Re: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit businesses

2014-02-26 Thread Marci Hamilton
They are similar in that both involve believers demanding a right to 
discriminate due to their religion. If Hobby Lobby wins, Walmart will have an 
argument to get around prohibitions based on race, gender, religion, alienage, 
and disability.  
All they need is one owner or board member and they are good to go.  

But here is the critical difference: The state amendment proposals are not 
moderate or almost identical.  Rfra applies only against the govt.  These bills 
bring private vs private disputes under its misguided, concocted standard.   
It's ugly.

Marci



Sent from my iPhone

On Feb 25, 2014, at 11:58 PM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:

 I have.  My point is your condemnation is not compelling to me when we 
 disagree on a either more moderate or almost identical bill (depending on how 
 Hobby Lobby comes out).
 
 
 On Tue, Feb 25, 2014 at 8:55 PM, hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 Have you read anything I've written for the last 20 years?
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215 
 http://sol-reform.com
 
 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Tue, Feb 25, 2014 8:47 pm
 Subject: Re: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit 
 businesses
 
 Would you say the Federal RFRA is  egregious, Marci?
 
 
 On Tue, Feb 25, 2014 at 6:38 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 I have read them and both are egregious.
 
 Sent from my iPhone
 
 On Feb 25, 2014, at 6:15 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
 
 The Arizona bill and the Kansas bill are very different. I don’t have time 
 right now to discuss this further, but all you have to do is to read the 
 bills. If you do, you will see that the arguments equating the two are 
 simply and egregiously wrong. I hope no one will comment in any strong way 
 without actually reading them.
  
 Mark
  
 Mark S. Scarberry
 Professor of Law
 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
  
  
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Greg Hamilton
 Sent: Tuesday, February 25, 2014 1:55 PM
 To: mich...@californialaw.org; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit 
 businesses
  
 …and Alan has been championing this bill on the spot at the Arizona 
 capitol. Sigh. I have fought him over it when he tried to push me into 
 supporting the Idaho bill which was just as egregious as the Arizona bill, 
 but perhaps more targeted.
  
 Gregory W. Hamilton, President
 Northwest Religious Liberty Association
 5709 N. 20th Street
 Ridgefield, WA 98642
 Office: (360) 857-7040
 Website: www.nrla.com
  
 image001.jpg
  
 Championing Religious Freedom and Human Rights for All People of Faith
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Michael Peabody
 Sent: Tuesday, February 25, 2014 1:38 PM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit 
 businesses
  
 After reading the legislation, it's amazing how broadly it is drafted. It 
 would seem to not only include permitting discrimination on the basis of 
 sexual orientation or marital status, but also on the basis of religion.  
 It would make it very easy for any business with a religious inkling to 
 refuse to accommodate the religious exercise of employees, or even 
 terminate them on the basis of religious differences.
  
 The Hobby Lobby case may go a long way in showing what rights employers 
 have, and it seems to be part of a general strike against the application 
 of the Bill of Rights to the states (14th Amendment).  
  
 Any time the principle argument in favor of a potentially dangerous law 
 is, What's the worse that can happen? I think there's reason to get 
 really nervous.
  
 There is probably an answer for those who don't want to violate their 
 religious conscience by accommodating those members of protected classes 
 that disagree with them, but this legislation is not it.
  
 Michael D. Peabody, Esq.
 Editor
 ReligiousLiberty.TV
 http://www.religiousliberty.tv
  
  
  
 ___
 
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are 
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or 
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options

Re: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit businesses

2014-02-26 Thread Marci Hamilton
Mark-- does the AZ bill permit discrimination on gender and race by private 
businesses?

The RFRAs say explicitly they are good against the govt.  expanding to private 
parties is a huge leap.  Remember RFRAs are supposedly the return to 
constitutional protections.  The Constitution requires state action but the 
RFRAs are explicit in the need for a govt defendant.   It's not NYT v Sullivan

Marci

Sent from my iPhone

On Feb 26, 2014, at 9:45 AM, Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu 
wrote:

 Marci's view of the rights of a Walmart under tha AZ bill, and likely even 
 the Kansas bill, is simply wrong.
 
 The application in the AZ bill to private enforcement by way of lawsuit 
 simply prevents the state from doing indirectly what it can't do directly, 
 cf. NY Times v. Sullivan, and makes clear something that already should be 
 the case under RFRAs, properly interpreted. 
 
 It also is the case that the AZ bill is much more moderate/sweeping than the 
 Kansas bill.
 
 Mark S. Scarberry
 Pepperdine University School of Law
 
 Sent from my Verizon Wireless 4G LTE Smartphone
 
 
  Original message 
 From: Marci Hamilton 
 Date:02/26/2014 5:09 AM (GMT-08:00) 
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
 Subject: Re: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit 
 businesses 
 
 They are similar in that both involve believers demanding a right to 
 discriminate due to their religion. If Hobby Lobby wins, Walmart will have an 
 argument to get around prohibitions based on race, gender, religion, 
 alienage, and disability.  
 All they need is one owner or board member and they are good to go.  
 
 But here is the critical difference: The state amendment proposals are not 
 moderate or almost identical.  Rfra applies only against the govt.  These 
 bills bring private vs private disputes under its misguided, concocted 
 standard.   It's ugly.
 
 Marci
 
 
 
 Sent from my iPhone
 
 On Feb 25, 2014, at 11:58 PM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:
 
 I have.  My point is your condemnation is not compelling to me when we 
 disagree on a either more moderate or almost identical bill (depending on 
 how Hobby Lobby comes out).
 
 
 On Tue, Feb 25, 2014 at 8:55 PM, hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 Have you read anything I've written for the last 20 years?
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215 
 http://sol-reform.com
 
 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Tue, Feb 25, 2014 8:47 pm
 Subject: Re: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit 
 businesses
 
 Would you say the Federal RFRA is  egregious, Marci?
 
 
 On Tue, Feb 25, 2014 at 6:38 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 I have read them and both are egregious.
 
 Sent from my iPhone
 
 On Feb 25, 2014, at 6:15 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
 
 The Arizona bill and the Kansas bill are very different. I don’t have 
 time right now to discuss this further, but all you have to do is to read 
 the bills. If you do, you will see that the arguments equating the two 
 are simply and egregiously wrong. I hope no one will comment in any 
 strong way without actually reading them.
  
 Mark
  
 Mark S. Scarberry
 Professor of Law
 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
  
  
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Greg Hamilton
 Sent: Tuesday, February 25, 2014 1:55 PM
 To: mich...@californialaw.org; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit 
 businesses
  
 …and Alan has been championing this bill on the spot at the Arizona 
 capitol. Sigh. I have fought him over it when he tried to push me into 
 supporting the Idaho bill which was just as egregious as the Arizona 
 bill, but perhaps more targeted.
  
 Gregory W. Hamilton, President
 Northwest Religious Liberty Association
 5709 N. 20th Street
 Ridgefield, WA 98642
 Office: (360) 857-7040
 Website: www.nrla.com
  
 image001.jpg
  
 Championing Religious Freedom and Human Rights for All People of Faith
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Michael Peabody
 Sent: Tuesday, February 25, 2014 1:38 PM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit 
 businesses
  
 After reading the legislation, it's amazing how broadly it is drafted. It 
 would seem to not only include permitting discrimination on the basis of 
 sexual orientation or marital status, but also on the basis of religion.  
 It would make it very easy for any business with a religious inkling to 
 refuse to accommodate the religious exercise

Re: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit businesses

2014-02-26 Thread Marci Hamilton
Mark-- please elaborate.   Can a Biblical white supremacist make an argument to 
refuse to serve a black person under the AZ bill?   How about the KS bill?
 And while we're at it, how about the GA bill?

I understand that the defenders of these bills have a long standing policy of 
not wanting to explain the details pf how the bill will work in operation, but 
that gambit is unethical in my view.   The burden is on the defenders of these 
new bills to explain how they improve our society by increasing opportunities 
to discriminate by religious actors.   

As I have said before the supporters of extreme religious liberty are morally 
responsible for the consequences of these laws/bills.   

Marci 

Sent from my iPhone

On Feb 26, 2014, at 10:03 AM, Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu 
wrote:

 That should have been much more moderate/less sweeping.
 
 Mark
 
 Mark S. Scarberry
 Pepperdine University School of y
 
 
 Sent from my Verizon Wireless 4G LTE Smartphone
 
 
  Original message 
 From: Scarberry, Mark 
 Date:02/26/2014 6:47 AM (GMT-08:00) 
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
 Subject: RE: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit   
 businesses 
 
 Marci's view of the rights of a Walmart under tha AZ bill, and likely even 
 the Kansas bill, is simply wrong.
 
 The application in the AZ bill to private enforcement by way of lawsuit 
 simply prevents the state from doing indirectly what it can't do directly, 
 cf. NY Times v. Sullivan, and makes clear something that already should be 
 the case under RFRAs, properly interpreted. 
 
 It also is the case that the AZ bill is much more moderate/sweeping than the 
 Kansas bill.
 
 Mark S. Scarberry
 Pepperdine University School of Law
 
 Sent from my Verizon Wireless 4G LTE Smartphone
 
 
  Original message 
 From: Marci Hamilton 
 Date:02/26/2014 5:09 AM (GMT-08:00) 
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
 Subject: Re: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit 
 businesses 
 
 They are similar in that both involve believers demanding a right to 
 discriminate due to their religion. If Hobby Lobby wins, Walmart will have an 
 argument to get around prohibitions based on race, gender, religion, 
 alienage, and disability.  
 All they need is one owner or board member and they are good to go.  
 
 But here is the critical difference: The state amendment proposals are not 
 moderate or almost identical.  Rfra applies only against the govt.  These 
 bills bring private vs private disputes under its misguided, concocted 
 standard.   It's ugly.
 
 Marci
 
 
 
 Sent from my iPhone
 
 On Feb 25, 2014, at 11:58 PM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:
 
 I have.  My point is your condemnation is not compelling to me when we 
 disagree on a either more moderate or almost identical bill (depending on 
 how Hobby Lobby comes out).
 
 
 On Tue, Feb 25, 2014 at 8:55 PM, hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 Have you read anything I've written for the last 20 years?
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215 
 http://sol-reform.com
 
 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Tue, Feb 25, 2014 8:47 pm
 Subject: Re: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit 
 businesses
 
 Would you say the Federal RFRA is  egregious, Marci?
 
 
 On Tue, Feb 25, 2014 at 6:38 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 I have read them and both are egregious.
 
 Sent from my iPhone
 
 On Feb 25, 2014, at 6:15 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
 
 The Arizona bill and the Kansas bill are very different. I don’t have 
 time right now to discuss this further, but all you have to do is to read 
 the bills. If you do, you will see that the arguments equating the two 
 are simply and egregiously wrong. I hope no one will comment in any 
 strong way without actually reading them.
  
 Mark
  
 Mark S. Scarberry
 Professor of Law
 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
  
  
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Greg Hamilton
 Sent: Tuesday, February 25, 2014 1:55 PM
 To: mich...@californialaw.org; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit 
 businesses
  
 …and Alan has been championing this bill on the spot at the Arizona 
 capitol. Sigh. I have fought him over it when he tried to push me into 
 supporting the Idaho bill which was just as egregious as the Arizona 
 bill, but perhaps more targeted.
  
 Gregory W. Hamilton, President
 Northwest Religious Liberty Association
 5709 N. 20th Street
 Ridgefield, WA 98642
 Office: (360) 857-7040
 Website

Re: The Arizona bill and Hobby Lobby

2014-02-26 Thread Marci Hamilton
These are not speech cases -- they are conduct cases.  RFRA explicitly says 
against the govt.   it was never intended in text or meaning to apply between 
private parties and I do not understand why anyone would want to foment such 
discord.   What RLUIPA has done to residential neighborhoods on that score is 
enough 

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Feb 26, 2014, at 4:52 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
 
 So is it wrong that the constitutional malice standard from NY Times v. 
 Sullivan applies not just when the government is a party, and not even just 
 when there is a government official who is a party, but even where the 
 plaintiff is a public figure who is not a government official? Under current 
 doctrine, the 1st Am applies when a non-government party is trying to use the 
 state judicial system to enforce state law against a non-government party by 
 suing that person for engaging in offensive speech. 
  
 On a related note, how about use of the IIED tort to recover for “blasphemy” 
 that is outrageous under current norms of religious tolerance and that causes 
 and is intended to cause serious emotional distress to the believer?
  
 The state shouldn’t be able to do indirectly, by way of creation of a private 
 cause of action, what it can’t do directly.
  
 Mark S. Scarberry
 Professor of Law
 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
  
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
 Sent: Wednesday, February 26, 2014 12:48 PM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Re: The Arizona bill and Hobby Lobby
  
 The difference is that in the Hobby Lobby cases, the Defendant is the 
 government.  In the AZ cases, both parties would be private, with the 
 business being able to raise RFRA against
 the private actor.
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215 
 http://sol-reform.com
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Wed, Feb 26, 2014 3:35 pm
 Subject: The Arizona bill and Hobby Lobby
 
 Apologies in advance if someone has already made this connection:
 
 If I'm understanding it correctly, the effect of the Arizona bill would be to 
 establish or confirm that the Arizona RFRA does exactly what Hobby Lobby and 
 its amici are arguing the federal RFRA already does -- namely, extend 
 protections to for-profit commercial operations.
 
 And the Republican establishment, including not only both Senator Flake and 
 Newt Gingrich, but also John McCain, an amicus in Hobby Lobby, are strongly 
 lobbying against it.  And they are doing so, presumably, because the Arizona 
 bill -- like the plaintiffs' argument in Hobby Lobby -- would pave the way 
 for claims of entitlement to religious exemptions from anti-discrimination 
 norms in the commercial setting.
 
 I say this not to accuse those Republican officials of hypocrisy -- I'm sure 
 they have not made the association -- but merely to point out that if Hobby 
 Lobby did not involve the incendiary combination of contraception and Obama, 
 it's very unlikely that so many would be arrayed in support of the rule they 
 are asking the Court to announce about RFRA.
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
  
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people 
 can 
 read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
 messages to others.
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit businesses

2014-02-25 Thread Marci Hamilton
I have read them and both are egregious.

Sent from my iPhone

On Feb 25, 2014, at 6:15 PM, Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu 
wrote:

 The Arizona bill and the Kansas bill are very different. I don’t have time 
 right now to discuss this further, but all you have to do is to read the 
 bills. If you do, you will see that the arguments equating the two are simply 
 and egregiously wrong. I hope no one will comment in any strong way without 
 actually reading them.
  
 Mark
  
 Mark S. Scarberry
 Professor of Law
 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
  
  
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Greg Hamilton
 Sent: Tuesday, February 25, 2014 1:55 PM
 To: mich...@californialaw.org; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit 
 businesses
  
 …and Alan has been championing this bill on the spot at the Arizona capitol. 
 Sigh. I have fought him over it when he tried to push me into supporting the 
 Idaho bill which was just as egregious as the Arizona bill, but perhaps more 
 targeted.
  
 Gregory W. Hamilton, President
 Northwest Religious Liberty Association
 5709 N. 20th Street
 Ridgefield, WA 98642
 Office: (360) 857-7040
 Website: www.nrla.com
  
 image001.jpg
  
 Championing Religious Freedom and Human Rights for All People of Faith
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Michael Peabody
 Sent: Tuesday, February 25, 2014 1:38 PM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Subject: Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit businesses
  
 After reading the legislation, it's amazing how broadly it is drafted. It 
 would seem to not only include permitting discrimination on the basis of 
 sexual orientation or marital status, but also on the basis of religion.  It 
 would make it very easy for any business with a religious inkling to refuse 
 to accommodate the religious exercise of employees, or even terminate them on 
 the basis of religious differences.
  
 The Hobby Lobby case may go a long way in showing what rights employers have, 
 and it seems to be part of a general strike against the application of the 
 Bill of Rights to the states (14th Amendment).  
  
 Any time the principle argument in favor of a potentially dangerous law is, 
 What's the worse that can happen? I think there's reason to get really 
 nervous.
  
 There is probably an answer for those who don't want to violate their 
 religious conscience by accommodating those members of protected classes that 
 disagree with them, but this legislation is not it.
  
 Michael D. Peabody, Esq.
 Editor
 ReligiousLiberty.TV
 http://www.religiousliberty.tv
  
  
  
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RLPA history for RLUIPA

2014-02-21 Thread Marci Hamilton
 on religious 
 exercise within the meaning of RFRA (I think the RFRA claims are strong) 
 makes me think that the following blog post, by our colleague Alan 
 Brownstein, is well worth a read and reflection:
 
 http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2014/02/prof-alan-brownstein-on-this-terms-religious-freedom-cases.html
 
 Some on this list have shared their view that ND's claim is implausible, 
 or disingenuous, or insincere, or incoherent, or insane, etc. and, 
 clearly, most of us are not sympathetic, even if we are open in principle 
 to religious accommodations.  Alan's post - which, as one would expect, is 
 fair, charitable, and thoughtful - is (among other things) an invitation 
 to law-and-religion folks to use the Town of Greece and HHS cases as an 
 occasion to ask ourselves why we sometimes dismiss as insubstantial (or 
 worse) claims of religion-related harm or burdens on religious exercise 
 that we do not understand or that we are not willing to accommodate. 
 
 I admit:  I am probably as mystified by the hostile reactions of those who 
 are mystified by ND's claims (which doesn't mean I think the ultimate 
 question is easy) as they are by those claims.  I have long been 
 underwhelmed by the allegations of injury in religious-symbols cases.  
 And, I regard the notion that ND's claims are - in a world where one's 
 irritation at the prospect that, somewhere, a disadvantaged kid is using a 
 voucher to attend a parochial school amounts to a standing-creating wound 
 to conscience - bizarrely outside the realm of possibility (or worse!) 
 as,well, bizarre.  But . . . Alan's post is a powerful one and - like 
 Larry Solum would say - highly recommended.
 
 Best, Rick
 
 
 Sent from my iPad
 
 On Feb 14, 2557 BE, at 3:38 PM, Levinson, Sanford V 
 slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:
 
 I know I’ve made this point before, but I still don’t see the difference 
 between the “setting in motion” that is generated by sending in the form 
 and the “setting in motion” that occurs when one pays, under penalty of 
 law, one’s taxes that can then be used for all sorts of immoral purposes 
 according to the tenets of one or another religion.  If I didn’t know 
 better, I’d simply describe this claim as “frivolous,” but I do realize 
 that people I respect apparently take it seriously.  But isn’t it a 
 recipe for the kind of Scalian anarchy that he warned about in Smith?   
 It is a sad truth that out everyday acts of compliance with the law, 
 including tax law, serves to enable the state to do things we (perhaps 
 justifiably) don’t like.  I really don’t see how one can distinguish 
 Notre Dame’s claim from the refusal of a postal worker to deliver mail to 
 an abortion clinic on the grounds that it enables their wicked handiwork. 
 
  
 
 I don’t think Barnette applies to this case, since the kids in that case 
 were being forced to proclaim their allegiance, which they treated as an 
 act of idolatry.  And, for what it is worth, the Court was crystal clear 
 in viewing it as a Free Speech, not a freedom of religion, case.
 
  
 
 From: conlawprof-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:conlawprof-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Scot Zentner
 Sent: Friday, February 14, 2014 3:21 PM
 To: conlawp...@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: RE: Posner on oral advocacy in religion caseesri
 
  
 
 I am not sure, but is it not the case that ND's precise claim is that the 
 exemption part of the form is not the problem, but the fact that the form 
 is also an instrument that sets in motion the provision of 
 contraceptive services by the third party?  So ND's objection is that the 
 employee would not have contraceptives but for the provision of insurance 
 by ND and its signing of the form.  
 
  
 
 Scot Zentner
 
 Professor
 
 Political Science
 
 CSU, San Bernardino
 
  
 
  
 
 From: conlawprof-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [conlawprof-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Marci Hamilton 
 [hamilton.ma...@gmail.com]
 Sent: Friday, February 14, 2014 12:46 PM
 To: Marty Lederman
 Cc: conlawp...@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Re: Posner on oral advocacy in religion caseesri
 
 I don't want to put too fine a point on this, but this entire line of 
 reasoning by ND is utter insanity.   The good news is that the religious 
 groups have gotten too clever by half and awakened the women and civil 
 rights groups in the country who did not understand how RFRA operates 
 against the vulnerable. It is, however, the natural end point of the 
 likelihood that believers and institutions would try to exploit 
 
 RFRA to its absolute maximum limits.  Every group/individual is likely to 
 exploit the power they have.  That is one of the most important 
 principles the US is built on.  
 
  
 
 But the people, the Constitution, and the state constitutions are 
 supposed to guard against such overreaching.  If this is what
 
 RFRA requires,  it is a violation of the Establishment Clause.  All that 
 is left is for someone to claim that their religious

Re: RLPA history for RLUIPA

2014-02-21 Thread Marci Hamilton
And under your reading of the Hobby Lobby situation, if the owners of a major 
residential developer were to believe that contraception is sinful (and 
therefore there
should be more housing for large families than small families), they should be 
able to use that belief to trump the zoning laws and change the land use plan 
to make all housing single family rather than multi family?
Or let's say we have a developer whose fellow believers believe in having many 
children for purposes of populating heaven but don't believe
in working so as to have more time
For religious study, so that developer invokes RLUIPA to change all single 
family zoning to more affordable multi-family.

