exemption. If it eliminated the exemption, it would burden religious believers 
in violation of RFRA. The upshot is that it would be a violation of RFRA to 
read RFRA in a way that excludes non-religious claims. And that seems like a 
strange outcome. 

I don't think we have to read RFRA to demand this kind of recursivity -- either 
in my example or in other cases (say, in Caldor). As Cutter recognizes, the 
Establishment Clause imposes limits, and those limits can be incorporated into 
RFRA through compelling interest analysis. But even if they are not (as 
apparently is the case in the Hobby Lobby litigation), the government can 
respect those limits as independent grounds for rejecting harms to 
non-beneficiaries. 

Micah
 
On Dec 2, 2013, at 4:48 PM, Alan Brownstein aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu wrote:

 Micah,
  
 I guess the question for me is whether the fact that the government has not 
 offered to provide coverage to the employees of exempt organizations 
 constrains permissive accommodations under a statute like RFRA. If the 
 provision of coverage to the employees of exempt organizations is a less 
 restrictive alternative  that adequately furthers the government’s asserted 
 compelling interests, why doesn’t that lead to the conclusion that the 
 government has violated RFRA. Or to put it another way, why should the 
 government’s failure to adopt a less restrictive alternative be the basis for 
 denying the religious objector’s claim under RFRA?
  
 If we apply strict scrutiny in a free speech case and the government’s 
 compelling state interest is to avoid unruly behavior by the audience if an 
 unpopular speaker is permitted to speak, the government can’t fortify its 
 argument by refusing to provide adequate police to preserve order during the 
 event. Government providing police to preserve order is a less burdensome 
 alternative than silencing the speaker whether the government actually 
 provides police services or not.
  
 I assume one response to this argument would be that the Establishment Clause 
 prohibits the burdening of third parties – but that leads to the question of 
 which government action violates the Establishment Clause. Should we view the 
 government’s compliance with RFRA as the Establishment Clause violation or 
 the government’s imposition of the mandate (which created a duty to exempt 
 religious objectors under existing law – e.g.  RFRA) without providing for 
 coverage of employees working for exempt organizations as the problem. (This 
 last argument is very tentative. I just thought of it and will withdraw it if 
 it makes no sense.)
  
 Alan
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Micah Schwartzman
 Sent: Monday, December 02, 2013 12:38 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: The Establishment Clause, burden on others, the employer 
 mandate, and the draft
  
 Alan, 
  
 I think you're right that the problem of burdening non-beneficiary employees 
 could be 

Re: Warner v. City of Boca Raton

2013-12-03 Thread Douglas Laycock
I don't think that substantial burden merely means sincerity. As I said, I 
think that burden and compelling interest inevitably become a balancing test, 
so that the degree of substantiality matters whether the statute says so or 
not. 

I did mean to say that the Florida court's interpretation is so implausible 
that I cannot believe the word substantially -- or any other part of the 
statutory text -- did the work. I think that the decision could only have 
resulted from hostility to the statute as drafted, and that substantially was 
just the most convenient word to seize upon. 

Had it been omitted, they would have found another way. The way they found made 
no textual sense, and any alternative would not have had to make textual sense 
either.

On Tue, 03 Dec 2013 13:27:07 -0500
 Michael Masinter masin...@nova.edu wrote:
Like Doug, I think the Florida supreme court misconstrued FRFRA (more full 
disclosure -- I chaired the ACLUFL legal panel that authorized Jim Green and 
Doug to represent Warner on behalf of the ACLUFL).  But it remains the case 
that the court devoted several critical paragraphs of its opinion to the 
meaning of the word substantial, and relied on its definition of substantial 
to decide the case.

I offered Warner in response to a specific question -- whether any court had 
regarded the presence or absence of the word substantial in a state RFRA as 
significant -- not whether the court that did so construed it properly.  So it 
seems to me reasonable to suggest that the inclusion of the word substantial 
within the statutory text does do some work, even if, as happens here, we 
agree that Warner does not accurately capture the work that it does.

Perhaps substantial was meant only to invoke a sincerity inquiry into the 
objector's claim that the burden was substantial, but that still seems to 
effectively edit the word our of the statute. Construing the statute to leave 
the determination of what is substantial entirely to the subjective assessment 
of the objector, subject only to a sincerity determination, means that in 
every case in which the objector invokes a RFRA, the court must either find 
the objection insincere or apply strict scrutiny.  It would be easy enough to 
write such a statute, but why in writing it would one include the word 
substantial?

Mike


Michael R. Masinter  3305 College Avenue
Professor of Law Fort Lauderdale, FL 33314
Nova Southeastern University 954.262.6151 (voice)
masin...@nova.edu954.262.3835 (fax)



Quoting Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu:

 Michael cites Warner v. Boca Raton, 887 So.2d 1023 (Fla. 2004), as an
 example of a case where the word “substantially” was critical to the result.
 And that is what the court says. But it is quite obviously not true.



 The Florida court read “substantially” to mean that only those practices
 that were required by a faith were protected by Florida RFRA. The Florida
 legislature had attempted to specifically negate any such requirement, as
 the court recognized. The statute defined “exercise of religion” as “an act
 or refusal to act that is substantially motivated by religious belief,
 whether or not the religious exercise is compulsory or central to a larger
 system of religious belief.” The Florida court’s interpretation of
 “substantially burden” negated this definition and read back into the
 statute a requirement that religious exercise be compulsory to be protected.
 The statutory definition of religious exercise will never again matter to a
 Florida RFRA case; only a subset of religious exercise as defined will ever
 be protected. This opinion is plainly driven not by the word
 “substantially,” but by the court’s disagreement with the scope of the
 statute. Full disclosure: I argued the case for the plaintiffs.



 Here is what the court said about the statutory definition, just before it
 turned to the meaning of “substantially burden”:



 “The FRFRA includes several important definitions:



 * * *



 (3) “Exercise of religion” means an act or refusal to act that is
 substantially motivated by a religious belief, whether or not the religious
 exercise is compulsory or central to a larger system of religious belief.



 § 761.02, Fla. Stat. (2003).



 * * * The protection afforded to the free exercise of religiously motivated
 activity under the FRFRA is broader than that afforded by the decisions of
 the United States Supreme Court for two interrelated reasons. First, the
 FRFRA expands the free exercise right as construed by the Supreme Court in
 Smith because it reinstates the Court's pre-Smith holdings by applying the
 compelling interest test to neutral laws of general application. Second,
 under the FRFRA the definition of protected “exercise of religion” subject
 to the compelling state interest test includes any act or refusal to act
 whether or not compelled by or central to a system of religious 

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-03 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
This is an excellent hypothetical.  My own inclination is that the only 
justification for a clergy-penitent privilege is a) if there is a duty to 
confess to a member of the clergy; and b) if the clergy in question believes 
that God will punish disclosure of the confession.  (It shouldn't be enough 
that the doctrine of the religion prevents disclosure unless divine punishment 
is thought to attend it.)   I have argued for some years that the only defense 
of religious privileges is the belief on the part of the claimant that 
commission of the act in question will generate divine sanctions.  This is 
probably too strict, since I (still) support the critique of Smith, and I have 
no reason to believe that the ingestion of peyote was a divine command 
violation of which would generate some kind of punishment (including punishment 
in the world to come).  But Eugene's hypo makes very real the costs to innocent 
third parties of treating any and all members of the clergy differently from 
one's best friends, fellow family members, or even, in most courts, reporters.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics (religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu)
Subject: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

One more question about the unconstitutional burdens on third 
parties theory:  The clergy-penitent privilege allows the clergy (and 
penitents) to refuse to testify about penitential communications, even when the 
result is that a litigant is deprived of potentially highly probative evidence.