These hypos are on all 4s w Hobby Lobby--for-profit organization, w owners w 
specific beliefs, imposing its beliefs on others.   

Congress did not even understand that the vast majority of the burdens
of RLUIPA would be imposed on residential neighborhoods.  This scenario was not 
on the table.  Nor should it be as it violates the Establishment Clause.

Marci




Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Feb 21, 2014, at 10:37 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
 
 Did you really think I don’t know that? There is the Kennedy-Hatch Manager’s 
 Statement on RLUIPA in the Senate, but the great bulk of RLUIPA’s legislative 
 history is the hearings, committee report, and floor debate on RLPA.
  
 For-profit land developers are persons under RLUIPA. But they would have to 
 show that they are developing the property for the purpose of religious 
 exercise and that they use or intend to use the property for religious 
 exercise.
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Friday, February 21, 2014 9:16 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RLPA history for RLUIPA
  
 Doug--  as a point of information-there is no specific RLUIPA history.   RLPA 
 history is used.   
  
 Does the CLS brief argument mean that for-profit land developers w religious 
 owners can use RLUIPA to get around the zoning laws?   If not, what is the 
 distinction?
  
 Marci
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
  
  
 
 On Feb 15, 2014, at 9:11 AM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
 
 I too found Alan Brownstein's post, which Rick put up at MOJ and linked in 
 his post here, quite thoughtful and provocative. I am not a Catholic, so I do 
 not feel like I have a basis for judgment about Notre Dame's arguments that 
 rest on ideas of both complicity and scandal (as I understand the latter, 
 which I probably don't, it involves institutional responsibility to avoid 
 active participation in a sinful enterprise).  Part of the problem with RFRA, 
 in its incorporation of pre-Smith free exercise principles, is the Thomas v. 
 Review Board doctrine that believers self-declare the religious 
 substantiality of their own burdens.  Judges can weigh the secular cost 
 (fines, prison, etc.) of compliance with faith  but cannot evaluate the 
 religious cost of complying with the law.  On that latter question, believers 
 are judges in their own cause.
  
 But I have a deeper problem with Alan's post and Rick's reaction to it.  Rick 
 seems to be one who has trouble seeing the burdens of publicly sponsored 
 prayer in Town of Greece, or seeing the problem of public financing of 
 religious education, through vouchers or otherwise.  Rick frequently 
 expresses doubt, sometimes tied to ideas of standing, about the injury 
 associated with these practices.
  
 With all respect to Rick and Alan, I think the equation of Town of Greece 
 with Hobby Lobby (or Notre Dame) rests on a profound category mistake.  The 
 free exercise clause (and RFRA) protects those who believe and practice their 
 faiths (individual and institutional actors).  The establishment clause is 
 aimed primarily at polity harms, not injuries to individuals.  Judge 
 Calabresi, in Town of Greece, did not focus on coercion of those who attended 
 Town Board meetings; the vice of the prayer practice, he wrote, was that it 
 aligned the Town with Christianity.  This would be a constitutional wrong 
 even if every person in the Town was a committed Christian who explicitly 
 consented to the prayers.  Our constitutional philosophy includes a 
 commitment that the government will not take on a religious identity -- this 
 protects liberty, yes, but it also protects against the long-term harm to the 
 political community that is generated by government adoption of a religious 
 identity. An analogy might be to the Town giving up democracy and turning 
 over all power to govern

Re: RLPA history for RLUIPA

2014-02-21 Thread Marci Hamilton
I disagree. Hobby Lobby is not required to sell arts and crafts.  My developer 
is not required to build anything.  He just wants to build what he wants but 
the govt requires him to do it in certain zones.   Hobby Lobby is required to 
operate its chosen business with restrictions on discrimination against women 
and on religion.   I think it is all 4s.

   

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Feb 21, 2014, at 11:55 AM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:
 
 I think the hypotheticals Marci poses are much closer to United States v. 
 Lee.  The case on all fours with Hobby Lobby would be if the developer was 
 required to build multi-family (or single-family) housing (as opposed to 
 leaving the property vacant) with government funding.
 
 
 On Fri, Feb 21, 2014 at 9:46 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 And under your reading of the Hobby Lobby situation, if the owners of a 
 major residential developer were to believe that contraception is sinful 
 (and therefore there
 should be more housing for large families than small families), they should 
 be able to use that belief to trump the zoning laws and change the land use 
 plan to make all housing single family rather than multi family?
 Or let's say we have a developer whose fellow believers believe in having 
 many children for purposes of populating heaven but don't believe
 in working so as to have more time
 For religious study, so that developer invokes RLUIPA to change all single 
 family zoning to more affordable multi-family.
 
 These hypos are on all 4s w Hobby Lobby--for-profit organization, w owners w 
 specific beliefs, imposing its beliefs on others.   
 
 Congress did not even understand that the vast majority of the burdens
 of RLUIPA would be imposed on residential neighborhoods.  This scenario was 
 not on the table.  Nor should it be as it violates the Establishment Clause.
 
 Marci
 
 
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 
 
 
 On Feb 21, 2014, at 10:37 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu 
 wrote:
 
 Did you really think I don’t know that? There is the Kennedy-Hatch 
 Manager’s Statement on RLUIPA in the Senate, but the great bulk of RLUIPA’s 
 legislative history is the hearings, committee report, and floor debate on 
 RLPA.
 
  
 
 For-profit land developers are persons under RLUIPA. But they would have to 
 show that they are developing the property for the purpose of religious 
 exercise and that they use or intend to use the property for religious 
 exercise.
 
  
 
 Douglas Laycock
 
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 
 University of Virginia Law School
 
 580 Massie Road
 
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
 
  434-243-8546
 
  
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Friday, February 21, 2014 9:16 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RLPA history for RLUIPA
 
  
 
 Doug--  as a point of information-there is no specific RLUIPA history.   
 RLPA history is used.   
 
  
 
 Does the CLS brief argument mean that for-profit land developers w 
 religious owners can use RLUIPA to get around the zoning laws?   If not, 
 what is the distinction?
 
  
 
 Marci
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 
 Yeshiva University
 
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 
  
 
  
 
 
 On Feb 15, 2014, at 9:11 AM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
 
 I too found Alan Brownstein's post, which Rick put up at MOJ and linked in 
 his post here, quite thoughtful and provocative. I am not a Catholic, so I 
 do not feel like I have a basis for judgment about Notre Dame's arguments 
 that rest on ideas of both complicity and scandal (as I understand the 
 latter, which I probably don't, it involves institutional responsibility to 
 avoid active participation in a sinful enterprise).  Part of the problem 
 with RFRA, in its incorporation of pre-Smith free exercise principles, is 
 the Thomas v. Review Board doctrine that believers self-declare the 
 religious substantiality of their own burdens.  Judges can weigh the 
 secular cost (fines, prison, etc.) of compliance with faith  but cannot 
 evaluate the religious cost of complying with the law.  On that latter 
 question, believers are judges in their own cause.
 
  
 
 But I have a deeper problem with Alan's post and Rick's reaction to it.  
 Rick seems to be one who has trouble seeing the burdens of publicly 
 sponsored prayer in Town of Greece, or seeing the problem of public 
 financing of religious education, through vouchers or otherwise.  Rick 
 frequently expresses doubt, sometimes tied to ideas of standing, about the 
 injury associated with these practices.
 
  
 
 With all respect to Rick and Alan, I think the equation of Town of Greece 
 with Hobby Lobby

Re: Kansas/Arizona statutes protecting for-profit businesses

2014-02-21 Thread Marci Hamilton
It is unconstitutional under Romer v Evans.   If they override the veto they 
are asking to underwrite federal litigation 

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Feb 21, 2014, at 10:14 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
 
 And a story out of Arizona . . . 
 
 http://www.nytimes.com/2014/02/22/us/religious-right-in-arizona-cheers-bill-allowing-businesses-to-refuse-to-serve-gays.html?hpwrref=politics
 
 Here's the bill (likely to be vetoed):
 
 http://www.azleg.gov/legtext/51leg/2r/bills/sb1062s.pdf
 
 
 On Sun, Feb 16, 2014 at 2:46 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 
 wrote:
 Not so fast, Chip!
 
 The Kansas House passed it, but it appears that the Senate will not do so . 
 . . despite a 32-8 Republican majority!
 
 http://www.chicagotribune.com/sns-rt-usa-gaymarriagekansas-20140212,0,4249694,full.story
 
 Even in red states, it's incredible how fast hearts and minds are changing . 
 . . 
 
 
 On Sun, Feb 16, 2014 at 2:12 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
 Look at the new Kansas law on the right of individuals and religious 
 entities to discriminate against those in same sex marriages, domestic 
 partnerships, etc.: 
 http://kslegislature.org/li/b2013_14/measures/documents/hb2453_01_.pdf\
 
 Note the definitions in section 3 (a) which defines religious entity to 
 include a privately-held business . . .  (section 3(a)(3)).  Perhaps this 
 is the unfortunate wave of the future in red states, preparing for a 14th 
 Amendment obligation to recognize same sex marriage.  
 
 
 On Sun, Feb 16, 2014 at 2:01 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 
 wrote:
 On a quick read, it appears that neither of the state assisted suicide 
 statutes is analogous, either.  They merely confirm that although entities 
 can assist suicides, no one is under any obligation to do so.  No need for 
 any exemption at all, since there's no duty in the first place.  And thus, 
 not surprisingly, no reference to religion at all, far as I could see.
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: recommended Hobby Lobby posts

2014-02-20 Thread Marci Hamilton
As someone who was involved in RLPA in Congress from day one through many 
hearings, only a tortured reading of history supports the notion that Congress 
believed that its proponents believed RFRA should apply to for-profit 
organizations let alone that they intended it to. 

 Given current deadlines I cannot add more , but I look forward to reading 
Jim's piece and will be doing something of my own closer to the argument.

Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Feb 20, 2014, at 12:34 PM, James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu wrote:
 
 I have a short essay coming out next month that offers a considerably 
 different take than Doug on both the legislative history of RLPA and the text 
 of the 1999 version of RLPA as compared to RFRA. A draft of the essay is 
 available here:
 
 Obamacare, RFRA, and the Perils of Legislative History
 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2398763
 
 The relevant discussion can be found on pages 5-10 of the draft. My 
 bottom-line conclusion is that the 1998 and 1999 debates over RLPA fall far 
 short of demonstrating an 'undisputed public understanding that the language 
 in RFRA protected for-profit corporations and their owners.' 
 
 On the specific claim that the text of RFRA and RLPA were identical, I make 
 the same point I see Marty has made in his separate response to Doug -- the 
 1999 RLPA has a broad construction provision that was in neither the 1998 
 RLPA or RFRA. Thus, the more relevant RLPA legislative history is the 1998 
 debate, not the 1999 debate Doug relies upon in the CLS amicus brief and his 
 SCOTUS Blog post. And the 1998 testimony casts considerable doubt on the 
 claim that large for-profit businesses are protected by RFRA.  
 
 On a different note, I want to second Marty's recommendation of the symposium 
 over at SCOTUS Blog. Specifically, I highly recommend folks take a look at 
 Chip and Bob's piece, which makes an important argument calling for symmetry 
 between the treatment of employee accommodations under Title VII and employer 
 accommodations under RFRA (in both cases this avoids establishment concerns 
 raised by exemptions that impose more than de minimis burdens on others). 
 Chip and Bob's piece is available here: 
 http://www.scotusblog.com/2014/02/symposium-religious-questions-and-saving-constructions/
 
 - Jim
 
 On Thu, Feb 20, 2014 at 7:30 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu 
 wrote:
 I have not gone back to review all the RLPA testimony, but yes we did 
 predict that large commercial businesses seeking religious exemptions from 
 civil rights laws would generally lose.
 
  
 
 The context of that testimony was civil rights claims. And it was a 
 prediction of what the courts would do in fact, not a judgment about what 
 they should do. But I would probably be comfortable with most of the results 
 we predicted.
 
  
 
 The kinds of civil rights claims RLPA’s supporters wanted to preserve mostly 
 did not arise in business situations. Religious discrimination by religious 
 organizations setting their criteria for membership, as in CLS v. Martinez, 
 is rarely a legitimate business interest. Sex and marital-status 
 discrimination in the ordination of a celibate male clergy is not a business 
 interest.
 
  
 
 The existing examples at the time were the landlord-tenant cases, all of 
 which involved small landlords. People could envision issues with kosher 
 butchers and Christian bookstores, and with the broad reach of some state 
 civil rights laws. Some state laws prohibit discrimination on the basis of 
 “any lawful off-the-job activity.” Think the church secretary moonlighting 
 in an abortion clinic, or a strip club, or any other business that is lawful 
 but disreputable in the view of some.
 
 Same-sex marriage was on the far horizon; I don’t recall anyone thinking 
 about wedding photographers and the like.
 
  
 
 I believed that as the business grows, it becomes less plausible to view it 
 as a personal extension of the owner. Mrs. Smith with two duplexes may feel 
 morally responsible for every unit, and she may be doing all the work of 
 leasing and maintenance herself. A landlord with multiple apartment 
 complexes is less likely to feel that moral responsibility, and less likely 
 to persuade a court that he does. He certainly does not have to become 
 personally involved with what he considers the immoral use of his property 
 by particular tenants. And as the business grows, the government’s interest 
 grows.
 
  
 
 I did not envision at the time, and I don’t know that anyone else did, a 
 case like Hobby Lobby. Here the business is large, but it is closely held by 
 devoutly religious and religiously unanimous owners. The government is 
 demanding a decision that must be made at the level of senior management for 
 the entire corporation; in 1998 and 99, people were thinking about issues 
 posed by one customer somewhere, to be dealt 

Re: Notre Dame-- where's the complicit participation? Sincerity

2014-02-17 Thread Marci Hamilton
Just to clarify for the latecomers and then I will not be returning to this -- 
My point was not that believers who have failed to live up to their beliefs are 
vulnerable to a sincerity attack.   My point, which is based on multiple polls 
and my own direct, personal knowledge of many  American Catholics, is that many 
reject the Church's teaching on contraception.  They simply don't believe it.  
That makes Alan's hypo and Mark's analysis off-point.  
FWIW, I think Marty is correct such inquiries will work themselves out on 
substantial burden analysis, not sincerity.   My interest is the gap between 
facts, public perception, and doctrine.

I have a book deadline and so will not be checking the listserv again for at 
least a week.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Feb 16, 2014, at 10:07 PM, Alan Brownstein aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu 
 wrote:
 
 I thought there was a great deal of merit in Mark Scarberry's earlier post 
 and I appreciate the distinctions that Marty draws between lack of sincerity 
 and lack of depth and substantiality of religious belief. I have three 
 thoughts.
  
 First, since I know very little about Catholic theology or the institutional 
 structure of Catholic institutions such as Notre Dame, let me pose a 
 hypothetical based on religious beliefs and institutional frameworks with 
 which I am more familiar.
  
 Let us assume that a small group of Reform Jews lives in a community. Assume 
 further that most of them do not keep Kosher kitchens in their homes. Because 
 they are too small a group to develop a house of worship, they meet in 
 people's homes for services, notwithstanding the lack of Kosher facilities. 
 Later, the group constructs a small building to use as a place of worship. 
 There are limited kitchen facilities. Some attempt is made to adhere to 
 Jewish dietary laws, but it is haphazard at best. Eventually, the community 
 grows to a size that enables it purchase a complex of buildings including 
 both a sanctuary and a social hall. Through a generous donation, it is able 
 to construct a new kitchen in the social hall. The Synagogue Board, most of 
 the directors of which do not keep Kosher homes themselves, agree that the 
 new kitchen should be strictly Kosher. The great majority of members of the 
 congregation also do not keep Kosher homes.
  
 The town passes a law that has the incidental effect of requiring the 
 Synagogue's kitchen to violate Jewish dietary laws (I know that is unlikely, 
 but bear with me.) The Synagogue challenges the ordinance under a state RFRA. 
 The town argues the Synagogue's claim should be barred because the history of 
 the congregation and the Synagogue, and the personal conduct of the Board and 
 congregation members, demonstrate either a lack of sincerity or religious 
 convictions of insufficient depth and substantiality to justify any burden of 
 justification on the town. On these facts, should the town be required to 
 justify its law and its refusal to exempt the Synagogue from the law's 
 operation. 
  
 Second, I think most of us are in various relationships -- with spouses, 
 children, parents, employers, voluntary associations -- which are the source 
 of obligations we take very seriously. I also suspect that many of us would 
 be vulnerable to challenges based on the inconsistency and incoherency of our 
 conduct. If we really cared deeply about our (fill in the blanks) we might be 
 asked, why did we sometimes act in ways that seem contrary to these 
 commitments that we claim to respect, to which we claim to adhere. I think it 
 would be a mistake, however, to leap to quickly to the conclusion that these 
 commitments and obligations lack substantiality or depth.
  
 Third, and finally, to go back to the very beginning of the thread in which 
 it was asked -- why do we assume good faith and sincerity on the part of 
 religious individuals and institutional claimants. I suppose one general 
 answer is that we are typically discussing more abstract doctrinal questions 
 and do not know enough about the facts to impugn anyone's integrity. But the 
 more experience based answer, at least for me, is that I presume as a fact 
 that the claimant seeking an exemption is sincere because most of the time it 
 is true.
  
 Alan 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
 on behalf of Marty Lederman [lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
 Sent: Sunday, February 16, 2014 1:10 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Notre Dame-- where's the complicit participation? Sincerity
 
 I may have more to say on this point later, but for now this'll have to 
 suffice:  
 
 First, Doug may be correct that there is no doubt about what the Church's 
 teaching is about the morality of contraception use.  But there sure is 
 plenty of doubt, as Eduardo noted, about whether the Church, or Notre Dame, 
 or 

Re: Notre Dame-- where's the complicit participation? Sincerity

2014-02-16 Thread Marci Hamilton
There is a doubt however about what American Catholics believe.  They 
overwhelmingly reject the church teaching against contraception.   They don't 
think they are sinners as Mark suggested.  They reject it.

Every poll supports that as does the fact that it is rare to find a Catholic 
family w 10-20 children in the US.  The teaching is one thing: the belief is 
another in the US.   This is not an idle observation.  ND has inserted itself 
into the spotlight by asserting beliefs that most Americans know Catholics 
reject-in theory and in practice.  

On Marty's point--the fact that the government gives for-profits a pass
on abortion does not show they have a conscience.  It shows religious abortion 
opponents had political clout.Your reasoning strikes me as backward.   I 
think Marty and the SG are on the stronger ground here   If the Court finds 
they have
such rights, the slippery slope is perpendicular to the ground.

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Feb 16, 2014, at 3:45 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
 
 No doubt the Board and senior administration speaks for Notre Dame. But on 
 faith and morals, they may (and may be expected to or required to) take their 
 guidance from the bishops. There is no doubt what the Church’s teaching is, 
 and no doubt that teaching is sincere. What I said was that Notre Dame’s 
 leadership may sincerely feel obliged to follow that teaching in their 
 official capacity as leaders of a Catholic institution, whatever they may do 
 in their private life.
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
 Sent: Sunday, February 16, 2014 3:14 PM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Re: Notre Dame-- where's the complicit participation? Sincerity
  
 Is Doug correct as a legal matter that the bishops speak for Notre Dame, as 
 opposed to its officials, and the officials' actions are irrelevant?  And 
 that the actions of its co-religionist officials are irrelevant to  proof of 
 the organization's beliefs?  Why don't the practices of Notre Dame's 
 officials prove insincerity in this case?   (I'm assuming that they don't 
 have the 10-20 children
 typically incident to not using birth control and that they follow the vast 
 majority of American Catholics in rejecting the belief against 
 contraception).  How can they claim
 a right not to provide contraception for their employees/students in their 
 health plan because of complicity if they are using it themselves?
  
 To provide an analogy:   In the prison cases, you can test a prisoner's 
 sincerity when he demands kosher food (because it's better than the usual 
 fare),
 and claims a conversion to Judaism, but they find pork rinds in his cell, it 
 is assumed he is not sincere and does not receive the accommodation (a state
 prison general counsel provided this example for me)
  
 Marci
  
  
  
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Supreme Court Issues Compromise Injunction Pending Appeal In Contraceptive Mandate Case

2014-01-24 Thread Marci Hamilton
It looks like the Court told them to do what they said they didn't want to do.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Jan 24, 2014, at 5:28 PM, Friedman, Howard M. 
 howard.fried...@utoledo.edu wrote:
 
 The Supreme Court today extended the injunction pending appeal in Little 
 Sisters of the Poor case, but with unusual conditions-- see 
 http://religionclause.blogspot.com/2014/01/supreme-court-enjoins-enforcement-of.html
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Supreme Court Issues Compromise Injunction Pending Appeal In Contraceptive Mandate Case

2014-01-24 Thread Marci Hamilton
What exactly is the burden on the Little Sisters again?  