What's more, this is a specifically identifiable litigant who is being denied 
the benefit of applying the normal duty to testify.  And, unlike with the 
conscientious objector exemption, the clergy-penitent exemption is indeed 
limited to religious communications, with no secular philosophical analog.  
(The psychotherapist-patient privilege, I think, is quite different, partly 
because it requires communications to someone who is licensed by the state, 
requires a state-prescribed course of training, and is usually quite expensive, 
and partly because it tends to have fewer exceptions.)

Say, then, there are two people.  Anita works for an employer who (by 
hypothesis) has been exempted from the usually applicable (with some secular 
exemptions) employer mandate as a result of a statutory religious objector 
exemption.  As a result, she doesn't get, say, $500/year worth of contraceptive 
benefits that she would have been legally entitled to but for the employer 
mandate.

Barbara is suing Don Defendant for $500,000.  She has reason to think that Don 
has confessed to Carl Clergyman that Don is indeed liable, so she wants Carl to 
be ordered to testify about the communication.  But Carl has been exempted from 
the usually applicable (with some secular exemptions) duty to testify as a 
result of a statutory clergy-congregant privilege.  As a result, she doesn't 
win the $500,000 that she would have been legally entitled to but for the 
clergy-congregant privilege.

Is the application of the clergy-congregant exemption from the duty to testify 
in Barbara's case an Establishment Clause violation, on the grounds that it 
imposes an excessive burden on Barbara?  And if it isn't, then why would the 
application of the hypothetical exemption from the employer mandate an 
Establishment Clause violation in Anita's case?

Eugene
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-03 Thread Douglas Laycock
Eugene's hypothetical presumably describes some of the cases, from the least 
sophisticated or most desperate penitents. But it probably doesn't describe 
very many; most penitents rely on the privilege, and few would confess to their 
priest if priests were routinely testifying against folks who confessed. The 
word would obviously get around to perps that this is what priests do when you 
confess.

So the plaintiff in Eugene's lawsuit really hasn't lost anything; the privilege 
deprives her only of evidence that would not exist but for the privilege. 

Meanwhile, the priest does some good, in at least some of the cases, toward 
encouraging reform or even restitution. In the original American case on the 
privilege, the priest had recovered the stolen goods and returned them to the 
owner. 

On Wed, 4 Dec 2013 02:37:42 +
 Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
This is an excellent hypothetical.  My own inclination is that the only 
justification for a clergy-penitent privilege is a) if there is a duty to 
confess to a member of the clergy; and b) if the clergy in question believes 
that God will punish disclosure of the confession.  (It shouldn't be enough 
that the doctrine of the religion prevents disclosure unless divine punishment 
is thought to attend it.)   I have argued for some years that the only defense 
of religious privileges is the belief on the part of the claimant that 
commission of the act in question will generate divine sanctions.  This is 
probably too strict, since I (still) support the critique of Smith, and I have 
no reason to believe that the ingestion of peyote was a divine command 
violation of which would generate some kind of punishment (including 
punishment in the world to come).  But Eugene's hypo makes very real the costs 
to innocent third parties of treating any and all members of the clergy 
differently from
  one's
best friends, fellow family members, or even, in most courts, reporters.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics (religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu)
Subject: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

One more question about the unconstitutional burdens on third 
 parties theory:  The clergy-penitent privilege allows the clergy (and 
 penitents) to refuse to testify about penitential communications, even when 
 the result is that a litigant is deprived of potentially highly probative 
 evidence.

What's more, this is a specifically identifiable litigant who is being denied 
the benefit of applying the normal duty to testify.  And, unlike with the 
conscientious objector exemption, the clergy-penitent exemption is indeed 
limited to religious communications, with no secular philosophical analog.  
(The psychotherapist-patient privilege, I think, is quite different, partly 
because it requires communications to someone who is licensed by the state, 
requires a state-prescribed course of training, and is usually quite 
expensive, and partly because it tends to have fewer exceptions.)

Say, then, there are two people.  Anita works for an employer who (by 
hypothesis) has been exempted from the usually applicable (with some secular 
exemptions) employer mandate as a result of a statutory religious objector 
exemption.  As a result, she doesn't get, say, $500/year worth of 
contraceptive benefits that she would have been legally entitled to but for 
the employer mandate.

Barbara is suing Don Defendant for $500,000.  She has reason to think that Don 
has confessed to Carl Clergyman that Don is indeed liable, so she wants Carl 
to be ordered to testify about the communication.  But Carl has been exempted 
from the usually applicable (with some secular exemptions) duty to testify as 
a result of a statutory clergy-congregant privilege.  As a result, she doesn't 
win the $500,000 that she would have been legally entitled to but for the 
clergy-congregant privilege.

Is the application of the clergy-congregant exemption from the duty to testify 
in Barbara's case an Establishment Clause violation, on the grounds that it 
imposes an excessive burden on Barbara?  And if it isn't, then why would the 
application of the hypothetical exemption from the employer mandate an 
Establishment Clause violation in Anita's case?

Eugene

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read 

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-03 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
I strongly suspect that Doug is right.  Still, I do wonder how often cases do 
arise beyond the Catholic Church (which probably fulfills my conditions for the 
privilege).

sandy

-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock [mailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu] 
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 10:06 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; Levinson, Sanford V
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

Eugene's hypothetical presumably describes some of the cases, from the least 
sophisticated or most desperate penitents. But it probably doesn't describe 
very many; most penitents rely on the privilege, and few would confess to their 
priest if priests were routinely testifying against folks who confessed. The 
word would obviously get around to perps that this is what priests do when you 
confess.

So the plaintiff in Eugene's lawsuit really hasn't lost anything; the privilege 
deprives her only of evidence that would not exist but for the privilege. 

Meanwhile, the priest does some good, in at least some of the cases, toward 
encouraging reform or even restitution. In the original American case on the 
privilege, the priest had recovered the stolen goods and returned them to the 
owner. 

On Wed, 4 Dec 2013 02:37:42 +
 Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
This is an excellent hypothetical.  My own inclination is that the only 
justification for a clergy-penitent privilege is a) if there is a duty to 
confess to a member of the clergy; and b) if the clergy in question believes 
that God will punish disclosure of the confession.  (It shouldn't be enough 
that the doctrine of the religion prevents disclosure unless divine punishment 
is thought to attend it.)   I have argued for some years that the only defense 
of religious privileges is the belief on the part of the claimant that 
commission of the act in question will generate divine sanctions.  This is 
probably too strict, since I (still) support the critique of Smith, and I have 
no reason to believe that the ingestion of peyote was a divine command 
violation of which would generate some kind of punishment (including 
punishment in the world to come).  But Eugene's hypo makes very real the costs 
to innocent third parties of treating any and all members of the clergy 
differently from
  one's
best friends, fellow family members, or even, in most courts, reporters.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
(religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu)
Subject: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

One more question about the unconstitutional burdens on third 
 parties theory:  The clergy-penitent privilege allows the clergy (and 
 penitents) to refuse to testify about penitential communications, even when 
 the result is that a litigant is deprived of potentially highly probative 
 evidence.

What's more, this is a specifically identifiable litigant who is being 
denied the benefit of applying the normal duty to testify.  And, unlike 
with the conscientious objector exemption, the clergy-penitent 
exemption is indeed limited to religious communications, with no 
secular philosophical analog.  (The psychotherapist-patient privilege, 
I think, is quite different, partly because it requires communications 
to someone who is licensed by the state, requires a state-prescribed 
course of training, and is usually quite expensive, and partly because 
it tends to have fewer exceptions.)

Say, then, there are two people.  Anita works for an employer who (by 
hypothesis) has been exempted from the usually applicable (with some secular 
exemptions) employer mandate as a result of a statutory religious objector 
exemption.  As a result, she doesn't get, say, $500/year worth of 
contraceptive benefits that she would have been legally entitled to but for 
the employer mandate.