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Jan 24, 2014, at 6:27 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
 
 I found the form. Here is a statement that is included on the back of the 
 government form that the Little Sisters would have had to sign, absent the 
 Court’s order:
  
 The organization or its plan must provide a copy of this certification to the 
 plan’s health insurance
 issuer (for insured health plans) or a third party administrator (for 
 self-insured health plans) in order
 for the plan to be accommodated with respect to the contraceptive coverage 
 requirement.
  
 Notice to Third Party Administrators of Self-Insured Health Plans
  
 In the case of a group health plan that provides benefits on a self-insured 
 basis, the provision of
 this certification to a third party administrator for the plan that will 
 process claims for
 contraceptive coverage required under 26 CFR 54.9815-2713(a)(1)(iv) or 29 CFR 
 2590.715-
 2713(a)(1)(iv) constitutes notice to the third party administrator that the 
 eligible organization:
  
 (1) Will not act as the plan administrator or claims administrator with 
 respect to claims for
 contraceptive services, or contribute to the funding of contraceptive 
 services; and
  
 (2) The obligations of the third party administrator are set forth in 26 CFR 
 54.9815-2713A, 29
 CFR 2510.3-16, and 29 CFR 2590.715-2713A.
  
 This certification is an instrument under which the plan is operated.
  
  
  
 It seems to me that signing a form that says that the third party 
 administrator has the obligations set out in the CFR is the equivalent of 
 directing the third party administrator to comply with those regulations. 
 They would be notifying the administrator that it has the obligations set out 
 in the CFR. I suppose, in addition, that the Little Sisters dispute whether 
 the government can require their third party administrator to comply with 
 those regulations; the form would require the Little Sisters to make a 
 statement that they do not believe to be true. The last sentence of the form 
 suggests that the obligations of the plan administrator under the CFR are 
 included as part of the health care plan.
  
 In effect, the Little Sisters, if they signed the form, would be (1) 
 notifying the administrator that it must comply with the regs, (2) stating 
 that the administrator has the obligations set out in the CFR, (3) directing 
 the third party administrator to provide the objectionable services, and (4) 
 amending the plan documents to include a requirement that the third party 
 administrator do so.
  
 It seems, then, that the Court has given the Little Sisters substantial 
 relief by not requiring them to sign the government form.
  
 Mark
  
 Mark S. Scarberry
 Professor of Law
 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
  
  
  
  
  
 From: Scarberry, Mark 
 Sent: Friday, January 24, 2014 2:45 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Supreme Court Issues Compromise Injunction Pending Appeal In 
 Contraceptive Mandate Case
  
 Does anyone have a copy of the government-prescribed form that the Court said 
 the Little Sisters didn’t have to use?
  
 Mark
  
 Mark S. Scarberry
 Professor of Law
 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
  
  
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marc DeGirolami
 Sent: Friday, January 24, 2014 2:36 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Supreme Court Issues Compromise Injunction Pending Appeal In 
 Contraceptive Mandate Case
  
 Nope. It looks like the Court told them to send the government a copy of 
 their complaint.
  
 From: Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com
 Reply-To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Date: Friday, January 24, 2014 at 5:32 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Re: Supreme Court Issues Compromise Injunction Pending Appeal In 
 Contraceptive Mandate Case
  
 It looks like the Court told them to do what they said they didn't want to do.
  
 Marci
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
  
  
 
 On Jan 24, 2014, at 5:28 PM, Friedman, Howard M. 
 howard.fried...@utoledo.edu wrote:
 
 The Supreme Court today extended the injunction pending appeal in Little 
 Sisters of the Poor case, but with unusual conditions-- see 
 http://religionclause.blogspot.com/2014/01/supreme-court-enjoins-enforcement-of.html
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note

Re: Conestoga Opening Brief -- Free Exercise/Selective Exemption Argument

2014-01-11 Thread Marci Hamilton
To follow up on Marty's last point --In the Milwaukee Archdiocese bankruptcy, 
the AD is arguing that the religious exemptions in the federal bankruptcy code 
trigger strict scrutiny.   I agree w Marty's implicit point -- that makes 
little sense.  
Our opening briefs  to the 7 th Cir are due on Wed. 

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Jan 11, 2014, at 7:54 AM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
 
 Just a quick point to quibble with the factual premises of the selectivity 
 argument.  Plans offered by small business do have to include the relevant 
 preventive services, including -- but hardly limited to -- contraception 
 services.  (The services also include cholesterol screening; colorectal 
 cancer screening; diabetes screening for those with high blood pressure; 
 certain immunizations; “evidence-informed preventive care and screenings” for 
 infants, children, and adolescents; specified annual well-woman visits; 
 gestational diabetes screening; HPV DNA testing; testing for sexually 
 transmitted diseases and HIV screening and counseling; breastfeeding support, 
 supplies and counseling; and domestic violence screening and counseling.)  
 
 Likewise, the so-called grandfathering exception is merely an ordinary 
 phasing in, or timing, provision, which allows a transition period for 
 compliance with several of the Act's requirements until the plans otherwise 
 make one of several specified changes.  The employees of such plans will 
 eventually receive the preventive care coverages (not only contraception -- 
 all those listed above).
 
 The only real carve-out -- the only one that would result in employees not 
 receiving contraceptive coverage -- is HHS's own exemption for churches and 
 their auxiliaries.  And if that religious accommodation is what triggers 
 Lukumi, well . . .  
 
 
 On Fri, Jan 10, 2014 at 9:37 PM, James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu wrote:
 The opening brief for Conestoga Wood Specialties Corp. has been filed, and I 
 believe this may be the first time the Supreme Court has been presented with 
 an argument in a party's merits brief as to the scope of the so-called 
 Sherbert-exception to Smith -- the idea expressed in both Smith and Lukumi 
 that although the Free Exercise Clause does not require religious exemptions 
 to be made from uniform legal obligations, religious exemptions may be 
 required when other exemptions to a law are available. 
 
 In an article last year, I suggested that there remain at least five major 
 unresolved questions about the selective-exemption rule:
 
 1.  What is the purpose of the rule: is it designed to guard against the 
 danger of intentional discrimination or to address the adverse impact on 
 religious minorities of unintentional neglect or indifference?
 
 
 
 2.  Does the rule only apply when a law allows for ad hoc, individualized 
 exemptions to an obligation (e.g., discretionary excuses under a good 
 cause or necessary standard), or does it also apply when the government 
 makes select categorical exemptions to a law?
 
 
 
 3.  If the rule applies when categorical exemptions are made, how should 
 courts determine whether an existing categorical exemption to a law is 
 sufficiently analogous to the requested religious exemption to be deemed a 
 relevant comparator?
 
 
 
 4.  How many comparable categorical exemptions must exist before the 
 selective-exemption rule is triggered by the denial of a religious exemption?
 
 
 
 5. What is the appropriate level of judicial scrutiny to be applied once the 
 selective-exemption rule is triggered?
 
 
 Conestoga's positions on questions #2 and #5 are what you would expect. On 
 #2, it argues that the selective-exemption rule extends to situations 
 involving categorical exemptions (in this case, the ACA's exemptions for 
 small businesses and grandfathered plans). On #5, it argues for strict 
 scrutiny (which is what the Court indicated in both Smith and Lukumi applies 
 to individualized-exemption situations).
 
 Conestoga's brief does not contain much argument relevant to questions #3 
 and #4. 
 
 As for #1, I found the most relevant passage in Conestoga's brief to be 
 quite surprising. Usually, advocates of a broad reading of the 
 selective-exemption rule make a point of contending that the rule is not 
 limited to situations involving the danger of discriminatory intent. Yet, 
 Conestoga's brief quotes a portion of the Third Circuit's decision in 
 Fraternal Order of Police Newark Lodge v. Newark that speaks directly to 
 discriminatory intent and is not usually quoted by advocates of a broad 
 reading of the rule:
 
 Providing secular exemptions 'while refusing religious exemptions is 
 sufficiently suggestive of discriminatory intent as to trigger heightened 
 scrutiny under Smith and Lukumi.' Br. at 46 (quoting Newark Lodge at 365).  
  
 
 As it turns out, this is the very same 

Re: The nonprofit contraception services cases

2014-01-06 Thread Marci Hamilton
This is strictly an informational question-- is Notre Dame allowed to 
discriminate on the basis of religion in undergraduate admission?



Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Jan 6, 2014, at 2:46 PM, Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:
 
 Dear colleagues,
  
 I would recommend Prof. Kevin Walsh’s post (here:  
 http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2014/01/what-does-the-form-that-the-government-insists-the-little-sisters-of-the-poor-must-sign-actually-do.html)
  on the issue with which Marty kicked off this thread a few days ago.  
 Kevin’s post is called “What does the form that the government insists the 
 Little Sisters of the Poor must sign actually do?”
  
 Of course, others have moved from the specific issues that Marty raised to 
 more general (and always important) conversations about RFRA’s 
 constitutionality and the moral desirability of Yoder, but I wanted to ask 
 just a few things with respect to Greg Lipper’s report that Americans United 
 for Separation of Church  State has filed a motion seeking to intervene in 
 the University of Notre Dame’s lawsuit challenging the mandate.  (Although I 
 am blessed to teach at Notre Dame, I have no role in the University’s 
 lawsuit.)
 https://www.au.org/media/press-releases/americans-united-seeks-to-intervene-in-notre-dame-lawsuit-challenging-womens
  
 I understand (though I do not agree with) the claim that, because Notre Dame 
 is a large employer in the area, its right to refuse to provide coverage for 
 contraceptives (in cases where a physician has not indicated that the 
 contraceptives are medically indicated) to employees who do not embrace the 
 Catholic Church’s teachings on sexual morality and abortion is limited.  That 
 is, Notre Dame’s role and place in the market limits its right to say to 
 employees “this is who we are, and if you want to work for us, you should 
 expect that who we are will be relevant to the terms of our arrangement with 
 you.”
  
 With respect to students, though, it is harder for me to see why Notre Dame 
 should not be able to say to prospective students (as Notre Dame does), “This 
 is who we are.  If you come here – and you are welcome to, but you don’t have 
 to – you should know that our character, mission, aspirations, and values 
 will shape the terms of our arrangement with you.”   Is it the view of AU, or 
 of others, that the Establishment Clause (or anything else) prevents the 
 government from exempting a Catholic (or other mission-oriented) educational 
 institution from an otherwise general rule in order to allow the institution 
 to say (something like) this to students and the broader world – again, 
 assuming that students who get into Notre Dame (a) have plenty of options and 
 (b) know full well that Notre Dame aspires to a meaningfully Catholic 
 character?
  
 Best,
  
 Rick
  
 Richard W. Garnett
 Professor of Law and Concurrent Professor of Political Science
 Director, Program on Church, State  Society
 Notre Dame Law School
 P.O. Box 780
 Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780
 574-631-6981 (w)
 574-276-2252 (cell)
 rgarn...@nd.edu
  
 To download my scholarly papers, please visit my SSRN page
  
 Blogs:
  
 Prawfsblawg
 Mirror of Justice
  
 Twitter:  @RickGarnett
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Friday, January 03, 2014 1:42 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: The nonprofit contraception services cases
  
 Marty-- could you please elaborate on your response?  I am not following this 
 exchange
  
 Thanks--
 Marci
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
  
  
 
 On Jan 3, 2014, at 12:43 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
 
 They will -- the government realizes that its plan is undermined and is 
 reassessing
 
 Sent from my iPhone
 
 On Jan 3, 2014, at 12:08 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
 
 Why don't all these religious nonprofits choose Christian Brothers Services 
 as their health insurer?  That way, certification or not, the employees will 
 not receive the services to which the employer objects?  Something is missing 
 from this narrative.
 
 
 Sent from my iPhone
 
 On Jan 3, 2014, at 10:56 AM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
 
 The government's brief in Little Sisters:
 
 http://balkin.blogspot.com/2014/01/government-bref-in-little-sisters.html
  
 
 On Wed, Jan 1, 2014 at 5:34 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 
 wrote:
 Another post, this one about the nonprofit cases that have now wound their 
 way to the Court . . .
 
 http://balkin.blogspot.com/2014/01/not-quite-hobby-lobby-nonprofit-cases.html
  
 
 On Mon, Dec 16, 2013 at 1:53 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 
 wrote:
 Since no one else

Re: The nonprofit contraception services cases

2014-01-06 Thread Marci Hamilton
Doesn't it depend in some way on how much 
federal money it receives?   Again, I am
simply asking.

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Jan 6, 2014, at 3:15 PM, Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:
 
 Notre Dame is allowed (I assume – again, I am just an employee and am not 
 involved in admissions or with the University Counsel’s work) to take 
 religion, and many other factors, into account when building its classes, 
 sure.  Does anyone believe that Notre Dame should *not* be able to conduct 
 admissions so as to, for example, admit classes that are predominantly 
 Catholic?
  
 Best,
  
 Rick
  
 Richard W. Garnett
 Professor of Law and Concurrent Professor of Political Science
 Director, Program on Church, State  Society
 Notre Dame Law School
 P.O. Box 780
 Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780
 574-631-6981 (w)
 574-276-2252 (cell)
 rgarn...@nd.edu
  
 To download my scholarly papers, please visit my SSRN page
  
 Blogs:
  
 Prawfsblawg
 Mirror of Justice
  
 Twitter:  @RickGarnett
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Monday, January 06, 2014 3:08 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: The nonprofit contraception services cases
  
 This is strictly an informational question-- is Notre Dame allowed to 
 discriminate on the basis of religion in undergraduate admission?
  
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
  
  
 
 On Jan 6, 2014, at 2:46 PM, Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:
 
 Dear colleagues,
  
 I would recommend Prof. Kevin Walsh’s post (here:  
 http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2014/01/what-does-the-form-that-the-government-insists-the-little-sisters-of-the-poor-must-sign-actually-do.html)
  on the issue with which Marty kicked off this thread a few days ago.  
 Kevin’s post is called “What does the form that the government insists the 
 Little Sisters of the Poor must sign actually do?”
  
 Of course, others have moved from the specific issues that Marty raised to 
 more general (and always important) conversations about RFRA’s 
 constitutionality and the moral desirability of Yoder, but I wanted to ask 
 just a few things with respect to Greg Lipper’s report that Americans United 
 for Separation of Church  State has filed a motion seeking to intervene in 
 the University of Notre Dame’s lawsuit challenging the mandate.  (Although I 
 am blessed to teach at Notre Dame, I have no role in the University’s 
 lawsuit.)
 https://www.au.org/media/press-releases/americans-united-seeks-to-intervene-in-notre-dame-lawsuit-challenging-womens
  
 I understand (though I do not agree with) the claim that, because Notre Dame 
 is a large employer in the area, its right to refuse to provide coverage for 
 contraceptives (in cases where a physician has not indicated that the 
 contraceptives are medically indicated) to employees who do not embrace the 
 Catholic Church’s teachings on sexual morality and abortion is limited.  That 
 is, Notre Dame’s role and place in the market limits its right to say to 
 employees “this is who we are, and if you want to work for us, you should 
 expect that who we are will be relevant to the terms of our arrangement with 
 you.”
  
 With respect to students, though, it is harder for me to see why Notre Dame 
 should not be able to say to prospective students (as Notre Dame does), “This 
 is who we are.  If you come here – and you are welcome to, but you don’t have 
 to – you should know that our character, mission, aspirations, and values 
 will shape the terms of our arrangement with you.”   Is it the view of AU, or 
 of others, that the Establishment Clause (or anything else) prevents the 
 government from exempting a Catholic (or other mission-oriented) educational 
 institution from an otherwise general rule in order to allow the institution 
 to say (something like) this to students and the broader world – again, 
 assuming that students who get into Notre Dame (a) have plenty of options and 
 (b) know full well that Notre Dame aspires to a meaningfully Catholic 
 character?
  
 Best,
  
 Rick
  
 Richard W. Garnett
 Professor of Law and Concurrent Professor of Political Science
 Director, Program on Church, State  Society
 Notre Dame Law School
 P.O. Box 780
 Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780
 574-631-6981 (w)
 574-276-2252 (cell)
 rgarn...@nd.edu
  
 To download my scholarly papers, please visit my SSRN page
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can

Re: The nonprofit contraception services cases

2014-01-06 Thread Marci Hamilton
Is the ND rule students can't use it --or can't get it under student insurance 
--or can't get it from student health services?  Or a combination?

It would also be interesting what their policy was before and after the ACA was 
enacted.



Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Jan 6, 2014, at 3:35 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
 
 Sorry, I should have added that if ND prohibited only women, and not men, 
 from using contraception, that would violate the title IX prohibition on sex 
 discrimination.  But a rule that all students must not indulge in unmarried 
 sex, or in unmarried sex with contraception, might be ok under current 
 federal law.
 
 
 On Mon, Jan 6, 2014 at 3:29 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 
 wrote:
 And here's a post that (in part) responds to Kevin -- although my principal 
 point is the Little Sisters case is an unimportant sideshow, and that it 
 won't matter much what the Court does on the emergency motion, in particular:
 
 http://balkin.blogspot.com/2014/01/little-sisters-state-of-play.html
 
 On Rick's new question, I'd need to think some more about it, but I assume 
 that it would be permissible for Congress either to grant N.D. an exemption 
 from title IX, thereby allowing N.D. to enroll only practicing Catholics . 
 . . or to deny N.D. such an exemption.
 
 Moreover, as it stands now, and unless I'm forgetting something, I don't 
 think anything in the law would prohibit N.D. from requiring enrolling women 
 to certify that they will not use contraception.  But N.D. of course does 
 not do so.
 
 
 
 On Mon, Jan 6, 2014 at 2:46 PM, Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:
 Dear colleagues,
 
  
 
 I would recommend Prof. Kevin Walsh’s post (here:  
 http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2014/01/what-does-the-form-that-the-government-insists-the-little-sisters-of-the-poor-must-sign-actually-do.html)
  on the issue with which Marty kicked off this thread a few days ago.  
 Kevin’s post is called “What does the form that the government insists the 
 Little Sisters of the Poor must sign actually do?”
 
  
 
 Of course, others have moved from the specific issues that Marty raised to 
 more general (and always important) conversations about RFRA’s 
 constitutionality and the moral desirability of Yoder, but I wanted to ask 
 just a few things with respect to Greg Lipper’s report that Americans 
 United for Separation of Church  State has filed a motion seeking to 
 intervene in the University of Notre Dame’s lawsuit challenging the 
 mandate.  (Although I am blessed to teach at Notre Dame, I have no role in 
 the University’s lawsuit.)
 https://www.au.org/media/press-releases/americans-united-seeks-to-intervene-in-notre-dame-lawsuit-challenging-womens
 
  
 
 I understand (though I do not agree with) the claim that, because Notre 
 Dame is a large employer in the area, its right to refuse to provide 
 coverage for contraceptives (in cases where a physician has not indicated 
 that the contraceptives are medically indicated) to employees who do not 
 embrace the Catholic Church’s teachings on sexual morality and abortion is 
 limited.  That is, Notre Dame’s role and place in the market limits its 
 right to say to employees “this is who we are, and if you want to work for 
 us, you should expect that who we are will be relevant to the terms of our 
 arrangement with you.”
 
  
 
 With respect to students, though, it is harder for me to see why Notre Dame 
 should not be able to say to prospective students (as Notre Dame does), 
 “This is who we are.  If you come here – and you are welcome to, but you 
 don’t have to – you should know that our character, mission, aspirations, 
 and values will shape the terms of our arrangement with you.”   Is it the 
 view of AU, or of others, that the Establishment Clause (or anything else) 
 prevents the government from exempting a Catholic (or other 
 mission-oriented) educational institution from an otherwise general rule in 
 order to allow the institution to say (something like) this to students and 
 the broader world – again, assuming that students who get into Notre Dame 
 (a) have plenty of options and (b) know full well that Notre Dame aspires 
 to a meaningfully Catholic character?
 
  
 
 Best,
 
  
 
 Rick
 
  
 
 Richard W. Garnett
 
 Professor of Law and Concurrent Professor of Political Science
 
 Director, Program on Church, State  Society
 
 Notre Dame Law School
 
 P.O. Box 780
 
 Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780
 
 574-631-6981 (w)
 
 574-276-2252 (cell)
 
 rgarn...@nd.edu
 
  
 
 To download my scholarly papers, please visit my SSRN page
 
  
 
 Blogs:
 
  
 
 Prawfsblawg
 
 Mirror of Justice
 
  
 
 Twitter:  @RickGarnett
 
  
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Friday, January 03, 2014 1:42 PM
 
 
 To: Law  Religion

Re: The nonprofit contraception services cases

2014-01-06 Thread Marci Hamilton
This reminds me of the religious organizations
who tell their employees in writing that they do not discriminate but when they 
get sued for discrimination
argue the ministerial exception. 

   Religious employers appear to be no different from any other in seeking the 
most beneficial position at the
expense of employees or others.   The question
is whether courts will hold them to their
previous statements and positions.

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Jan 6, 2014, at 4:21 PM, Greg Lipper lip...@au.org wrote:
 
 One further note, related to Marci’s question, and detailed in our 
 intervention papers: Notre Dame has emphasized the secular nature of its 
 benefits when in its legal interests to do so. 
 
 In Laskowski v. Spellings, 546 F.3d 822 (7th Cir. 2008), an Establishment 
 Clause challenge to public funding of a teacher-training program at Notre 
 Dame, the university argued that the benefits that it provides, including 
 health insurance, are “secular expenses.” See Br. of Def.-Intervenor-Appellee 
 at 7-8, Laskowski, No. 05-2749 (7th Cir.), 2005 WL 3739459, at *8. 
 
 And in American Jewish Congress v. Corporation for National  Community 
 Service, 323 F. Supp. 2d 44 (D.D.C. 2004), rev'd sub nom. Am. Jewish Cong. v. 
 Corp. for Nat'l.  Cmty. Serv., 399 F.3d 351 (D.C. Cir. 2005), another 
 Establishment Clause challenge to Notre Dame’s receipt of public funds, the 
 University argued that purchasing health insurance is “administrative” in 
 nature and does not constitute “religious instruction or activity.” Mem. of 
 Def.-Intervenor Univ. of Notre Dame, Am. Jewish Cong., 2003 WL 25709328,at 
 Part A, § 3, para 10.
 
 So whatever else Notre Dame may or may not do to create a religious 
 educational environment, presumably it can’t have it both ways – health 
 insurance is either a secular expense or involves religious exercise, but it 
 can’t be both at the same time.
 
 
 
 
 
 On Jan 6, 2014, at 3:44 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 
 Doesn't it depend in some way on how much 
 federal money it receives?   Again, I am
 simply asking.
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 
 
 
 On Jan 6, 2014, at 3:15 PM, Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:
 
 Notre Dame is allowed (I assume – again, I am just an employee and am not 
 involved in admissions or with the University Counsel’s work) to take 
 religion, and many other factors, into account when building its classes, 
 sure.  Does anyone believe that Notre Dame should *not* be able to conduct 
 admissions so as to, for example, admit classes that are predominantly 
 Catholic?
  
 Best,
  
 Rick
  
 Richard W. Garnett
 Professor of Law and Concurrent Professor of Political Science
 Director, Program on Church, State  Society
 Notre Dame Law School
 P.O. Box 780
 Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780
 574-631-6981 (w)
 574-276-2252 (cell)
 rgarn...@nd.edu
  
 To download my scholarly papers, please visit my SSRN page
  
 Blogs:
  
 Prawfsblawg
 Mirror of Justice
  
 Twitter:  @RickGarnett
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Monday, January 06, 2014 3:08 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: The nonprofit contraception services cases
  
 This is strictly an informational question-- is Notre Dame allowed to 
 discriminate on the basis of religion in undergraduate admission?
  
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
  
  
 
 On Jan 6, 2014, at 2:46 PM, Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:
 
 Dear colleagues,
  
 I would recommend Prof. Kevin Walsh’s post (here:  
 http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2014/01/what-does-the-form-that-the-government-insists-the-little-sisters-of-the-poor-must-sign-actually-do.html)
  on the issue with which Marty kicked off this thread a few days ago.  
 Kevin’s post is called “What does the form that the government insists the 
 Little Sisters of the Poor must sign actually do?”
  
 Of course, others have moved from the specific issues that Marty raised to 
 more general (and always important) conversations about RFRA’s 
 constitutionality and the moral desirability of Yoder, but I wanted to ask 
 just a few things with respect to Greg Lipper’s report that Americans 
 United for Separation of Church  State has filed a motion seeking to 
 intervene in the University of Notre Dame’s lawsuit challenging the 
 mandate.  (Although I am blessed to teach at Notre Dame, I have no role in 
 the University’s lawsuit.)
 https://www.au.org/media/press-releases/americans-united-seeks-to-intervene-in-notre-dame-lawsuit-challenging-womens
  
 I understand (though I do not agree with) the claim that, because

Re: The nonprofit contraception services cases

2014-01-06 Thread Marci Hamilton
Ok-- I am confused.  Is Derek saying federal funds subsidiz Notre Dame's health 
care system?   

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Jan 6, 2014, at 8:45 PM, Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org wrote:
 
 It seems to me that there is a much less nefarious explanation.  In the 
 context of those Establishment Clause challenges, it was permissible for a 
 religious entity like Notre Dame to receive the government funds so long as 
 they were not used for items deemed to be inherently religious activities 
 such as worship or instruction.   In saying that the provision of health 
 insurance was a secular expense, Notre Dame was merely distinguishing such 
 expenses from those that might be spent on things like theological 
 instruction or wine for a mass.   But to say that the provision of health 
 insurance is a secular expense, unlike worship or instruction, says nothing 
 about whether Notre Dame can and does apply its religious beliefs to what 
 type of health insurance it provides.Moreover, it would also be an 
 “administrative” or “secular” expense (as opposed to inherently religious) 
 for Notre Dame to pay for the salary of someone running one of its government 
 grant programs, but that doesn’t mean Notre Dame can’t apply its religious 
 beliefs and criteria to selecting those that it hires.So I think it is 
 fair to say that there can be secular expenses (as opposed to inherently 
 religious) under Establishment Clause jurisprudence that still involve the 
 exercise of religious beliefs by a religious entity.  
  
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 
  
 This reminds me of the religious organizations
 who tell their employees in writing that they do not discriminate but when 
 they get sued for discrimination
 argue the ministerial exception. 
  
Religious employers appear to be no different from any other in seeking 
 the most beneficial position at the
 expense of employees or others.   The question
 is whether courts will hold them to their
 previous statements and positions.
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 
 On Jan 6, 2014, at 4:21 PM, Greg Lipper lip...@au.org wrote:
 
 One further note, related to Marci’s question, and detailed in our 
 intervention papers: Notre Dame has emphasized the secular nature of its 
 benefits when in its legal interests to do so. 
  
 In Laskowski v. Spellings, 546 F.3d 822 (7th Cir. 2008), an Establishment 
 Clause challenge to public funding of a teacher-training program at Notre 
 Dame, the university argued that the benefits that it provides, including 
 health insurance, are “secular expenses.” See Br. of Def.-Intervenor-Appellee 
 at 7-8, Laskowski, No. 05-2749 (7th Cir.), 2005 WL 3739459, at *8. 
  
 And in American Jewish Congress v. Corporation for National  Community 
 Service, 323 F. Supp. 2d 44 (D.D.C. 2004), rev'd sub nom. Am. Jewish Cong. v. 
 Corp. for Nat'l.  Cmty. Serv., 399 F.3d 351 (D.C. Cir. 2005), another 
 Establishment Clause challenge to Notre Dame’s receipt of public funds, the 
 University argued that purchasing health insurance is “administrative” in 
 nature and does not constitute “religious instruction or activity.” Mem. of 
 Def.-Intervenor Univ. of Notre Dame, Am. Jewish Cong., 2003 WL 25709328,at 
 Part A, § 3, para 10.
  
 So whatever else Notre Dame may or may not do to create a religious 
 educational environment, presumably it can’t have it both ways – health 
 insurance is either a secular expense or involves religious exercise, but it 
 can’t be both at the same time.
  
  
 On Jan 6, 2014, at 3:44 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
  
 
 Doesn't it depend in some way on how much 
 federal money it receives?   Again, I am
 simply asking.
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
  
 
 On Jan 6, 2014, at 3:15 PM, Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:
 
 Notre Dame is allowed (I assume – again, I am just an employee and am not 
 involved in admissions or with the University Counsel’s work) to take 
 religion, and many other factors, into account when building its classes, 
 sure.  Does anyone believe that Notre Dame should *not* be able to conduct 
 admissions so as to, for example, admit classes that are predominantly 
 Catholic?
  
 Best,
  
 Rick
  
 Richard W. Garnett
 Professor of Law and Concurrent Professor of Political Science
 Director, Program on Church, State  Society
 Notre Dame Law School
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly

Re: RFRA's constitutionality

2014-01-05 Thread Marci Hamilton
.
 
   Jon
 
 On 2014-01-04 11:29, Marci Hamilton wrote:
 Marty-- I apologize for missing this because I think it raises an
 important distinction. Thanks for raising it.
 
 I am saying in part that Smith supports a reading of beyond the
 judicial ken, but I was basing my argument more on the Court's
 structural jurisprudence (which Boerne fits squarely into) where the
 branches (and state vs fed govt) have distinguishable stronger and
 weaker capacities (which may overlap in some instances). In my view
 courts legitimately take over the primary legislative role of policy
 setting (which is what strict scrutiny is) in cases where there is
 strong suspicion of a constitutional violation, eg, race based
 distinctions or a law that is not neutral or generally applicable.
 
 It is illegitimate for them to take over the legislative role when
 the law does not create a strong suspicion of a constitutional
 violation, eg, a neutral, generally applicable law. In the RFRA,
 RLUIPA cases, we routinely see federal courts answering questions they
 have no capacity to answer, either from judicial inexperience (land
 use in particular) or because the parties and rules of evidence and
 their own institutional restrictions make it impossible to build a
 record that will yield a well-reasoned or at least informed public
 policy. If we were in a civil court system, or courts could hold
 open hearings, or have a free-ranging discussion unrestricted to the
 parties' facts and agendas, and most importantly. had no case or
 controversy clause, I might think differently. But I think all of
 those entrenched features of the federal court system make RFRA and
 RLUIPA toxic to sound public policy.
 
 I do not think that O Centro speaks to this at all and actually Cutter
 cuts in my direction in my view, because the Court was so careful to
 explain that the prison provisions apply to the most possible severe
 deprivations of religious liberty, plainly limited its reasoning to
 both the Establishment Clause in cases where there is an extreme
 deprivation and explicitly said it was not addressing the land use
 side. In addition, J Thomas's concurrence implicitly invites
 structural or congressional power attacks.
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton
 
 On Dec 30, 2013, at 7:18 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com
 [2] wrote:
 
 See
 
 http://www.jstor.org/stable/1073407 [1]
 
 Of course, if a statute incorporates a constitutional test that,
 according to the Court, had required it to do things no article III
 court could do -- which is one reading of Smith, namely, that
 application of the Sherbert/Yoder test was beyond the judicial ken
 -- then the statute is unconstitutional for having borrowed the
 constitutional test.
 
 That was, as I recall, Marci's reading of Smith -- and not an
 unreasonable reading, given Scalia's rationale. But I think it fair
 to say that the Court rejected that reading of Smith -- and of the
 Court's own alleged institutional disability -- in Cutter, and
 implicitly in O Centro.
 
 Marci
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton
 
 
 
 Links:
 --
 [1] http://www.jstor.org/stable/1073407
 [2] mailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: RFRA's constitutionality

2014-01-05 Thread Marci Hamilton
That reality is compounded by the presence of sibling incest and the 
community's choice to stand behind the boy and expel a girl who tells on the 
boy.   

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Jan 5, 2014, at 4:21 PM, Judy Baer j-b...@pols.tamu.edu wrote:
 
 Marci, I share your discomfort with Yoder.
 
 Martha Nussbaum wrote that the impact of Yoder was worse for Amish girls than 
 for Amish boys, because the boys learned marketable skills and the girls did 
 not. So it was harder for girls to leave the community.
 
 Judy Baer
 
 Sent from my iPhone
 
 On Jan 5, 2014, at 11:41 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 
 Michael-- My answers are interlineated below  
 
 
 
 
 1. Congress never debated the contraception mandate as part of Obamacare.  
 Thus the religious right never lost in Congress,
 I do not think this meets my point.  The paid lobbyists for many religious 
 groups watched this statute closely and let their views be known.   You 
 don't need a floor debate to lose in Congress.   In fact, that describes
 most legislation. Moreover, if they hadn't been paying attention, that is a 
 political loss in our system.
 
 2. Are there any reports of any women objecting formally?  I understand 
 they are the group that you claim are harmed, but surely they could sue and 
 properly bring this issue.  In reality, the vast majority of women will 
 either receive coverage or continue to buy ella and Plan B (for-profit 
 cases rarely oppose traditional contraception.)  Sandra Fluke will get her 
 contraception-- she's not working for one of the few companies impacted.
 
 It makes no sense to risk your job
 until the courts rule on whether employers have RFRA rights to carve up 
 health plans according
 to their religious lights.  We shall see what is really at stake once the 
 Court rules.   
 
 
 3.The Establishment Clause sheds light on this because the contraception 
 mandate pushes some religions out of a debate that has been very real on 
 the value of contraception.  You are assuming contraception helps women, 
 and undoubtedly it helps many.  But that is a value judgement, and the 
 administration is using a regulation to try and end a debate on this (as I 
 noted above, without Congress's approval.
 
 As a scientific matter, fully supported by many scientists, contraception 
 helps the entire society by reducing
 health costs, freeing women to choose when to have children (ie, releasing 
 them from biological determination), treating rape victims, and treating 
 many serious illnesses including endometriosis.   Those are facts, which are 
 included in the women's health care study which was basis of the 
 contraceptive mandate.
 
 4. There are only about 50 for-profit cases in a nation of hundreds of 
 thousands of for-profit businesses.  As of today, the exemption being 
 argued for is extremely narrow, and it is unfair to say this is a vast war 
 on women when this is a lot like Yoder, where few will want this exception.
 
 
 The exemption being requested has no meaningful boundary.  The argument 
 applies equally to emergency contraception and blood transfusions. In my 
 view, treatment of a rape victim is as compelling an interest as a blood 
 transfusion (treatment a Jehovah's Witness employer would object to).  If 
 these employers win, I expect children's vaccinations are next.
 
 
 Yoder opened the door for the many parents who claim a religious reason not 
 to send their children to school, to the detriment of those children.I 
 am not nearly as sanguine about Yoder as others, because my focus is on the 
 needs of each and every child.   
 
 
  Marci
 
 
 
 On Sun, Jan 5, 2014 at 7:13 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 Well-said!  The irony w RFRA is that it is a majoritarian statute parading 
 as a minority rights statute.   In the US, religious lobbyists are some of 
 our most powerful.   Their political purse, will,and power is 
 extraordinary.   RFRA plays to their worst instincts by giving them a 
 second, large bite of the apple.
 
  As the Hobby Lobby cases illustrate so well: having lost the 
 anti-contraception battle in Congress, and the executive branch, despite 
 their enormous power especially when they band together, individual 
 religious actors can then go into a federal court w a standard designed to 
 hand-tailor the law to each of them.
 
 Who are the losers this time?  Those traditionally oppressed or ignored,  
 women.   Next time it will be children (clergy abuse/ medical 
 neglect/abandonment in polygamous marriages).   Or unorganized taxpayers 
 (RLUIPA). Or unpaid creditors (diocesan bankruptcies).  It is no answer to 
 say the govt has a compelling interest vis a vis even children, because 
 the least restrictive means invites the uninformed/misinformed judge to 
 carve up the law to the benefit of the believer.
 
 Marci
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil

Re: RFRA's constitutionality

2014-01-05 Thread Marci Hamilton
Jon--  I do not believe you can separate those realities.  The law is just a 
line drawn around conduct.   RFRA and Yoder move that line.  When the line is 
moved, we must ask as a civilized society who is harmed.   In the case of 
Yoder, more
Children are harmed with the movement of that line.   It is simply a fact.   
And once again, children and females are the ones who pay the price

Same is true for polygamy.

Off list topic--Hundreds of social science studies disprove the  assumption 
that child abuse is overreported.  Quite the opposite in fact

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



 On Jan 5, 2014, at 5:49 PM, mallamud malla...@camden.rutgers.edu wrote:
 
 I have reservations about equating the decision in Yoder with the endorsement 
 of the specific practices that make Judy, Marci and others uncomfortable.  A 
 short answer is the same as I would give for polygamy. There are less 
 restrictive means of dealing with the evils than outlawing the legitimate 
 religious aspects of a long-existing community. Allowing exceptions from some 
 child-protective laws (such as school attendance) does not mean not policing 
 abuses. Rather than a freedom of religion question, these concerns raise the 
 issue of how far the state should intrude into domestic life.  While we all 
 do not like to see children harmed, what justifies state intrusion raises 
 substantial issues of what it means to live in a free country.  I fear that 
 child abuse reporting laws, giving immunity for reporting child abuse, have 
 been abused and certainly give rise to the potential for abuse.  But we also 
 have many egalitarian and intentional and utopian communities both religious !
 and not based on religion.  This this takes me off list and this is really 
beyond the scope of religion law, I just want to say that I would not judge the 
wisdom of the decision in Yoder by the fact that one can find abusive practices 
in Amish communities.
 
Jon
 
 On 2014-01-05 16:56, Marci Hamilton wrote:
 That reality is compounded by the presence of sibling incest and the
 community's choice to stand behind the boy and expel a girl who tells
 on the boy.
 
 Marci
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton
 
 On Jan 5, 2014, at 4:21 PM, Judy Baer j-b...@pols.tamu.edu [16]
 wrote:
 
 Marci, I share your discomfort with Yoder.
 
 Martha Nussbaum wrote that the impact of Yoder was worse for Amish
 girls than for Amish boys, because the boys learned marketable
 skills and the girls did not. So it was harder for girls to leave
 the community.
 
 Judy Baer
 
 Sent from my iPhone
 
 On Jan 5, 2014, at 11:41 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com
 [13] wrote:
 
 Michael-- My answers are interlineated below
 
 1. Congress never debated the contraception mandate as part of
 Obamacare. Thus the religious right never lost in Congress,
 
 I do not think this meets my point. The paid lobbyists for many
 religious groups watched this statute closely and let their views
 be known. You don't need a floor debate to lose in Congress. In
 fact, that describes
 most legislation. Moreover, if they hadn't been paying attention,
 that is a political loss in our system.
 
 2. Are there any reports of any women objecting formally? I
 understand they are the group that you claim are harmed, but
 surely they could sue and properly bring this issue. In reality,
 the vast majority of women will either receive coverage or
 continue to buy ella and Plan B (for-profit cases rarely oppose
 traditional contraception.) Sandra Fluke will get her
 contraception-- she's not working for one of the few companies
 impacted.
 
 It makes no sense to risk your job
 until the courts rule on whether employers have RFRA rights to
 carve up health plans according
 to their religious lights. We shall see what is really at stake
 once the Court rules.
 
 3.The Establishment Cla
 
 because the contraception mandate pushes some religions out of a
 debate that has been very real on the value of contraception.
 You are assuming contraception helps women, and undoubtedly it
 helps many. But that is a value judgement, and the
 administration is using a regulation to try and end a debate on
 this (as I noted above, without Congress's approval.
 
 As a scientific matter, fully suppor
 cientists, contraception helps the entire society by reducing
 health costs, freeing women to choose when to have children (ie,
 releasing them from biological determination), treating rape
 victims, and treating many serious illnesses including
 endometriosis. Those are facts, which are included in the women's
 health care study which was basis of the contraceptive mandate.
 
 4. There are only about 50 for-profit cases in a nation of
 
 for-profit businesses. As of today, the exemption being argued
 for is extremely narrow, and it is unfair

RFRA's constitutionality

2014-01-04 Thread Marci Hamilton

Marty-- I apologize for missing this because I think it raises an important 
distinction.  Thanks for raising it.

  I am saying in part that Smith supports a reading of beyond the judicial ken, 
but I was basing my argument more on the Court's structural jurisprudence 
(which Boerne fits squarely into) where the branches (and state vs fed govt) 
have distinguishable stronger and weaker capacities (which may overlap in some 
instances).   In my view courts legitimately take over the primary legislative 
role of policy setting (which is what strict scrutiny is) in cases where there 
is strong suspicion of a constitutional violation, eg, race based distinctions 
or a law that is not neutral or generally applicable.

  It is illegitimate for them to take over the legislative role when the law 
does not create a strong suspicion of a constitutional violation, eg, a 
neutral, generally applicable law.In the RFRA, RLUIPA cases, we routinely 
see federal courts answering questions they have no capacity to answer, either 
from judicial inexperience (land use in particular) or because the parties and 
rules of evidence and their own institutional restrictions make it impossible 
to build a record that will yield a well-reasoned or at least informed public 
policy.  If we were in a civil court system, or courts could hold
open hearings, or have a free-ranging discussion unrestricted to the parties' 
facts and agendas, and most importantly. had no case or controversy clause, I 
might think differently.   But I think all of those entrenched features of the 
federal court system make RFRA and RLUIPA toxic to sound public policy.

I do not think that O Centro speaks to this at all and actually Cutter cuts in 
my direction in my view, because the Court was so careful to explain that the 
prison provisions apply to the most possible severe deprivations of religious 
liberty, plainly limited its reasoning to both the Establishment Clause in 
cases where there is an extreme deprivation and explicitly said it was not 
addressing the land use side.  In addition, J Thomas's concurrence implicitly 
invites structural or congressional power attacks.   



Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 30, 2013, at 7:18 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:

 See
 
 http://www.jstor.org/stable/1073407
 
 Of course, if a statute incorporates a constitutional test that, according to 
 the Court, had required it to do things no article III court could do -- 
 which is one reading of Smith, namely, that application of the Sherbert/Yoder 
 test was beyond the judicial ken -- then the statute is unconstitutional for 
 having borrowed the constitutional test.  
 