Barbara is suing Don Defendant for $500,000.  She has reason to think that Don 
has confessed to Carl Clergyman that Don is indeed liable, so she wants Carl 
to be ordered to testify about the communication.  But Carl has been exempted 
from the usually applicable (with some secular exemptions) duty to testify as 
a result of a statutory clergy-congregant privilege.  As a result, she doesn't 
win the $500,000 that she would have been legally entitled to but for the 
clergy-congregant privilege.

Is the application of the clergy-congregant exemption from the duty to testify 
in Barbara's case an Establishment Clause violation, on the grounds that it 
imposes an excessive burden on Barbara?  And if it isn't, then why would the 
application of the hypothetical exemption from the employer mandate an 
Establishment Clause violation in Anita's case?

Eugene

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law University of Virginia Law School
580 

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-03 Thread Ira Lupu
And the clergy-penitent privilege is one of many such privileges --
doctor-patient, lawyer-client, spousal privilege, etc.  They are designed
to encourage communication within relationships the law values.  So this
example is like Walz -- it does not involve special treatment for religion.
 It is that kind of special treatment that triggers the concern for third
party harms (Estate of Thornton v. Caldor).


On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 10:05 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 Eugene's hypothetical presumably describes some of the cases, from the
 least sophisticated or most desperate penitents. But it probably doesn't
 describe very many; most penitents rely on the privilege, and few would
 confess to their priest if priests were routinely testifying against folks
 who confessed. The word would obviously get around to perps that this is
 what priests do when you confess.

 So the plaintiff in Eugene's lawsuit really hasn't lost anything; the
 privilege deprives her only of evidence that would not exist but for the
 privilege.

 Meanwhile, the priest does some good, in at least some of the cases,
 toward encouraging reform or even restitution. In the original American
 case on the privilege, the priest had recovered the stolen goods and
 returned them to the owner.

 On Wed, 4 Dec 2013 02:37:42 +
  Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
 This is an excellent hypothetical.  My own inclination is that the only
 justification for a clergy-penitent privilege is a) if there is a duty to
 confess to a member of the clergy; and b) if the clergy in question
 believes that God will punish disclosure of the confession.  (It shouldn't
 be enough that the doctrine of the religion prevents disclosure unless
 divine punishment is thought to attend it.)   I have argued for some years
 that the only defense of religious privileges is the belief on the part of
 the claimant that commission of the act in question will generate divine
 sanctions.  This is probably too strict, since I (still) support the
 critique of Smith, and I have no reason to believe that the ingestion of
 peyote was a divine command violation of which would generate some kind of
 punishment (including punishment in the world to come).  But Eugene's hypo
 makes very real the costs to innocent third parties of treating any and all
 members of the clergy differently from
   one's
 best friends, fellow family members, or even, in most courts, reporters.
 
 sandy
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
 Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:39 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics (religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu)
 Subject: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
 
 One more question about the unconstitutional burdens on
 third parties theory:  The clergy-penitent privilege allows the clergy
 (and penitents) to refuse to testify about penitential communications, even
 when the result is that a litigant is deprived of potentially highly
 probative evidence.
 
 What's more, this is a specifically identifiable litigant who is being
 denied the benefit of applying the normal duty to testify.  And, unlike
 with the conscientious objector exemption, the clergy-penitent exemption is
 indeed limited to religious communications, with no secular philosophical
 analog.  (The psychotherapist-patient privilege, I think, is quite
 different, partly because it requires communications to someone who is
 licensed by the state, requires a state-prescribed course of training, and
 is usually quite expensive, and partly because it tends to have fewer
 exceptions.)
 
 Say, then, there are two people.  Anita works for an employer who (by
 hypothesis) has been exempted from the usually applicable (with some
 secular exemptions) employer mandate as a result of a statutory religious
 objector exemption.  As a result, she doesn't get, say, $500/year worth of
 contraceptive benefits that she would have been legally entitled to but for
 the employer mandate.
 