 That was, as I recall, Marci's reading of Smith -- and not an unreasonable 
 reading, given Scalia's rationale.  But I think it fair to say that the Court 
 rejected that reading of Smith -- and of the Court's own alleged 
 institutional disability -- in Cutter, and implicitly in O Centro.
 
Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: The nonprofit contraception services cases

2014-01-03 Thread Marci Hamilton
Marty-- could you please elaborate on your response?  I am not following this 
exchange

Thanks--
Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Jan 3, 2014, at 12:43 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:

 They will -- the government realizes that its plan is undermined and is 
 reassessing
 
 Sent from my iPhone
 
 On Jan 3, 2014, at 12:08 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
 
 Why don't all these religious nonprofits choose Christian Brothers Services 
 as their health insurer?  That way, certification or not, the employees will 
 not receive the services to which the employer objects?  Something is 
 missing from this narrative.
 
 
 Sent from my iPhone
 
 On Jan 3, 2014, at 10:56 AM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
 
 The government's brief in Little Sisters:
 
 http://balkin.blogspot.com/2014/01/government-bref-in-little-sisters.html
 
 
 On Wed, Jan 1, 2014 at 5:34 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 
 wrote:
 Another post, this one about the nonprofit cases that have now wound their 
 way to the Court . . .
 
 http://balkin.blogspot.com/2014/01/not-quite-hobby-lobby-nonprofit-cases.html
 
 
 On Mon, Dec 16, 2013 at 1:53 PM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 
 wrote:
 Since no one else has mentioned it, I will:  
 
 Eugene recently published a remarkable series of posts on the case -- so 
 much there that virtually everyone on this listserv is sure to agree with 
 some arguments and disagree with others.  It's an amazing public service, 
 whatever one thinks of the merits.  He and I turned the posts into a 
 single, 53-page (single-spaced!) Word document for your convenience:
 
 www.volokh.com/wp-content/uploads/2013/12/hobbylobby.docx
 
 I've just started my own series of posts on the case on Balkinization -- 
 links to the first three below.  The second is about the thorny 
 contraception/abortifacient issue (nominally) in play in the two cases 
 the Court granted.  In the third post, I endeavor to explain that the 
 case is fundamentally different from what all the courts and plaintiffs 
 (and press) have assumed, because there is in fact no employer mandate 
 to provide contraception coverage.
 
 http://balkin.blogspot.com/2013/12/hobby-lobby-part-i-framing-issues.html
 
 http://balkin.blogspot.com/2013/12/hobby-lobby-part-ii-whats-it-all-about.html
 
 http://balkin.blogspot.com/2013/12/hobby-lobby-part-iiitheres-no-employer.html
 
 Thanks to those of you who have already offered very useful provocations 
 and arguments on-list; I'd welcome further reactions, of course.
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are 
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or 
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are 
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or 
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: courts and lawmaking

2013-12-30 Thread Marci Hamilton
: courts and lawmaking
 
 
 Subject: Re: courts and lawmaking
 From: phorw...@hotmail.com
 Date: Sat, 28 Dec 2013 23:17:10 -0500
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 CC: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 
 Although I don't share this orientation, this is certainly an
 interesting
 discussion. I'm wondering how New York Times v. Sullivan and Roe v.
 Wade would
 fare under this standard, and possibly Baker v. Carr or Miranda.
 
 On Dec 28, 2013, at 10:51 PM, Marci Hamilton
 hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com
 wrote:
 
 Eugene- I take it you would not have overturned the Lochner line of
 cases?
 Your defense of unaccountable, robust policy making by judges would
 revive the
 federal court's role in those cases and reverse the reasoning of, eg,
 Williamson
 v lee optical. You have also failed to articulate any meaningful limit
 on
 federal court policy making.
 Perhaps you think there should be no limit, but that is not consistent
 w the
 separation of powers cases or the Framers' belief that all entities
 holding
 power must be limited and that one means of limitation is to assign
 different
 primary roles to each branch.
 
 also--It is not enough to say that Congress can fix a bad decision to
 excuse a
 violation of a branch's structural role.
 
 I also question your broad generalizations in describing purported
 federal
 judicial policy making . As you have to and do concede, federal common
 law is
 forbidden, so generally you are talking about cases where the federal
 courts are
 engaging in statutory interpretation. As such, they are not making law
 in the
 first instance, but rather according to canons of statutory
 construction.
 
 I think you have fundamentally confused the role of the courts with
 the results
 of particular decisions. I also think the state and federal courts
 cannot be
 equated in terms of their roles, so I am focussing on federal courts.
 
 You also have not responded to any of my concrete examples of how
 courts have
 gone wrong in religion cases because they lack critical facts where
 the fact
 record is manufactured by self-interested parties. Given the
 incontrovertible
 record of harm religious entities have inflicted on
 vulnerable populations, and the fact courts cannot pierce their
 self-serving
 crafting of the record in most circumstances, the role of the courts
 you
 describe is likely to harm minorities, children, the disabled, and
 women. Not
 to mention employees generally in light of Hosanna Tabor (remember
 employees are
 almost always vulnerable to employer acts unless protected by
 statute).
 
 For all of these reasons, I am not persuaded that your description
 of federal
 court lawmaking is accurate, and I continue to believe that RFRA puts
 federal
 courts in a role where they are institutionally incompetent. Their
 incompetence was clear in the Lochner cases. The religion cases and
 recent
 history do not make the courts anymore defensible as policymakers.
 
 Marci
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted;
 people can
 read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly)
 forward the
 messages to others.
 
 
 
 Links:
 --
 [1] http://sol-reform.com/
 [2] https://www.facebook.com/professormarciahamilton?fref=ts
 [3] https://twitter.com/marci_hamilton
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: courts and lawmaking

2013-12-30 Thread Marci Hamilton
Actually Boerne says Congress does not have the power (govts don't have rights) 
to do whatever it wants for anyone it wants.  As does the Establishment Clause, 
among other limits.

Cutter is only  an Establishment Clause challenge to the prison side of RLUIPA. 
the court explicitly does not address the land use side let alone RFRA's broad 
coverage.  Cutter does not address Congress's power. So not on point

It is simply a fact that religious entities and believers have a history of 
harming vulnerable populations.  They are humans.Smith and Lukumi protect 
religion while also protecting the vulnerable.  RFRA gives religious believers 
a hammer against others.  Hobby Lobby has extraordinary power as compared to 
its employees who presumably need the job.  

But religious entities don't only seek to overcome laws that protect the 
vulnerable so my reference to the vulnerable was only meant to be an example of 
RFRA's folly, not a comprehensive explanation of its unintended consequences.

Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 30, 2013, at 1:31 PM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:

 The only time RFRA comes into effect at all is when the religion, corporation 
 or individual asserting a RFRA right is also in a minority. In the Hobby 
 Lobby case, the issue is not the individual workers suing (perhaps why the 
 Court shouldn't entertain the Gedicks and Van Tassel theory this time), but a 
 minority religious belief suing.
 
 Marci claims RFRA is a means for religious groups to undermine minorities 
 and vulnerable populations, but in reality the government has every right to 
 give these minorities and vulnerable populations every right the government 
 wishes too (hence why RFRA is not an argument used in Windsor, or one that 
 could be used if someone tried to overturn Griswold).  The only thing it 
 cannot do is force other individuals to violate their conscience. As Cutter 
 said about RLIUPA, RFRA alleviates exceptional government-created burdens on 
 private religious exercise.
 
 In Cutter, we had government officers seeking to nullify RLIUPA by hurting 
 the religious in prison.  Likewise, in Hobby Lobby we have government 
 officers seeking to ignore RFRA by enlisting religious believers to assist 
 them by doing what the government was already doing without free exercise 
 issues.
 
 
 
 On Mon, Dec 30, 2013 at 10:08 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 There needs to be more precision in the use of the term rights.
 
 RFRA is in fact an attempt by Congress to amend the Free Exercise Clause by 
 simple majority vote.   For Congress, Smith was not the final word on the 
 interpretation of free exercise; instead it inserted Yoder as its preferred 
 interpretation, at the behest of political pressure from religious groups 
 and at the time severely misguided civil rights groups who have finally come 
 to their senses and understand that RFRA is a means for religious groups to 
 undermine minorities and vulnerable populations.
 
 RFRA employs a constitutional standard of review that references 
 constitutional cases.  It is disingenuous to treat it as anything other than 
 it is.
 
 As Boerne pointed out in a fn, as an amendment to the First Am, it violates 
 Art V's amendment requirements.
 
 If RFRA is, alternatively, a statutory rights statute, the courts have no 
 special role and are simply interpreting congressional intent,which 
 undermines Mark's points in my view.
 
 Marci
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton
 
 
 
 On Dec 30, 2013, at 12:11 PM, mallamud malla...@camden.rutgers.edu wrote:
 
  Mark's point makes sense to me: As is often the case, courts have to do 
  what they can, despite institutional difficulties, to protect rights, 
  whether constitutional or statutory. One important aspect of the division 
  of power between courts and the legislature is that when important 
  decisions do not get made politically, the Supreme Court often can save 
  the day.  Brown for example although I prefer to use cases like the Nixon 
  tapes case where the Court made a narrow decision, recognizing an 
  executive privilege subject to an exception for the production of material 
  to the grand jury in a criminal case in which the President is an 
  unindicted coconspirator.
 
But I disagree with Mark on RFRA.  I think that Smith was correct and I 
  think that the Congress, driven by political and majoritarian 
  considerations should not try to make constitutional law.  Justice Douglas 
  said that it took five years or so for a new Justice to develop an 
  approach to judging.  I always understood that to mean that a person comes 
  to the Court with a perspective and understanding honed in particular 
  contexts and that the Court took a unique and different view of things 
  because they saw

Re: courts and lawmaking

2013-12-30 Thread Marci Hamilton
 legitimate for Congress to authorize federal 
 courts to develop, in common-law-like fashion, religious exemptions to 
 various laws, just as federal courts have long developed, in common-law-like 
 fashion, defenses to criminal laws.
  
 5.  I haven’t responded to “concrete examples of how courts 
 have gone wrong in religion cases because they lack critical facts” because 
 that doesn’t tell us what’s constitutional and what’s not.  Surely 
 legislatures have often gone wrong in a  wide range of cases, including 
 religious exemption cases, because they lack critical facts because they have 
 been lobbied by self-interested lobbyists; but that doesn’t make legislative 
 decisionmaking unconstitutional.  Likewise, federal courts’ decisionmaking in 
 antitrust cases, admiralty cases, privilege cases, fair use cases, and more 
 might be said to lack critical facts for similar reasons, but that doesn’t 
 make such judicial decisionmaking unconstitutional.  Similarly, legislatures’ 
 letting courts recognize religious exemptions isn’t made unconstitutional by 
 the fact that courts will sometimes err in such recognition. 
  
 6.  That some Congressionally prescribed allocation of decisionmaking 
 authority is said by some to on balance harm “minorities, children, the 
 disabled, and women” (a position that seems to me far from clear, given that 
 “minorities” includes religious minorities) doesn’t make it constitutionally 
 impermissible.
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Saturday, December 28, 2013 5:29 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics (religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu)
 Subject: Re: courts and lawmaking
  
 Eugene-  I take it you would not have overturned the Lochner line of cases?
 Your defense of unaccountable, robust policy making by judges would revive 
 the federal court's role in those cases and reverse the reasoning of, eg, 
 Williamson v lee optical.You have also failed to articulate any 
 meaningful limit on federal court policy making.   
 Perhaps you think there should be no limit, but that is not consistent w the 
 separation of powers cases or the Framers' belief that all entities holding 
 power must be limited and that one means of limitation is to assign different 
 primary roles to each branch.  
  
 also--It is not enough to say that Congress can fix a bad decision to excuse 
 a violation of a branch's structural role.   
  
 I also question your broad generalizations in describing purported federal 
 judicial policy making .   As you have to and do concede, federal common law 
 is forbidden, so generally you are talking about cases where the federal 
 courts are engaging in statutory interpretation.  As such, they are not 
 making law in the first instance, but rather according to canons of statutory 
 construction.  
  
 I think you have fundamentally confused the role of the courts with the 
 results of particular decisions.   I also think the state and federal courts 
 cannot be equated in terms of their roles, so I am focussing on federal 
 courts.
  
 You also have not responded to any of my concrete examples of how courts have 
 gone wrong in religion cases because they lack critical facts where the fact 
 record is manufactured by self-interested parties.   Given the 
 incontrovertible record of harm religious entities have inflicted on
 vulnerable populations, and the fact courts cannot pierce their self-serving 
 crafting of the record in most circumstances, the role of the courts you 
 describe is likely to harm minorities, children, the disabled, and women.
 Not to mention employees generally in light of Hosanna Tabor (remember 
 employees are almost always vulnerable to employer acts unless protected by 
 statute).   
  
 For all of these reasons, I am not persuaded that your description of 
 federal court lawmaking is accurate, and  I continue to believe that RFRA 
 puts federal courts in a role where they are institutionally incompetent.
 Their incompetence was clear in the Lochner cases.  The religion cases and 
 recent history do not make the courts anymore defensible as policymakers.
  
  
  
 Marci
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman

Re: Are large employers really better off dropping health insurance?

2013-12-28 Thread Marci Hamilton
The holidays have made it difficult to keep up but I did want to respond to 
Michael.   The notion that the distinguishing of Sherbert and Yoder were pure 
legal fictions in Smith is unpersuasive.With respect to Sherbert, the 
Court's reasoning is actually accurate and reflects the Court's understanding 
of Smith as a case of first impression as the Justice's Conference notes show.

The distinguishing of Yoder is unpersuasive but it appears the Court was 
reinforcing what Yoder was until RFRA -- an outlier.  Literally the only case 
to apply strict scrutiny to a neutral, generally applicable law, with little or 
no precedential value.   Its value is even more questionable today when 
children's interests would have to be taken into account and, therefore, 
Douglass's view would likely change the result, especially now that we have 
strong evidence of the harm done to Amish children by the failure to educate 
them.

All of this matters, because it is my view that RFRA in these cases is as 
unconstitutional as it was in Boerne.  The Court did not limit its reasoning to 
state law and relied explicitly on separation of powers.  Politics, not the 
Court, transformed Boerne into a decision only relevant to state law.As I 
have said before, and may have missed either Eugene's or Marty's responses over 
the holiday, their debate is one the courts are ill-suited to decide. 

If the Court takes this approach, the mandate cases will be an excellent 
example of how RFRA turns courts into legislatures and makes them lawmakers (in 
the tradition actually of the Lochner cases where strict scrutiny was employed 
to permit the courts to second guess employment laws), without the competence 
to do so.  

The problem of course is that the DOJ has failed to attack RFRA's 
constitutionality but that is, once again, politics, not constitutional 
analysis.


Marci


Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 18, 2013, at 4:54 PM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:

 You have a fair point;  I'm uncomfortable with Reynolds, but that doesn't 
 mean there weren't less protections for religion pre-incorporation.  However, 
 the distinguishing of Yoder and Sherbert (not to mention Cantwell) in Smith 
 is just a legal fiction Scalia made up.  The Law Review article by James D. 
 Gordon III Free exercise on the Mountaintop illustrates well the problems 
 with the theory that Smith was right
 
 
 On Wed, Dec 18, 2013 at 2:37 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 This reasoning is based on the mythology created around the free exercise 
 clause by the reactions to Smith and the misrepresentations about the 
 doctrine to Congress.  It is quite remarkable this many years later so many 
 continue to parrot what is in fact untrue.  Yoder was an outlier and 
 Sherbert was not applied outside unemployment.  And the Justices thought in 
 those terms during the Term Smith was decided.
 
   Now folks may well want a different regime than pre-Smith but it would be 
 refreshing to see at least scholars (if not litigators) accurately discuss 
 the actual doctrine and not the doctrine they prefer.   
 
 The New York ACA case yesterday including indefensible reasoning on what 
 RFRA is and what the doctrine was before.  For example, the court cites to 
 Michael mcConnell's article, for the proposition that mandatory exemptions 
 were common at the time of the framing, a theory the Justices have rejected 
 and Ellis West and Philip Hamburger have shown to be deeply flawed 
 historically.  In my own work on liberty vs licentiousness, it is abundantly 
 clear the framers were far closer to the Smith way of reasoning than 
 mandatory accommodation.
 
 Marci
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 
 
 
 On Dec 18, 2013, at 9:45 AM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:
 
 And yet, without some form of heightened scrutiny, the free exercise clause 
 becomes a shell-- a hollow clause.  I'm not saying RFRA gets the balancing 
 right (I could make that argument, but I'm not), I'm saying that we have to 
 let judges do this balancing in some way.  Otherwise the Free Exercise 
 Clause will become as important as the Ninth Amendment is to contemporary 
 jurisprudence.  And Employment Division's principles apply to churches, not 
 just the litigants in this set of cases.
 
 There are plenty of 14th Amendment cases (think Brown and subsequent busing 
 cases in lower courts) where judges have acted as super-legislatures. 
 Why?  To protect rights!
 
 Michael
 
 
 On Wed, Dec 18, 2013 at 3:46 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 This exchange, which shows both Marty and Eugene's high qualifications for 
 public service, underscores how RFRA (and RLUIPA) turn federal courts into 
 super legislatures and violate the separation of powers -- as Boerne 
 ruled.  No court in my

Re: courts and lawmaking

2013-12-28 Thread Marci Hamilton
Eugene-  I take it you would not have overturned the Lochner line of cases?
Your defense of unaccountable, robust policy making by judges would revive the 
federal court's role in those cases and reverse the reasoning of, eg, 
Williamson v lee optical.You have also failed to articulate any meaningful 
limit on federal court policy making.   
Perhaps you think there should be no limit, but that is not consistent w the 
separation of powers cases or the Framers' belief that all entities holding 
power must be limited and that one means of limitation is to assign different 
primary roles to each branch.  

also--It is not enough to say that Congress can fix a bad decision to excuse a 
violation of a branch's structural role.   

I also question your broad generalizations in describing purported federal 
judicial policy making .   As you have to and do concede, federal common law is 
forbidden, so generally you are talking about cases where the federal courts 
are engaging in statutory interpretation.  As such, they are not making law in 
the first instance, but rather according to canons of statutory construction.  

I think you have fundamentally confused the role of the courts with the results 
of particular decisions.   I also think the state and federal courts cannot be 
equated in terms of their roles, so I am focussing on federal courts.

You also have not responded to any of my concrete examples of how courts have 
gone wrong in religion cases because they lack critical facts where the fact 
record is manufactured by self-interested parties.   Given the incontrovertible 
record of harm religious entities have inflicted on
vulnerable populations, and the fact courts cannot pierce their self-serving 
crafting of the record in most circumstances, the role of the courts you 
describe is likely to harm minorities, children, the disabled, and women.
Not to mention employees generally in light of Hosanna Tabor (remember 
employees are almost always vulnerable to employer acts unless protected by 
statute).   

For all of these reasons, I am not persuaded that your description of federal 
court lawmaking is accurate, and  I continue to believe that RFRA puts federal 
courts in a role where they are institutionally incompetent.Their 
incompetence was clear in the Lochner cases.  The religion cases and recent 
history do not make the courts anymore defensible as policymakers.



Marci

 



Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 28, 2013, at 5:53 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 But courts have made rules in the past regarding substantive 
 law as well -- what shall be a crime, what shall be a tort, what constitutes 
 a contract, what property rights are recognized, and so on.  They continue to 
 make such rules in many areas, less so with regard to substantive criminal 
 law but, in many jurisdictions, as to criminal law defenses.  These decisions 
 often involve broad-ranging public policy issues, such as what product 
 liability regime to have, whether to recognize various limitations on duty 
 (such as social host rules), whether the heart balm torts should be 
 abrogated, whether the criminal law necessity defense is recognized, and so 
 on.  To be sure, they might err on this, partly because their factfinding 
 sources are more limited, but the legislature can step in to correct those 
 errors.  Each branch has its own limitation, but the American tradition is 
 that they have made law together.
  
 And this tradition has included the federal courts.  It’s 
 true that in diversity cases there is no general federal common law, and that 
 common law crimes were rejected by federal courts long before the penal codes 
 were codified in the states.  But in those areas where the federal government 
 has broad authority -- such as admiralty law, federal enclaves, or 
 substantive defenses to federal crimes -- federal courts have unsurprisingly 
 followed much the same path as state courts.
  
 I don’t see why legislative authorization to federal courts 
 to engage in such continued decisionmaking -- whether as to judicial practice 
 and procedure (evidence), substantive copyright law (fair use), implicitly as 
 to substantive criminal law defenses, or as to a newly statutory religious 
 objection defense (the best way of viewing RFRA, I think, and analogous to 
 fair use and the criminal law defenses) -- is at all unconstitutional, 
 whether done by state legislatures using state RFRAs or by Congress using the 
 federal RFRA.  If Congress or a state legislature doesn’t like a specific 
 exemption granted under a RFRA, it can legislatively exclude that subject 
 from the RFRA, and if it generally doesn’t like judicial decisionmaking under 
 RFRAs, it can repeal the RFRA.  But there is no basis, I think, for courts to 
 say that it’s unconstitutional for 

Re: Are large employers really better off dropping health insurance?

2013-12-18 Thread Marci Hamilton
This exchange, which shows both Marty and Eugene's high qualifications for 
public service, underscores how RFRA (and RLUIPA) turn federal courts into 
super legislatures and violate the separation of powers -- as Boerne ruled.  No 
court in my view is institutionally competent to make these assessments and no 
judge, who is unaccountable to the electorate, should.  

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 17, 2013, at 9:10 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 The heart of Marty’s argument (I focus for now on item 1 below) is, I think, 
 an empirical claim:  Large employers such as Hobby Lobby would be better off 
 just dropping coverage, paying the $2000/employee/year tax, “us[ing] some of 
 [the] enormous cost savings” to compensate employees for the lost coverage, 
 thus keeping the employees happy, and then pocketing the rest of the 
 “enormous cost savings.”  (Indeed, if employees grumble over the 
 inconvenience or just the change, the employers can split some of the rest of 
 the enormous cost savings with the employees -- a win-win proposition for 
 employers and employees.)  And, if Marty is right, this would be true for 
 employers generally, not just religious employers.  We should thus expect a 
 large fraction of savvy employers to take advantage of this option, purely 
 out of respect for Mammon quite regardless of God.
  
 But I wonder whether this is empirically likely to be true, given not just 
 the nondeductibility of the tax, but also other factors, such as payroll 
 taxes on the compensation payment to the employees.  It’s not surprising that 
 the Justice Department hasn’t made this argument, since the Administration 
 has long argued (unless I’m mistaken) that large employers won’t drop 
 employer-based health insurance.  And the Congressional Budget Office, 
 http://www.cbo.gov/sites/default/files/cbofiles/ftpdocs/121xx/doc12119/03-30-healthcarelegislation.pdf,
  likewise took the view that only a tiny percentage of employers would drop 
 their health insurance, because “the legislation leaves in place substantial 
 financial advantages for many people to receive insurance coverage through 
 their employers, and it provides some new incentives for employers to offer 
 insurance coverage to their employees.” 
  
 Now of course that was in 2011, and perhaps the analysis today would be 
 different.  But the CBO’s estimates still give me pause.  And if the CBO is 
 right, and large employers generally would lose financially -- rather than 
 gain from capturing some of the “enormous cost savings” -- by dropping health 
 insurance and adequately compensating employees, then I would think Hobby 
 Lobby and others would be in the same position.  The mandate, even enforced 
 as a tax, thus would be a substantial burden.
  
 Am I mistaken in this?  Marty, do you have any pointers to studies that 
 support your sense of the money flows on this, and contradict what I see as 
 the CBO’s view?
  
 Eugene
  
  
 Marty writes:
  
 1.  On your first point, even if the 4980H(a) tax were the equivalent of a 
 $3000 assessment (because it's paid with after-tax dollars), the average cost 
 for providing health insurance to employees is, as I understand it, closer to 
 $10,000, so the employer would save about $7000 per employee.  (In any event, 
 there are no allegations in these cases that HL or CW is significantly 
 differently situated than a typical employer, e.g., that they have a 
 workforce comprised of almost all single employees with no family coverage.)
 
 In order to remain competitive for recruiting or retaining most of their 
 employees, the plaintiffs wouldn't have to kick in any extra money in salary, 
 because the employees would have their exchange-purchased plans subsidized by 
 the federal government (both in terms of the cost-savings realized by virtue 
 of the exchanges themselves as well as the government's premium tax credits 
 and cost-sharing reductions.  To be sure, some of their more well-compensated 
 employees might have paid less in premiums for the HL plan than they would to 
 purchase a plan on the exchange (maybe -- again, there's no allegation or 
 evidence of that here).  But to make up that hypothetical shortfall, and 
 attract those employees, HL need only use some of its enormous cost savings 
 to sweeten their salaries.  (This is presumably what the many large employers 
 who do not provide plans will do.)  
 
 For all these reasons, it is difficult to imagine HL or CW --or, more to the 
 point, the average large employer -- being financially worse off if it pays 
 the assessment.  (And again, there's no allegation of facts that would alter 
 that conclusion here, in any event.)
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 

Re: Are large employers really better off dropping health insurance?

2013-12-18 Thread Marci Hamilton
This reasoning is based on the mythology created around the free exercise 
clause by the reactions to Smith and the misrepresentations about the doctrine 
to Congress.  It is quite remarkable this many years later so many continue to 
parrot what is in fact untrue.  Yoder was an outlier and Sherbert was not 
applied outside unemployment.  And the Justices thought in those terms during 
the Term Smith was decided.

  Now folks may well want a different regime than pre-Smith but it would be 
refreshing to see at least scholars (if not litigators) accurately discuss the 
actual doctrine and not the doctrine they prefer.   

The New York ACA case yesterday including indefensible reasoning on what RFRA 
is and what the doctrine was before.  For example, the court cites to Michael 
mcConnell's article, for the proposition that mandatory exemptions were common 
at the time of the framing, a theory the Justices have rejected and Ellis West 
and Philip Hamburger have shown to be deeply flawed historically.  In my own 
work on liberty vs licentiousness, it is abundantly clear the framers were far 
closer to the Smith way of reasoning than mandatory accommodation.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 18, 2013, at 9:45 AM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:

 And yet, without some form of heightened scrutiny, the free exercise clause 
 becomes a shell-- a hollow clause.  I'm not saying RFRA gets the balancing 
 right (I could make that argument, but I'm not), I'm saying that we have to 
 let judges do this balancing in some way.  Otherwise the Free Exercise Clause 
 will become as important as the Ninth Amendment is to contemporary 
 jurisprudence.  And Employment Division's principles apply to churches, not 
 just the litigants in this set of cases.
 
 There are plenty of 14th Amendment cases (think Brown and subsequent busing 
 cases in lower courts) where judges have acted as super-legislatures. Why?  
 To protect rights!
 
 Michael
 
 
 On Wed, Dec 18, 2013 at 3:46 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 This exchange, which shows both Marty and Eugene's high qualifications for 
 public service, underscores how RFRA (and RLUIPA) turn federal courts into 
 super legislatures and violate the separation of powers -- as Boerne ruled.  
 No court in my view is institutionally competent to make these assessments 
 and no judge, who is unaccountable to the electorate, should.  
 
 Marci
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 
 
 
 On Dec 17, 2013, at 9:10 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 
 The heart of Marty’s argument (I focus for now on item 1 below) is, I 
 think, an empirical claim:  Large employers such as Hobby Lobby would be 
 better off just dropping coverage, paying the $2000/employee/year tax, 
 “us[ing] some of [the] enormous cost savings” to compensate employees for 
 the lost coverage, thus keeping the employees happy, and then pocketing the 
 rest of the “enormous cost savings.”  (Indeed, if employees grumble over 
 the inconvenience or just the change, the employers can split some of the 
 rest of the enormous cost savings with the employees -- a win-win 
 proposition for employers and employees.)  And, if Marty is right, this 
 would be true for employers generally, not just religious employers.  We 
 should thus expect a large fraction of savvy employers to take advantage of 
 this option, purely out of respect for Mammon quite regardless of God.
 
  
 
 But I wonder whether this is empirically likely to be true, given not just 
 the nondeductibility of the tax, but also other factors, such as payroll 
 taxes on the compensation payment to the employees.  It’s not surprising 
 that the Justice Department hasn’t made this argument, since the 
 Administration has long argued (unless I’m mistaken) that large employers 
 won’t drop employer-based health insurance.  And the Congressional Budget 
 Office, 
 http://www.cbo.gov/sites/default/files/cbofiles/ftpdocs/121xx/doc12119/03-30-healthcarelegislation.pdf,
  likewise took the view that only a tiny percentage of employers would drop 
 their health insurance, because “the legislation leaves in place 
 substantial financial advantages for many people to receive insurance 
 coverage through their employers, and it provides some new incentives for 
 employers to offer insurance coverage to their employees.” 
 
  
 
 Now of course that was in 2011, and perhaps the analysis today would be 
 different.  But the CBO’s estimates still give me pause.  And if the CBO is 
 right, and large employers generally would lose financially -- rather than 
 gain from capturing some of the “enormous cost savings” -- by dropping 
 health insurance and adequately compensating employees, then I would think 
 Hobby Lobby and others would be in the same position.  The mandate, even

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-07 Thread Marci Hamilton
Richard's point is fair so let me provide some more context that perhaps would 
be helpful.   

Privileges are concoctions of positive law dealing w what information can be 
excluded in the judicial process.   The confessional privilege is no different 
than the attorney client privilege or the spousal  privilege on that score.  
Every faith invokes it or tries to to avoid disclosing legally damaging 
evidence in the judicial process.  The RCC and LDS are the most active in 
lobbying to expand it in the state legislatures.

  It is always invoked in clergy sex abuse cases and to avoid mandatory 
reporting of child sex abuse.  Courts have had to struggle w the distinction 
between counseling and confession for salvation purposes, because when laws are 
violated, the exclusion of relevant evidence is to be avoided.   The privilege, 
depending on the state, belongs to the confessor or confessee and always can be 
waived but how differs state to state.  It is routinely waived if the content 
is disclosed outside the one-on-one confession. 

It is also routinely invoked to conceal information that was obtained outside 
the confessional.   

It is my view that there should be an exception to it that parallels the 
attorney client exception for future crimes or fraud.   And that it should not 
be an exception to mandatory reporting of child sex abuse.   The privilege is a 
permissive accommodation that we have learned has a corrosive effect on 
children, families, churches, and society.   Under Smith it is not required and 
under a RFRA analysis it should not overcome the needs of the judicial process 
or  mandatory reporting laws.  

I offer these examples to contextualize the discussion.   It only matters when  
it is alleged a law has been broken so that  law should be the starting point 
for discourse.

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 6, 2013, at 11:18 PM, Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu 
wrote:

 As I’ve said earlier, I’m sympathetic to Richard’s argument  inasmuch as 
 confession is in fact part of a complex (required) sacramental process.  But 
 the point is that (I think) that’s relatively unusual, certainly not present, 
 so far as I am aware, in Judaism, for example.  Am I correct in believing 
 that the ingestion of peyote was in fact a sacramental aspect of the Native 
 American church?
  
 sandy
  
 From: religionlaw-bounces+slevinson=law.utexas@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-bounces+slevinson=law.utexas@lists.ucla.edu] On 
 Behalf Of Richard Dougherty
 Sent: Friday, December 06, 2013 6:09 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
  
 I will confess to not having read the state cases, or at least not most of 
 them.  But isn't the question whether the privilege is constitutionally 
 required?  (Perhaps the fact that it is referred to as a privilege muddies 
 the waters.)  If free exercise of religion includes receiving a sacrament, 
 then why is compelling violation of the privilege not a constitutional issue? 
  Indeed, I wonder why a recent discussion suggested stronger free speech 
 claims than free exercise claims; does the First Amendment make that 
 distinction?  I have no doubt courts have read it that way, but that's partly 
 why we get distortions of free exercise claims masquerading as free speech 
 claims.
  
 Richard Dougherty
 University of Dallas
  
 
 On Fri, Dec 6, 2013 at 1:17 PM, hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 With all due respect to this entire thread, how many people have actually 
 read the state cases involving the priest-penitent privilege?  There is a 
 level of abstraction
 to this discussion that indicates to me probably not.  As someone who has 
 actively been involved in arguing the issue in court in the last year, I'd 
 suggest that the law is
 more reticulated and specific. state-by-state, than the speculation going on 
 here.  It is state law, which means 50 states plus DC law, and it is a 
 privilege that is not constitutionally required,
 particularly when the issue is whether the religious confessor or confessee 
 engaged in illegal behavior. 
  
  
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215 
 http://sol-reform.com
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics' religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Fri, Dec 6, 2013 10:06 am
 Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
 
 Again, I’m late—sorry about that.  But honestly people, it’s shocking how 
 many posts are written between the hours of 9 p.m. and 7 a.m.  Who can keep 
 up?
  
 So this may backtrack, but I’ve been thinking about the earlier posts in this 
 thread.  Say there are no secular analogies to the 

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-07 Thread Marci Hamilton
In my view, there should be no privilege for criminal acts.  

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 7, 2013, at 12:12 PM, Richard Dougherty dou...@udallas.edu wrote:

 I much appreciate Marci's comments.  From the point of view of the free 
 exercise of religion, the question for the believer, in my view, is what the 
 effect of the revelation of confidential information is on the soul of the 
 penitent, not what the legal consequences might be.  Obviously the state has 
 other concerns, but they need not clash, except at the margins (though that's 
 what really counts).  I agree that the fall-out of the abuse crisis in the 
 Catholic Church has seen some try to claim privilege where no legitimate 
 claim of privilege seems to be at stake.  The dangers of doing so are 
 multiple -- most importantly, more people are put at risk of future abuse, 
 but it also undermines legitimate claims of privilege, as those entrusted 
 with making judgments about its legitimacy find it harder to distinguish the 
 genuine from the spurious.  I'm not convinced that discussions in diocesan 
 chanceries about how to avoid losses in court are part of the free exercise 
 of religion.
 
 The abuse crisis in contemporary America (not, of course, confined to the 
 Catholic Church) is painful for what it has done to so many who have 
 suffered, and it has been devastating for the Church.  Almost all of what I 
 have seen has nothing to do with Confession or free exercise of religion, 
 though, and here I support Marci's strong view of holding responsible those 
 who have enabled abusers; while this would likely prevent subsequent abuse -- 
 the most important consequence -- it would have the side effect of calling 
 Catholics to abide by their own beliefs.
 
 Richard Dougherty
 University of Dallas
 
 
 On Sat, Dec 7, 2013 at 7:45 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 Richard's point is fair so let me provide some more context that perhaps 
 would be helpful.   
 
 Privileges are concoctions of positive law dealing w what information can be 
 excluded in the judicial process.   The confessional privilege is no 
 different than the attorney client privilege or the spousal  privilege on 
 that score.  Every faith invokes it or tries to to avoid disclosing legally 
 damaging evidence in the judicial process.  The RCC and LDS are the most 
 active in lobbying to expand it in the state legislatures.
 
   It is always invoked in clergy sex abuse cases and to avoid mandatory 
 reporting of child sex abuse.  Courts have had to struggle w the distinction 
 between counseling and confession for salvation purposes, because when laws 
 are violated, the exclusion of relevant evidence is to be avoided.   The 
 privilege, depending on the state, belongs to the confessor or confessee and 
 always can be waived but how differs state to state.  It is routinely waived 
 if the content is disclosed outside the one-on-one confession. 
 
 It is also routinely invoked to conceal information that was obtained 
 outside the confessional.   
 
 It is my view that there should be an exception to it that parallels the 
 attorney client exception for future crimes or fraud.   And that it should 
 not be an exception to mandatory reporting of child sex abuse.   The 
 privilege is a permissive accommodation that we have learned has a corrosive 
 effect on children, families, churches, and society.   Under Smith it is not 
 required and under a RFRA analysis it should not overcome the needs of the 
 judicial process or  mandatory reporting laws.  
 
 I offer these examples to contextualize the discussion.   It only matters 
 when  it is alleged a law has been broken so that  law should be the 
 starting point for discourse.
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties

2013-12-05 Thread Marci Hamilton
It depends on the state actually. But generally the confession must be for 
spiritual/salvation purposes


Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 5, 2013, at 12:32 PM, Paul Horwitz phorw...@hotmail.com wrote:

 Is that accurate? It may vary, but I thought the privilege could be claimed 
 for any confidential communication made to a clergy member in his/her 
 professional capacity as a spiritual advisor. The person seeking that counsel 
 need not necessarily be a co-communicant. I don't think this is just 
 hair-splitting. It's not analogous to a statement that men as well as women 
 can seek medical care for pregnancy. 
 
 On Dec 4, 2013, at 10:56 PM, Levinson, Sanford V slevin...@law.utexas.edu 
 wrote:
 
 Free speech doctrine, for better or worse, presumably protects (almost) 
 everyone.  What is distinctive about the “clergy-penitent privilege” is that 
 it protects only a particular subset of people, i.e., those who claim some 
 religious identity, as against secularists who have the same desire to 
 unburden themselves to sympathetic listeners but can’t assume that it is 
 protected in the same way.  Aren’t we back to the conundra involving 
 “conscientious objection” and the Seeger and Welch cases.  There the Court 
 could adopt Paul Tillich and say that secularists, too, have “ultimate 
 concerns” equivalent to religious commitments.  Can one imagine a similar 
 move with regard to clergy privileges?  I support such cases as Rosenberger 
 (assuming, at least, one version of the facts in that case, which may or may 
 not be entirely correct) and Widmar v. Vincent on “equality” grounds, i.e., 
 those who are religious should not be selected out for worse treatment than 
 those who are secular.  If I can use a facility for meetings of my 
 philosophy club, then I think that others should be free to use the facility 
 for meetings of the “Good News Club.”  But it is telling that we’re talking 
 about a “privilege” that is denied to each and every secular person (unless 
 they can afford a shrink, though even there the privilege is significantly 
 more constrained than is the case with a priest), and “equality” arguments 
 go by the boards. 
  
 sandy
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Alan Brownstein
 Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 11:35 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
  
 Much of free speech law involves protecting speech that burdens third 
 parties; for example, the victims of hate speech suffer emotional distress 
 as do the mourners at funerals tormented by the Westboro Church, and speech 
 that does not quite violate Brandenburg can incite violence. Further, the 
 cost to the public in protecting speech can be extraordinarily high. cities 
 incurred tens of thousands of dollars in police and other costs while trying 
 to maintain order during Operation Rescue protests. Criminal procedure 
 rights can make it more difficult to apprehend and punish people who commit 
 crimes. Property rights can make it more difficult to protect the 
 environment. Rights have always been expensive politcal goods.
  
 It is true that the Establishment Clause imposes some constitutional 
 constraints on the costs government may incur or impose on third parties in 
 protecting religious liberty. Arguing that free exercise rights or statutory 
 religious liberty rights should only be protected in situations in which 
 doing so imposes virtually no costs on either the public or third parties, 
 however, would treat religious liberty differently than almost all other 
 rights and dramatically undermine their utility for people attempting to 
 exercise such rights.
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Christopher Lund 
 [l...@wayne.edu]
 Sent: Wednesday, December 04, 2013 5:53 PM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: RE: The clergy-penitent privilege and burdens on third parties
 
 I think Marc’s point is solid and underappreciated.  Following up on it, 
 does anyone know of any literature that tries to think about “burdens on 
 third parties” across constitutional rights?  We accept such burdens as a 
 matter of course with defamation law, as Marc notes.  Yet we also accept 
 them in other contexts.  Guns would be one obvious example.  But also think 
 of, for example, busing during the Civil Rights Era.  White suburban 
 families had to accept busing of their kids to distant and sometimes 
 difficult schools, because desegregation was that important.  Or think about 
 abortion: I think the Court was right to hold spousal consent and 
 notification laws unconstitutional, but there are real issues of third-party 
 harms there too.
  
 Best, Chris
  
  
  
 ___
 To 

Re: Warner v. City of Boca Raton

2013-12-03 Thread Marci Hamilton
I find it interesting that Doug concedes in this thread that results in RFRA 
cases turn on the judge's predilections on religious liberty regardless of the 
law's language.  I have witnessed this lack of neutrality in several cases, 
most notably the ruling by Judge Randa in the Milwaukee bankruptcy case.  (Full 
disclosure-- I represent the creditors' committee composed mostly of sex abuse 
victims in that case.)

RFRA seems to invite a lack of neutrality despite its language saying the 
Establishment Clause is to be unaffected.   The results as described by Doug 
and Chris strike me as involving judges who are being encouraged to and who do 
violate the Establishment Clause and their code of judicial ethics. I am 
interested in others thoughts on this.

I would appreciate no ad hominem responses to these factual observations.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 3, 2013, at 10:46 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:

 Michael cites Warner v. Boca Raton, 887 So.2d 1023 (Fla. 2004), as an example 
 of a case where the word “substantially” was critical to the result. And that 
 is what the court says. But it is quite obviously not true.
  
 The Florida court read “substantially” to mean that only those practices that 
 were required by a faith were protected by Florida RFRA. The Florida 
 legislature had attempted to specifically negate any such requirement, as the 
 court recognized. The statute defined “exercise of religion” as “an act or 
 refusal to act that is substantially motivated by religious belief, whether 
 or not the religious exercise is compulsory or central to a larger system of 
 religious belief.” The Florida court’s interpretation of “substantially 
 burden” negated this definition and read back into the statute a requirement 
 that religious exercise be compulsory to be protected. The statutory 
 definition of religious exercise will never again matter to a Florida RFRA 
 case; only a subset of religious exercise as defined will ever be protected. 
 This opinion is plainly driven not by the word “substantially,” but by the 
 court’s disagreement with the scope of the statute. Full disclosure: I argued 
 the case for the plaintiffs.
  