 Barbara is suing Don Defendant for $500,000.  She has reason to think
 that Don has confessed to Carl Clergyman that Don is indeed liable, so she
 wants Carl to be ordered to testify about the communication.  But Carl has
 been exempted from the usually applicable (with some secular exemptions)
 duty to testify as a result of a statutory clergy-congregant privilege.  As
 a result, she doesn't win the $500,000 that she would have been legally
 entitled to but for the clergy-congregant privilege.
 
 Is the application of the clergy-congregant exemption from the duty to
 testify in Barbara's case an Establishment Clause violation, on the grounds
 that it imposes an excessive burden on Barbara?  And if it isn't, then why
 would the application of the hypothetical exemption from the employer
 mandate an Establishment Clause violation in Anita's case?
 
 Eugene

 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott 

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Well, people do talk incautiously in contexts where no privilege is 
available, and their statements are used as a result.  Some people might not 
talk if they knew a privilege was unavailable, but others still might, 
especially if they feel they need to unburden themselves, and even more 
especially if they feel that such confession is a religious necessity.  (As I 
understand it, for instance, many psychiatrists' patients do say things to the 
psychiatrists that alert the psychiatrists to a danger to third parties, even 
though there is an exception to the privilege and to professional ethics in 
such situations, and even though under Tarasoff psychiatrists sometimes have a 
duty to disclose such threats.  Not a perfect analogy, I realize, but I hope a 
helpful one.)

So the consequence is that some litigants would not have benefited from 
the absence of a clergy-penitent privilege, since the penitent wouldn't have 
confessed.  But others would have, and I would think that there would be a 
considerable number of such others.  Under the Establishment Clause burden on 
nonbeneficiaries argument, why should it be necessary that the $500,000 loss 
to Barbara be guaranteed, as opposed to simply happening with some regularity 
to people in Barbara's shoes?

Eugene

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Levinson, Sanford V
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:40 PM
To: Douglas Laycock; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

I strongly suspect that Doug is right.  Still, I do wonder how often cases do 
arise beyond the Catholic Church (which probably fulfills my conditions for the 
privilege).

sandy

-Original Message-
From: Douglas Laycock [mailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu]
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 10:06 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; Levinson, Sanford V
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

Eugene's hypothetical presumably describes some of the cases, from the least 
sophisticated or most desperate penitents. But it probably doesn't describe 
very many; most penitents rely on the privilege, and few would confess to their 
priest if priests were routinely testifying against folks who confessed. The 
word would obviously get around to perps that this is what priests do when you 
confess.

So the plaintiff in Eugene's lawsuit really hasn't lost anything; the privilege 
deprives her only of evidence that would not exist but for the privilege. 

Meanwhile, the priest does some good, in at least some of the cases, toward 
encouraging reform or even restitution. In the original American case on the 
privilege, the priest had recovered the stolen goods and returned them to the 
owner. 

On Wed, 4 Dec 2013 02:37:42 +
 Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
This is an excellent hypothetical.  My own inclination is that the only 
justification for a clergy-penitent privilege is a) if there is a duty to 
confess to a member of the clergy; and b) if the clergy in question believes 
that God will punish disclosure of the confession.  (It shouldn't be enough 
that the doctrine of the religion prevents disclosure unless divine punishment 
is thought to attend it.)   I have argued for some years that the only defense 
of religious privileges is the belief on the part of the claimant that 
commission of the act in question will generate divine sanctions.  This is 
probably too strict, since I (still) support the critique of Smith, and I have 
no reason to believe that the ingestion of peyote was a divine command 
violation of which would generate some kind of punishment (including 
punishment in the world to come).  But Eugene's hypo makes very real the costs 
to innocent third parties of treating any and all members of the clergy 
differently from
  one's
best friends, fellow family members, or even, in most courts, reporters.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
(religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu)
Subject: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

One more question about the unconstitutional burdens on third 
 parties theory:  The clergy-penitent privilege allows the clergy (and 
 penitents) to refuse to testify about penitential communications, even when 
 the result is that a litigant is deprived of potentially highly probative 
 evidence.