 Here is what the court said about the statutory definition, just before it 
 turned to the meaning of “substantially burden”:
  
 “The FRFRA includes several important definitions:
  
 * * *
  
 (3) “Exercise of religion” means an act or refusal to act that is 
 substantially motivated by a religious belief, whether or not the religious 
 exercise is compulsory or central to a larger system of religious belief.
  
 § 761.02, Fla. Stat. (2003).
  
 * * * The protection afforded to the free exercise of religiously motivated 
 activity under the FRFRA is broader than that afforded by the decisions of 
 the United States Supreme Court for two interrelated reasons. First, the 
 FRFRA expands the free exercise right as construed by the Supreme Court in 
 Smith because it reinstates the Court's pre-Smith holdings by applying the 
 compelling interest test to neutral laws of general application. Second, 
 under the FRFRA the definition of protected “exercise of religion” subject to 
 the compelling state interest test includes any act or refusal to act whether 
 or not compelled by or central to a system of religious belief. The 
 legislative history of the FRFRA suggests that in order to state a claim that 
 the government has infringed upon the free exercise of religion, a plaintiff 
 must only establish that the government has placed a substantial burden on a 
 practice motivated by a sincere religious belief.”
  
 887 So.2d at 1031-32 (emphasis in original).
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
  
 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Michael Masinter
 Sent: Monday, December 02, 2013 8:44 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; Christopher Lund
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing substantial 
 as modifier of burden in state RFRAs
  
 The adjective substantial must do some work. For one state case so holding, 
 see Warner v. City of Boca Raton, 807 So. 2d 1023, 1033-1034 (Fla. 2004):
  
 Accordingly, we conclude that the narrow definition of substantial burden 
 adopted by the Fourth, Ninth, and Eleventh Circuits is most consistent with 
 the language and intent of the FRFRA. Thus, we hold that a substantial burden 
 on the free exercise of religion is one that either compels the religious 
 adherent to engage in conduct that his religion forbids or forbids him to 
 engage in conduct that his religion requires. See Mack, 80 F.3d at 1178. We 
 acknowledge that 

Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

2013-12-03 Thread Marci Hamilton
Chip has cut to the chase (thank you)  

i would add that Eugene's reasoning further underscores how RFRA is in fact a 
non-ratified amendment to the First Amendment, as the Court pointed out in a 
footnote in Boerne.   Advocates for it like Eugene cannot build in all the 
rules they like by borrowing from Supreme Court First Amendment doctrine but 
then say it is just a statute.As a statute, the plain language rule, the 
very title and the use of free exercise and the reference to religious cases 
means, yes, legislators are constrained to apply it only to religious 
believers.  If its application to only the religious makes it a violation of 
the Establishment Clause, we have a constitutional violation. 

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 3, 2013, at 11:03 AM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

 I'm happy to let others answer the question of why Eugene's FRA would be 
 crazy (and profoundly contrary to the statute Congress enacted in 1993).  If 
 Eugene is not persuaded, so be it.  
 
 
 On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 10:57 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 Why is it so crazy?  If, for instance, religious objectors 
 to abortion get exemptions from having to participate in abortion, 
 conscientious secular philosophical objectors would get such exemptions, 
 too.  That seems fair, and is indeed the rule both under various 
 abortion-specific conscience clauses and, as I noted, as to Title VII -- 
 which is narrower than RFRA in some ways, but broader in another very 
 important way (since it applies to private employers).  Nor has the 
 interpretation of Title VII to which I point been seen by courts as removing 
 the “religious” from “religious accommodation”; it just follows cases such 
 as Welsh in treating deeply held conscientious philosophical beliefs similar 
 to religious beliefs, something that would often have to be done in any 
 event given the large variety of religious views, including nontheistic ones.
 
  
 
 As to “crackpot philosoph[ies],” “crackpot” religious 
 objections -- including idiosyncratic ones -- are already covered under 
 RFRA.  Moreover, since the great majority of Americans consists of religious 
 believers, most philosophical objections can be tied by at least some of the 
 objectors to their religious beliefs, especially since all that is required 
 is sincerity of belief and not the sharing of the belief by a larger group.  
 Yet RFRA has not  been terribly burdensome for the government, as best I can 
 tell.  Why would allowing similarly crackpot (or noncrackpot) secular 
 philosophical objections to be covered suddenly cause much bigger problems?
 
  
 
 Eugene
 
  
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
 Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 7:45 AM
 
 
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions
  
 
 The reason not to construe RFRA to apply to all secular philosophical 
 objectors is that it's just plain crazy as a matter of policy.  RFRA (which 
 we would have to rename FRA after such a construction) applies to all of 
 federal law.  So this construction would give the holder of every crackpot 
 philosophy about the limited role of government the legal leverage of 
 requiring strict scrutiny as to why he or she should not be exempted from 
 the reach of federal law.  (Title VII is only about the employment relation, 
 and the duty of accommodation is limited to de minimis burdens on employers. 
  RFRA, or your FRA, would extend to everything.)  So if construction to 
 avoid constitutional doubt is what we are looking for, the only sensible 
 move is to keep the R -- that is what Congress was doing in 1993 -- and to 
 construe RFRA so as to avoid significant third party harms (in this case, to 
 employees).
 
  
 
 On Mon, Dec 2, 2013 at 11:43 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 
 I appreciate Jim’s argument, and also the arguments that the 
 problem with the exemption isn’t discrimination in favor of religion, but 
 rather the burden on third parties, regardless of whether the exemption is 
 only for the religious.  (I hope to respond to those arguments soon.)
 
  
 
 But as to the point below -- and assuming that a RFRA 
 employer mandate exemption that covers secular conscientious objectors is as 
 constitutional as the conscientious objector draft exemption -- wouldn’t the 
 canon of interpreting statutes to avoid unconstitutionality (even setting 
 aside constitutional “doubt”) be relevant here?  It’s true that RFRA 
 generally endorses Sherbert and Yoder and other federal cases, and in the 
 absence of an Establishment Clause objection it might well be interpreted to 
 apply only to religious objectors.  But if indeed such an 

Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions

2013-12-03 Thread Marci Hamilton
Religion is in the title.   The only testimony supporting it or RLUIPA was by 
religious folks.   Congress had no basis to enact and NEVER would
have enacted a law subjecting every law in the country to strict scrutiny 
triggered by every imaginable belief.   That statute is actually irrational.

It is a statute and its title is clear.   If this is to be its interpretation 
repeal should not be far behind. 

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 3, 2013, at 11:22 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 So I take it the EEOC and the great majority of courts that 
 have considered the meaning of “religion” in Title VII are wrong, too?  Here 
 are the citations I had when I last researched the matter in 1999:  Protos v. 
 Volkswagen of Am., Inc., 797 F.2d 129, 137 n.4 (3d Cir. 1986) (The breadth 
 of the 'exemption' afforded by Title VII is underscored by the fact that in 
 defining religion, the EEOC has used the same broad definition as the 
 Selective Service employs for conscientious objector purposes.); Nottelson 
 v. Smith Steel Workers, 643 F.2d 445, 454 n.12 (7th Cir. 1981) (noting the 
 same broad definition); Redmond v. GAF Corp., 574 F.2d 897, 901 n.12 (7th 
 Cir. 1978) (We believe the proper test to be applied to the determination of 
 what is 'religious' under § 2000e(j) can be derived from the Supreme Court 
 decisions in [Welsh] and [United States v. Seeger, 380 U.S. 163 (1969)], 
 i.e., (1) is the 'belief' for which protection is sought 'religious' in 
 person's own scheme of things, and (2) is it 'sincerely held.'); Ali v. 
 Southeast Neighborhood House, 519 F. Supp. 489, 490 (D.D.C. 1981) (Sincere 
 beliefs, meaningful to the believer, need not be confined in either source or 
 content to traditional or parochial concepts of religion. [Welsh.] See also 
 [Seeger] for the definition of 'religious training and belief' as applied to 
 a conscientious objector claim, which definition is no less appropriate 
 here.); Wondzell v. Alaska Wood Prods., Inc., 583 P.2d 860, 866 n.12 (Alaska 
 1978) (In order to avoid the danger of unconstitutionality we would 
 interpret [the state statute] to accord the same privileges to all sincere 
 conscientious beliefs, whether or not they are accompanied by a belief in a 
 supreme being.); Kolodziej v. Smith, 682 N.E.2d 604, 607 (Mass. 1997). 
  
 Even in the face of this caselaw, and the argument that such preference for 
 religion makes the statute unconstitutional, the Court can’t read RFRA the 
 same way, but is instead compelled to read it in a way that makes it 
 unconstitutional?
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Tuesday, December 03, 2013 8:14 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: RFRA, the Establishment Clause, and saving constructions
  
 Chip has cut to the chase (thank you)  
  
 i would add that Eugene's reasoning further underscores how RFRA is in fact a 
 non-ratified amendment to the First Amendment, as the Court pointed out in a 
 footnote in Boerne.   Advocates for it like Eugene cannot build in all the 
 rules they like by borrowing from Supreme Court First Amendment doctrine but 
 then say it is just a statute.As a statute, the plain language rule, 
 the very title and the use of free exercise and the reference to religious 
 cases means, yes, legislators are constrained to apply it only to religious 
 believers.  If its application to only the religious makes it a violation of 
 the Establishment Clause, we have a constitutional violation. 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
  
  
 
 On Dec 3, 2013, at 11:03 AM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
 
 I'm happy to let others answer the question of why Eugene's FRA would be 
 crazy (and profoundly contrary to the statute Congress enacted in 1993).  If 
 Eugene is not persuaded, so be it.  
  
 
 On Tue, Dec 3, 2013 at 10:57 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 Why is it so crazy?  If, for instance, religious objectors to 
 abortion get exemptions from having to participate in abortion, conscientious 
 secular philosophical objectors would get such exemptions, too.  That seems 
 fair, and is indeed the rule both under various abortion-specific conscience 
 clauses and, as I noted, as to Title VII -- which is narrower than RFRA in 
 some ways, but broader in another very important way (since it applies to 
 private employers).  Nor has the interpretation of Title VII to which I point 
 been seen by courts as removing the “religious” from “religious 
 accommodation”; it just follows cases such as Welsh in treating deeply held 
 conscientious philosophical beliefs similar to religious beliefs, something

Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing substantial as modifier of burden in state RFRAs

2013-12-02 Thread Marci Hamilton
Chris--  As I mentioned, CT's has been amended through interpretation  You are 
right about Alabama.   

I actually think these terms matter and removal of substantial  violates the 
Establishment Clause but it also shows the endless push by religious entities 
to overcome all laws.   I assume the next wave will be a push to interpret 
compelling to mean absolutely necessary.   That is not intended to be snide.  
Just an observation.   The Framers expected all those w power to
push it as far as they could.  They were right.

I look forward to reading your article.

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 2, 2013, at 12:01 PM, Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu wrote:

 Connecticut and Alabama use burden instead of substantial burden.  New 
 Mexico, Missouri, and Rhode Island don't use the burden terminology--they 
 speak of restrictions on religious liberty.  To me, that would seem like it 
 jettisons the requirement of burden altogether, but others may disagree.  Two 
 of the substantial burden states—Arizona and Idaho—say explicitly in their 
 statutes that the requirement is only meant to weed out trivial, technical, 
 or de minimis burdens.  I talk about the differences, and have a handy 
 though dated chart, in this piece, 
 http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1666268.
 
  
 
 It's a mess, in other words.  And I have to say, I don't know how much any of 
 these differences matter.  When I looked at state RFRA cases a few years 
 back, I found these differences in wording didn't matter much.  They are 
 rarely even talked about.  This may be an issue where academics care quite a 
 bit, but judges do not.  Judges are heavily influenced by the facts of these 
 cases; the wording of the RFRAs, I think, is secondary.
 
 From: hamilto...@aol.com
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Monday, December 2, 2013 10:43:51 AM
 Subject: Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing
 substantialas modifier of burden in state RFRAs
 
 The WIs bill was never passed to my knowledge, but if it went through under 
 the radar, I would be interested.  
 Conn did not include the term in one of the earliest bills, but the Conn 
 Supreme Court read it in.  To my knowledge, only
 KY passed such a bill, and only over the Governor's veto.
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215 
 http://sol-reform.com
 
 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Saperstein, David dsaperst...@rac.org
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Cc: religionlaw religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Mon, Dec 2, 2013 10:39 am
 Subject: Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing substantial 
 as modifier of burden in state RFRAs
 
 Just FY (forgive me if I missed an earlier reference)I believe there is 
 such a bill in Wisconsin as well ?  
 
 Sent from my iPhone
 
 On Dec 2, 2013, at 10:18 AM, hamilto...@aol.com hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 
 Thanks, Doug.  The letter in support of the new TRFRA amendment bill, which 
 would have omitted substantial as a modifier, does not mention the removal 
 of   
 substantial, but is in support of the bill.  
 
  If there is anyone who signed it who opposes removal of substantial, 
 please let me know.  Otherwise, I will assume all
 signatories have endorsed the removal of substantial as a modifier for 
 burden.  No need to respond if you support the bill as worded.
 
 Thanks all
 
   
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215 
 http://sol-reform.com
 
 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu; 
 hamilton02 hamilto...@aol.com
 Sent: Sun, Dec 1, 2013 11:37 am
 Subject: Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing substantial 
 as modifier of burden in state RFRAs
 
 The presence or absence of the word substantial was briefly addressed in a 
 follow-up letter here:
 
 http://www.law.virginia.edu/pdf/faculty/laycock/texasreligfreedamdt2013senate2corrected.pdf
 
 I defended the word's omission. I also suggested that the Committee add it if 
 they thought it mattered. 
 
 My apologies for the delay. There was an initial miscommunication with our 
 tech 
 people, and by the time they got this posted, I was caught up in Town of 
 Greece 
 and completely forgot to go back to this.
 
 On Sun, 1 Dec 2013 11:00:33 -0500 (EST)
  hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 Thanks Marty!  
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215 
 http://sol-reform.com
 
 
 
 
 
 -Original Message-
 

Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing substantial as modifier of burden in state RFRAs

2013-12-02 Thread Marci Hamilton
The Texas municipal league and civil rights groups -- especially those 
protecting children's and women's and gay rights -- would disagree w the notion 
substantial is irrelevant.   And the TX legislature had no interest,
or so I am told by those groups on the ground in Texas.   I don't want the 
listserv to have the impression that the state RFRA battles are being
fought solely by law professors and religious lobbyists.   The civil rights 
groups that initially backed RFRA
have caught up to the agendas behind the veil




  

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 2, 2013, at 12:28 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:

 Apologies to anyone getting this twice; I think it bounced the first time.
  
 What I said is in the second letter (link below) and summarized in the e-mail 
 to which Marci responded. We supported the bill as drafted, without 
 “substantial;” I also suggested that the committee restore “substantial” if 
 it were bothered by the omission. I think most of my co-signers would have 
 agreed with that suggestion, but I don’t know that, because they were not 
 asked to sign the second letter. I said it didn’t matter much because the 
 substantiality of the burden would affect the inevitable balancing of burden 
 against government interest; Chris Lund’s recent post better documents that 
 explanation.
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
  
 From: hamilto...@aol.com [mailto:hamilto...@aol.com] 
 Sent: Monday, December 02, 2013 10:18 AM
 To: dlayc...@virginia.edu; religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing substantial 
 as modifier of burden in state RFRAs
  
 Thanks, Doug.  The letter in support of the new TRFRA amendment bill, which 
 would have omitted substantial as a modifier, does not mention the removal 
 of 
 substantial, but is in support of the bill.  
  
  If there is anyone who signed it who opposes removal of substantial, 
 please let me know.  Otherwise, I will assume all
 signatories have endorsed the removal of substantial as a modifier for 
 burden.  No need to respond if you support the bill as worded.
  
 Thanks all
  
   
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215 
 http://sol-reform.com
 
  
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu; 
 hamilton02 hamilto...@aol.com
 Sent: Sun, Dec 1, 2013 11:37 am
 Subject: Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing substantial 
 as modifier of burden in state RFRAs
 
 The presence or absence of the word substantial was briefly addressed in a 
 follow-up letter here:
  
 http://www.law.virginia.edu/pdf/faculty/laycock/texasreligfreedamdt2013senate2corrected.pdf
  
 I defended the word's omission. I also suggested that the Committee add it if 
 they thought it mattered. 
  
 My apologies for the delay. There was an initial miscommunication with our 
 tech 
 people, and by the time they got this posted, I was caught up in Town of 
 Greece 
 and completely forgot to go back to this.
  
 On Sun, 1 Dec 2013 11:00:33 -0500 (EST)
  hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 Thanks Marty!  
  
  
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215 
 http://sol-reform.com
  
 
  
  
  
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing substantial as modifier of burden in state RFRAs

2013-12-02 Thread Marci Hamilton
It has certainly made a difference in RLUIPA cases.   I have to say I find it a 
little hard to believe these cases can be generalized across states given how 
few there are and how different each state operates procedurally, but I look 
forward to reading your article and will keep an open mind.

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 2, 2013, at 1:18 PM, Christopher Lund ed9...@wayne.edu wrote:

 
 Again I have not seen any evidence that differences in phrasing--burden, 
 substantial burden, restriction on religious liberty,--have caused any 
 differences in result (or even reasoning).  If you have examples, I'd love 
 to know about them.  If not, it suggests the differences in phrasing don't 
 matter.  That's my intuition from the cases I've read.  But it may be wrong, 
 and I'd like to know if it is.
 
 On Dec 2, 2013, at 12:44 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 
 Chris--  As I mentioned, CT's has been amended through interpretation  You 
 are right about Alabama.   
 
 I actually think these terms matter and removal of substantial  violates 
 the Establishment Clause but it also shows the endless push by religious 
 entities to overcome all laws.   I assume the next wave will be a push to 
 interpret compelling to mean absolutely necessary.   That is not intended 
 to be snide.  Just an observation.   The Framers expected all those w power 
 to
 push it as far as they could.  They were right.
 
 I look forward to reading your article.
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 
 
 
 On Dec 2, 2013, at 12:01 PM, Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu wrote:
 
 Connecticut and Alabama use burden instead of substantial burden.  New 
 Mexico, Missouri, and Rhode Island don't use the burden terminology--they 
 speak of restrictions on religious liberty.  To me, that would seem like 
 it jettisons the requirement of burden altogether, but others may 
 disagree.  Two of the substantial burden states—Arizona and Idaho—say 
 explicitly in their statutes that the requirement is only meant to weed 
 out trivial, technical, or de minimis burdens.  I talk about the 
 differences, and have a handy though dated chart, in this piece, 
 http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1666268.
 
  
 
 It's a mess, in other words.  And I have to say, I don't know how much any 
 of these differences matter.  When I looked at state RFRA cases a few 
 years back, I found these differences in wording didn't matter much.  They 
 are rarely even talked about.  This may be an issue where academics care 
 quite a bit, but judges do not.  Judges are heavily influenced by the 
 facts of these cases; the wording of the RFRAs, I think, is secondary.
 
 From: hamilto...@aol.com
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Monday, December 2, 2013 10:43:51 AM
 Subject: Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing
 substantialas modifier of burden in state RFRAs
 
 The WIs bill was never passed to my knowledge, but if it went through 
 under the radar, I would be interested.  
 Conn did not include the term in one of the earliest bills, but the Conn 
 Supreme Court read it in.  To my knowledge, only
 KY passed such a bill, and only over the Governor's veto.
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing substantial as modifier of burden in state RFRAs

2013-12-02 Thread Marci Hamilton
What they had was the reality of politics and the forces arrayed against them.  
 As one said to me, if it doesn't make a difference why try for a 
constitutional amendment to delete it and fix it permanently?

In federal court, substantial burden has been a difficult hurdle for claimants.



Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 2, 2013, at 2:09 PM, Christopher Lund ed9...@wayne.edu wrote:

 Sure, but what evidence did they have?  That is, what evidence did they have 
 that any of the differences in phrasing--burden, substantial burden, or 
 restriction on religious liberty,--would matter in deciding cases?
 
 Again I may be wrong about this and I really would like to be corrected if I 
 am.  But I have seen no evidence that these differences have practical payoff.
 
 On Dec 2, 2013, at 1:45 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 
 The Texas municipal league and civil rights groups -- especially those 
 protecting children's and women's and gay rights -- would disagree w the 
 notion substantial is irrelevant.   And the TX legislature had no interest,
 or so I am told by those groups on the ground in Texas.   I don't want the 
 listserv to have the impression that the state RFRA battles are being
 fought solely by law professors and religious lobbyists.   The civil rights 
 groups that initially backed RFRA
 have caught up to the agendas behind the veil
 
 
 
 
   
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 
 
 
 On Dec 2, 2013, at 12:28 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
 
 Apologies to anyone getting this twice; I think it bounced the first time.
  
 What I said is in the second letter (link below) and summarized in the 
 e-mail to which Marci responded. We supported the bill as drafted, without 
 “substantial;” I also suggested that the committee restore “substantial” if 
 it were bothered by the omission. I think most of my co-signers would have 
 agreed with that suggestion, but I don’t know that, because they were not 
 asked to sign the second letter. I said it didn’t matter much because the 
 substantiality of the burden would affect the inevitable balancing of 
 burden against government interest; Chris Lund’s recent post better 
 documents that explanation.
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
  
 From: hamilto...@aol.com [mailto:hamilto...@aol.com] 
 Sent: Monday, December 02, 2013 10:18 AM
 To: dlayc...@virginia.edu; religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing 
 substantial as modifier of burden in state RFRAs
  
 Thanks, Doug.  The letter in support of the new TRFRA amendment bill, which 
 would have omitted substantial as a modifier, does not mention the 
 removal of 
 substantial, but is in support of the bill. 
  
  If there is anyone who signed it who opposes removal of substantial, 
 please let me know.  Otherwise, I will assume all
 signatories have endorsed the removal of substantial as a modifier for 
 burden.  No need to respond if you support the bill as worded.
  
 Thanks all
  
   
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215 
 http://sol-reform.com
 
  
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu; 
 hamilton02 hamilto...@aol.com
 Sent: Sun, Dec 1, 2013 11:37 am
 Subject: Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing 
 substantial as modifier of burden in state RFRAs
 
 The presence or absence of the word substantial was briefly addressed in 
 a 
 follow-up letter here:
  
 http://www.law.virginia.edu/pdf/faculty/laycock/texasreligfreedamdt2013senat
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward

Re: Letter of 16 law professors in support of removing substantial as modifier of burden in state RFRAs

2013-12-02 Thread Marci Hamilton
Absolutely.  They all have lobbyists.   I don't view the term as necessarily 
perjorative.  Just descriptive.   

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Dec 2, 2013, at 2:10 PM, Paul Horwitz phorw...@hotmail.com wrote:

 I'm curious about how this response relates to your response to Chris Lund, 
 in which you cited the Madisonian assumption that every group will seek the 
 maximum amount of power. It reminded me of this profile of Valerie Jarrett: 
 http://www.nytimes.com/2012/09/02/us/politics/valerie-jarrett-is-the-other-power-in-the-west-wing.html?_r=2pagewanted=all;.
  
 
 If Madison was right, then doesn't every group try to maximize its own power 
 and agenda? And doesn't every politically savvy group use lobbyists and other 
 means, such as inside power players, to that end? Does anything turn on 
 describing religious groups as having lobbyists and an agenda, and implying 
 that other groups are wholly selfless and decent? Or is that just semantic 
 advocacy?
 
 On Dec 2, 2013, at 12:45 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 
 The Texas municipal league and civil rights groups -- especially those 
 protecting children's and women's and gay rights -- would disagree w the 
 notion substantial is irrelevant.   And the TX legislature had no interest,
 or so I am told by those groups on the ground in Texas.   I don't want the 
 listserv to have the impression that the state RFRA battles are being
 fought solely by law professors and religious lobbyists.   The civil rights 
 groups that initially backed RFRA
 have caught up to the agendas behind the veil
 
 
 
 
   
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Sex discrimination and objections to apparently abortifacent contraceptives

2013-11-28 Thread Marci Hamilton
Few quick observations and then my work through of the Title VII and RFRA 
factors.


These employers oppose sterilization, not just medicines.   Does that affect 
Eugene's analysis?  Also--Is there a sincerity point to be raised given they 
are religiously opposed to all contraception but basing these claims on a 
subset?  

Does anyone have a site or list of each of the medications each of the various 
plaintiffs in the ACA cases objects to?   
what they believe is an abortifacient will not make it medically true.  The 
courts must take their beliefs as sincere (if they are) but not as medical fact.

In any event, I think Eugene is missing the discrimination  point.   The 
discrimination is based on gender.  Women don't have privacy rights against 
these employers.  They have rights against gender and religious discrimination 
under Title VII.   This is gender discrimination.   And the only reason is 
religion which does not fly under Title VII .   So the employers  lose under 
Title VII.  

RFRA kicks in (assuming a for profit co was intended to be covered by RFRA 
which is far-fetched-- will leave to the side for now the Citizens United  
issues)   

No substantial burden.  Under settled benefits law, these companies are 
fiduciaries of their employees' compensation benefits plan.   They must manage 
that plan SOLELY for the benefit of employees.  Not providing women these 
accepted and safe medical treatments hurts individual women and all 
participants in the plan because it increases overall costs significantly. If 
the employer  has moral or  other objections to the benefit plan that would not 
be in the interest of plan beneficiaries, they are required by law to hand 
administration to a neutral beneficiary who will oversee the plan in the 
employees sole interest.   That means there is no substantial burden.

Assuming they could prove substantial burden, they can't win on compelling 
interest.  Gender discrimination under Title VII obviously serves a compelling 
interest.   There is an added compelling interest in foreclosing violation 
fiduciary of duties w respect to benefit plans in light of the many 
contemporary examples of underfunding pension plans.  If the law doesn't deter 
profit-seeking entities from abandoning their fiduciary obligations to their 
employees' benefit compensation packages the court would be undermining a 
century of legal developments protecting employees against self-serving 
employers.

LRM also fails because there is no  LRM here other than enforcing the 
discrimination laws and fiduciary laws against for profit cos.   congress 
considered a religious exemption for these companies and rejected it and 
religious exemptions for fiduciary obligations don't exist and would open a 
Pandora's box for employees.  The court would be acting as a super legislature 
to wipe out these settled laws for religious employers where 80% are religious 
believers of some sort.  If gender discrimination is ok then race and religion 
will be too.   Happy days for white supremacists and for-profit cos who only 
want their own  believers working near and with them.

The RFRA claim loses and women's civil rights are preserved.

Gotta get started on Thanksgiving dinner!!   Hope everyone has a wonderful day 
w family and friends!

Marci 

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Nov 28, 2013, at 1:34 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 Though I think the ACA regulations should be seen as 
 substantially burden the plaintiffs’ exercise of religion, I think the strict 
 scrutiny argument is much harder to analyze, and perhaps the government 
 should indeed win under strict scrutiny.  And I can see the appeal of the sex 
 discrimination argument.
  
 Nonetheless, I wonder how this fits within the Court’s 
 broader abortion jurisprudence.  I realize that people (including Justice 
 Ginsburg) have argued that abortion bans should indeed have been viewed as 
 presumptively unconstitutional sex discrimination, but my sense is that there 
 aren’t five votes for that on the Court.  After all, under this view any 
 restrictions on abortion (including ones that Justice Kennedy would be 
 prepared to accept as not “undue burdens”) would be presumptively 
 unconstitutional, and subject to near-strict scrutiny.  If I’m right, and 
 abortion restrictions aren’t treated as sex discrimination when imposed by 
 the government, would refusals to pay for certain contraceptives – based on 
 the objector’s view that the contraceptives are actually abortifacents – be 
 treated as sex discrimination for RFRA purposes?
  
 Eugene
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that 

Re: Discrimination under Title VII and RFRA (was Patently Frivolous)

2013-11-27 Thread Marci Hamilton
Chip--  it might be a standing issue regarding the religious discrimination but 
I still think it has legs because, eg, a Presbyterian is having her job 
benefits limited solely according to religion that she doesn't share, in 
contravention of both economics and health standards.  Shaping a compensation 
package to reflect one religion strikes me as similar the argument raised by 
the woman who challenges the employer who forbids the wearing of a headscarf.  
Why doesn't a woman's religious beliefs that require family planning and even 
abortion particularly where her health and life are implicated have a Title VII 
claim?  How is this different from the woman who demands the right to wear a 
headscarf on the reasoning of those who back RFRA and expansive religious 
liberty?

On another extremely important pr--

I would also point out that benefits law is relevant here and not yet mentioned 
by anyone -- employers are under a fiduciary duty to handle their employees 
health benefits plans solely for the benefit of the employees.  If they cannot 
do so for ethical or other reasons, they must step aside and put the benefits 
into the hands of a fiduciary who will handle the benefits in the interest of 
the employees.  This attempt to imprint their benefits compensation package 
according to their religion is a violation of their fiduciary duty.   

I wonder whether the lawyers for the companies involved or the bishops are 
advising these companies that they are teeing themselves up for potentially 
ruinous lawsuits by female employees for breach of fiduciary duty and explicit 
gender discrimination?

On this point-- the least restrictive means is to appoint an outside plan 
administrator.


Marci 

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Nov 27, 2013, at 11:12 AM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

 All of Marci's hypotheticals are loaded up, because they involve direct 
 imposition on women's behavior (wear head scarves, don't use certain 
 medicines or drugs) rather than just refusing to pay for the relevant goods.  
 And Marci's claim that Hobby Lobby and others are engaging in religious 
 discrimination seems wrong to me -- the refusal to cover affects every female 
 employee, regardless of her religious beliefs or affiliation or conduct.  
 
 But Marci's argument that Hobby Lobby and others are engaging in sex 
 discrimination, in violation, of Title VII, seems much more persuasive  - the 
 coverage refusal affects all women and only women, and is therefore a sex 
 discriminatory denial of legally compelled fringe benefits.  I have not read 
 a single post that replies to that way of framing the argument.   If we view 
 this as an attempt to gain a RFRA-based exemption from Title VII as well as 
 from the ACA, does that change the analysis?  Doesn't the government's 
 compelling interest argument get stronger -- under-inclusion is no longer a 
 problem of the same degree, and cases like Bob Jones University come into the 
 mix?  
 
 Are there good answers to this way of framing the question?  Is it too late 
 for the government to so frame it in the Supreme Court? 
 
 
 On Wed, Nov 27, 2013 at 11:01 AM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:
 I know this isn't a full answer; but the issue is not whether or not a woman 
 can use birth control for cramps, etc. as far as I am aware.
 
 Further, the issue is who pays for the contraception, not whether the 
 contraception can be used.
 
 
 On Wed, Nov 27, 2013 at 7:50 AM, hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 The Court has not drawn such a line, in part because it hasn't thought 
 about it carefully.  Citizens United brings the possibilities to the 
 forefront.
 
 In any event, the for-profit/nonprofit difference makes a meaningful 
 difference in this case, because it is in the ACA's women's reproductive 
 care mandate,
 and it is in Title VII, which protects women.All of my postings have 
 been in this arena, and given the pressures of this holiday week, I didn't 
 want to lose
 track of that focus with the lunch hypo Eugene suggested.  It is 
 undoubtedly interesting, but I don't think very illuminating given there is 
 no federal civil rights
 or constitutional right to lunch or food generally.  I noticed on NCR that 
 there is some talk by the bishops in light of the Pope's welcome focus
 on the poor, about the fundamental right to food, but that takes us far 
 afield from Hobby Lobby with all due respect to Eugene.
 
 I  had posed some on-point hypotheticals I am deeply interested in knowing 
 folks' views on, yet it was lost in the fascinating topics up for 
 discussion.  
 
 Here are a few modifications and additions to those.
 
 1.  Can employers successfully invoke RFRA to follow their religious 
 beliefs to impose headscarves on every woman in a for-profit corporation of 
 over 50 employees (Mandate +
 Title VII at play)?
 
 2.  Can employers successfully invoke RFRA 

Re: Discrimination under Title VII and RFRA (was Patently Frivolous)

2013-11-27 Thread Marci Hamilton
Marty- one addition --women will also have to pay for oral contraceptives to 
stop excessive bleeding, cramps, and hormone- triggered acne.   I think this 
discussion needs to factor in the medical uses beyond contraception for 
millions of women over the course of their lives.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Nov 27, 2013, at 11:44 AM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:

 The government is relying upon women's equality -- not only health -- as one 
 of the compelling interests.  This makes sense, since presumably most (but 
 not all) employees would pay for contraception ut of pocket, rather than go 
 without.
 
   As for whether an employer's failure to cover contraception would have 
 violated federal law before the HHS rule, in 2000 the EEOC interpreted the 
 PDA as requiring employers to cover prescription contraception for women if 
 they cover “other prescription drugs and devices, or other types of services, 
 that are used to prevent the occurrences of other medical conditions.” EEOC 
 Commission Decision on Coverage of Contraception (Dec. 14, 2000), available 
 at http://www.eeoc.gov/policy/docs/decision-contraception.html.  The only 
 court of appeals to address the issue disagreed, however, in a split decision 
 -- see In re Union Pacific R. Employment Practices Lit., 479 F3d 936 (CTA8 
 2007).
 
 
 On Wed, Nov 27, 2013 at 11:12 AM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
 All of Marci's hypotheticals are loaded up, because they involve direct 
 imposition on women's behavior (wear head scarves, don't use certain 
 medicines or drugs) rather than just refusing to pay for the relevant goods. 
  And Marci's claim that Hobby Lobby and others are engaging in religious 
 discrimination seems wrong to me -- the refusal to cover affects every 
 female employee, regardless of her religious beliefs or affiliation or 
 conduct.  
 
 But Marci's argument that Hobby Lobby and others are engaging in sex 
 discrimination, in violation, of Title VII, seems much more persuasive  - 
 the coverage refusal affects all women and only women, and is therefore a 
 sex discriminatory denial of legally compelled fringe benefits.  I have not 
 read a single post that replies to that way of framing the argument.   If we 
 view this as an attempt to gain a RFRA-based exemption from Title VII as 
 well as from the ACA, does that change the analysis?  Doesn't the 
 government's compelling interest argument get stronger -- under-inclusion is 
 no longer a problem of the same degree, and cases like Bob Jones University 
 come into the mix?  
 
 Are there good answers to this way of framing the question?  Is it too late 
 for the government to so frame it in the Supreme Court? 
 
 
 On Wed, Nov 27, 2013 at 11:01 AM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:
 I know this isn't a full answer; but the issue is not whether or not a 
 woman can use birth control for cramps, etc. as far as I am aware.
 
 Further, the issue is who pays for the contraception, not whether the 
 contraception can be used.
 
 
 On Wed, Nov 27, 2013 at 7:50 AM, hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 The Court has not drawn such a line, in part because it hasn't thought 
 about it carefully.  Citizens United brings the possibilities to the 
 forefront.
 
 In any event, the for-profit/nonprofit difference makes a meaningful 
 difference in this case, because it is in the ACA's women's reproductive 
 care mandate,
 and it is in Title VII, which protects women.All of my postings have 
 been in this arena, and given the pressures of this holiday week, I didn't 
 want to lose
 track of that focus with the lunch hypo Eugene suggested.  It is 
 undoubtedly interesting, but I don't think very illuminating given there 
 is no federal civil rights
 or constitutional right to lunch or food generally.  I noticed on NCR that 
 there is some talk by the bishops in light of the Pope's welcome focus
 on the poor, about the fundamental right to food, but that takes us far 
 afield from Hobby Lobby with all due respect to Eugene.
 
 I  had posed some on-point hypotheticals I am deeply interested in knowing 
 folks' views on, yet it was lost in the fascinating topics up for 
 discussion.  
 
 Here are a few modifications and additions to those.
 
 1.  Can employers successfully invoke RFRA to follow their religious 
 beliefs to impose headscarves on every woman in a for-profit corporation 
 of over 50 employees (Mandate +
 Title VII at play)?
 
 2.  Can employers successfully invoke RFRA to follow their religious 
 beliefs against contraception to bar women from using contraception to 
 stop a woman's constant
 bleeding due to hormone imablances?   Or to halt monthly debilitating 
 cramps?
 
 3.  Can employers successfully invoke RFRA to follow their religious 
 beliefs against contraception to bar families from providing oral 
 contraceptives to girls with
 disfiguring acne 

Re: Discrimination under Title VII and RFRA (was Patently Frivolous)

2013-11-27 Thread Marci Hamilton
I certainly hope they will rely on these statutes which are evidence of (1) the 
ingrained and ongoing persistence of gender discrimination across society and 
in private institutions; (2) the need to be vigilant as these hard-fought 
rights can be compromised at any time; and (3) this religious liberty argument 
is in fact an argument that necessarily disables women's equality and bodily 
integrity.

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Nov 27, 2013, at 12:16 PM, James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu wrote:

 There is at least one district court decision upholding the EEOC's view of 
 the PDA. See Erickson v. Bartell Drug Co., 141 F. Supp. 2d 1266, 1271-72 
 (W.D. Wash. 2001):
 
 Having reviewed the legislative history of Title VII and the PDA, the 
 language of the statute itself, and the relevant case law, the Court finds 
 that Bartell's exclusion of prescription contraception from its prescription 
 plan is inconsistent with the requirements of federal law. The PDA is not a 
 begrudging recognition of a limited grant of rights to a strictly defined 
 group of women who happen to be pregnant. Read in the context of Title VII as 
 a whole, it is a broad acknowledgment of the intent of Congress to outlaw any 
 and all discrimination against any and all women in the terms and conditions 
 of their employment, including the benefits an employer provides to its 
 employees. Male and female employees have different, sex-based disability and 
 healthcare needs, and the law is no longer blind to the fact that only women 
 can get pregnant, bear children, or use prescription contraception. The 
 special or increased healthcare needs associated with a woman's unique 
 sex-based characteristics must be met to the same extent, and on the same 
 terms, as other healthcare needs. Even if one were to assume that Bartell's 
 prescription plan was not the result of intentional discrimination, the 
 exclusion of women-only benefits from a generally comprehensive prescription 
 plan is sex discrimination under Title VII.
 Title VII does not require employers to offer any particular type or category 
 of benefit. However, when an employer decides to offer a prescription plan 
 covering everything except a few specifically excluded drugs and devices, it 
 has a legal obligation to make sure that the resulting plan does not 
 discriminate based on sex-based characteristics and that it provides equally 
 comprehensive coverage for both sexes. In light of the fact that prescription 
 contraceptives are used only by women, Bartell's choice to exclude that 
 particular benefit from its generally applicable benefit plan is 
 discriminatory.
 
 Marty is correct that the government is relying on women's equality, but 
 their brief to the Tenth Circuit did not invoke Title VII, the PDA, the EEOC 
 interpretation, or Erickson in support of the equality interest. In 
 retrospect, that strikes me as a big oversight. But I must admit that I 
 hadn't thought of the argument until one of my seminar students made it in a 
 paper they are writing about Hobby Lobby.  
 
 
 On Wed, Nov 27, 2013 at 8:44 AM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 
 wrote:
 The government is relying upon women's equality -- not only health -- as one 
 of the compelling interests.  This makes sense, since presumably most (but 
 not all) employees would pay for contraception ut of pocket, rather than go 
 without.
 
   As for whether an employer's failure to cover contraception would have 
 violated federal law before the HHS rule, in 2000 the EEOC interpreted the 
 PDA as requiring employers to cover prescription contraception for women if 
 they cover “other prescription drugs and devices, or other types of 
 services, that are used to prevent the occurrences of other medical 
 conditions.” EEOC Commission Decision on Coverage of Contraception (Dec. 14, 
 2000), available at 
 http://www.eeoc.gov/policy/docs/decision-contraception.html.  The only court 
 of appeals to address the issue disagreed, however, in a split decision -- 
 see In re Union Pacific R. Employment Practices Lit., 479 F3d 936 (CTA8 
 2007).
 
 
 On Wed, Nov 27, 2013 at 11:12 AM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
 All of Marci's hypotheticals are loaded up, because they involve direct 
 imposition on women's behavior (wear head scarves, don't use certain 
 medicines or drugs) rather than just refusing to pay for the relevant 
 goods.  And Marci's claim that Hobby Lobby and others are engaging in 
 religious discrimination seems wrong to me -- the refusal to cover affects 
 every female employee, regardless of her religious beliefs or affiliation 
 or conduct.  
 
 But Marci's argument that Hobby Lobby and others are engaging in sex 
 discrimination, in violation, of Title VII, seems much more persuasive  - 
 the coverage refusal affects all women and only women, and is therefore a 
 sex discriminatory denial of 

Re: Discrimination under Title VII and RFRA (was Patently Frivolous)

2013-11-27 Thread Marci Hamilton
Tom--  they are not opposed to the Pill?



Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Nov 27, 2013, at 12:16 PM, Berg, Thomas C. tcb...@stthomas.edu wrote:

 In response to Chip,
 
 As to the plaintiffs in Hobby Lobby and Conestoga, they object only to 
 certain medicines/methods that they believe cause abortions of fertilized 
 embryos.  Unless opposition to abortion is a form of statutory sex 
 discrimination, which the Court rejected in Bray v. Alexandria Women's Health 
 Center, this element at least complicates any argument that sex 
 discrimination is the interest in these cases.  (The government asserts that 
 abortion is not involved here, for both legal and medical reasons, but this 
 at least complicates the matter--especially in a case where the question 
 concerns the objector's conscientious belief.)
 
 Moreover, as to the Catholic plaintiffs--those opposed to contraception as 
 well as abortion--all of the complaints, as I remember, state that 
 plaintiffs' object to paying for sterilization as well as for abortion and 
 contraception.  Presumably they would object to having to pay for 
 vasectomies--if the mandate required those, which it apparently does not.  
 This article from Kaiser Health News indicates that the relevant parts of the 
 mandate only covers preventive services for