What's more, this is a specifically identifiable litigant who is being 
denied the benefit of applying the normal duty to testify.  And, unlike 
with the conscientious objector exemption, the clergy-penitent 
exemption is indeed limited to religious communications, with no 
secular philosophical analog.  (The psychotherapist-patient 

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-03 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I don't think that's right.  First, recall that the employer 
mandate exemption is supposed to be one of at least a few such exemptions 
(grandfathered plans and under-50-person plans being the other ones); fewer 
than the privileges, but not by that much.

Second, as I mentioned, the clergy-penitent privilege is 
unusually strong -- in California, as I understand it, it has no exemptions, 
while the others have some pretty big ones (e.g., the doctor-patient privilege 
doesn't apply at all to criminal cases, Cal. Evid. Code 998, and there are many 
exceptions to the spousal privilege and the lawyer-client privilege).  It is 
also unusually easy to get:  Unlike with doctors, lawyers, psychotherapists, 
there is no requirement of government licensure or extended professional 
training (though of course some but not all religions do require extended 
training as a matter of their own practice).  Perhaps because of this, for many 
people a clergyman is the only person whose sympathetic ear and helpful counsel 
they can get for free, which doubtless makes it easier for the clergy to spread 
their own messages as part of such counsel.

In that sense, the closer analogy isn't Walz but, I would 
think, Texas Monthly.  There too there were doubtless many products that were 
exempt from sales tax (most food items being the classic example in most 
states).  But this wasn't enough:  The fact that Texas grants other sales tax 
exemptions (e. g., for sales of food, agricultural items, and property used in 
the manufacture of articles for ultimate sale) for different purposes does not 
rescue the exemption for religious periodicals from invalidation. What is 
crucial is that any subsidy afforded religious organizations be warranted by 
some overarching secular purpose that justifies like benefits for nonreligious 
groups. There is no evidence in the record, and Texas does not argue in its 
brief to this Court, that the exemption for religious periodicals was grounded 
in some secular legislative policy that motivated similar tax breaks for 
nonreligious activities. It certainly appears that the exemption was intended 
to benefit religion alone.  Likewise, the purpose of the clergy-penitent 
privilege is quite different from that of the spousal privilege, the 
lawyer-client privilege, and the doctor-patient privilege, and I think 
different even from the psychotherapist-patient privilege (where the 
resemblance is stronger but still on balance quite distant).

This isn't to say that Texas Monthly necessarily invalidates the 
clergy-penitent privilege -- the privilege does lift a government-imposed 
substantial burden on religious practice, and it isn't as clearly a preference 
for propagation of religious ideas (which is what the concurrences stressed).  
I just don't think that the clergy-penitent privilege can be saved on the 
grounds that it does not involve special treatment for religion.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

And the clergy-penitent privilege is one of many such privileges -- 
doctor-patient, lawyer-client, spousal privilege, etc.  They are designed to 
encourage communication within relationships the law values.  So this example 
is like Walz -- it does not involve special treatment for religion.  It is that 
kind of special treatment that triggers the concern for third party harms 
(Estate of Thornton v. Caldor).

On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 10:05 PM, Douglas Laycock 
dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
Eugene's hypothetical presumably describes some of the cases, from the least 
sophisticated or most desperate penitents. But it probably doesn't describe 
very many; most penitents rely on the privilege, and few would confess to their 
priest if priests were routinely testifying against folks who confessed. The 
word would obviously get around to perps that this is what priests do when you 
confess.

So the plaintiff in Eugene's lawsuit really hasn't lost anything; the privilege 
deprives her only of evidence that would not exist but for the privilege.

Meanwhile, the priest does some good, in at least some of the cases, toward 
encouraging reform or even restitution. In the original American case on the 
privilege, the priest had recovered the stolen goods and returned them to the 
owner.

On Wed, 4 Dec 2013 02:37:42 +
 Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edumailto:slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
This is an excellent hypothetical.  My own inclination is that the only 
justification for a clergy-penitent privilege is a) if there is a duty to 
confess to a member of the clergy; and b) if the clergy in question believes 
that God will punish disclosure of the confession.  (It shouldn't be enough 

RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-03 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
I once wrote an article, Testimonial Privileges and the Preferences of 
Friendship, 1984 DUKE LAW JOURNAL 631-662 (1984), the general thesis of which 
is that there is no truly plausible general theory of such privileges. (The 
title, incidentally, comes from Rousseau, who wrote that the preferences of 
friendship are thefts committed against the fatherland.   All men are our 
brothers; all should be our friends.  No doubt there's something scary in that 
notion, but it also captures the often-arbitrary partiality in allowing a small 
subset of individuals to refuse to offer evidence of criminal (or even 
tortious) behavior.   But if one does defend such partialities and loyalties, 
then why must one be married, for example (especially in the modern world) to 
get an intimacy privilege, and why, exactly, do family members (other than 
spouses) have no privileges?  Well-off people can go to psychiatrists, while 
less well-off talk to their bartenders and hairdressers (or, simply, best 
friends or workmates, none of whom are covered.  Are nurse-practitioners (who 
will play an increasingly important role in the delivery of medical services) 
covered (a genuine, not a rhetorical, question, since I don't know what the 
answer is, and if it varies state by state, do we really expect ordinary people 
to realize whether they are protected or not)?   In that article, I offered the 
thought-experiment of privilege tickets, a limited number of which we would 
get when we turned 18 and could distribute throughout our lifetimes to those we 
wished to immunize from state inquiries.

Maybe the real question is what is contained within Chip's etc.  If there are 
literally dozens of privileges, then one can engage in a gestalt switch and say 
that it is discriminating against the clergy to deny them what
A-Y get.  But if we're really talking about a small subset of people (none of 
whom get the kind of absolute privilege that the clergy apparently get), then 
I must say it looks an awful lot like Establishment to me, and I find Eugene's 
reference to the Texas Monthly case very persuasive.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 10:39 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

And the clergy-penitent privilege is one of many such privileges -- 
doctor-patient, lawyer-client, spousal privilege, etc.  They are designed to 
encourage communication within relationships the law values.  So this example 
is like Walz -- it does not involve special treatment for religion.  It is that 
kind of special treatment that triggers the concern for third party harms 
(Estate of Thornton v. Caldor).

On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 10:05 PM, Douglas Laycock 
dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
Eugene's hypothetical presumably describes some of the cases, from the least 
sophisticated or most desperate penitents. But it probably doesn't describe 
very many; most penitents rely on the privilege, and few would confess to their 
priest if priests were routinely testifying against folks who confessed. The 
word would obviously get around to perps that this is what priests do when you 
confess.

So the plaintiff in Eugene's lawsuit really hasn't lost anything; the privilege 
deprives her only of evidence that would not exist but for the privilege.

Meanwhile, the priest does some good, in at least some of the cases, toward 
encouraging reform or even restitution. In the original American case on the 
privilege, the priest had recovered the stolen goods and returned them to the 
owner.

On Wed, 4 Dec 2013 02:37:42 +
 Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edumailto:slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
This is an excellent hypothetical.  My own inclination is that the only 
justification for a clergy-penitent privilege is a) if there is a duty to 
confess to a member of the clergy; and b) if the clergy in question believes 
that God will punish disclosure of the confession.  (It shouldn't be enough 
that the doctrine of the religion prevents disclosure unless divine punishment 
is thought to attend it.)   I have argued for some years that the only defense 
of religious privileges is the belief on the part of the claimant that 
commission of the act in question will generate divine sanctions.  This is 
probably too strict, since I (still) support the critique of Smith, and I have 
no reason to believe that the ingestion of peyote was a divine command 
violation of which would generate some kind of punishment (including 
punishment in the world to come).  But Eugene's hypo makes very real the costs 
to innocent third parties of treating any and all members of the clergy 
differently from
  one's
best friends, fellow family members, or even, in most courts, reporters.

sandy

From: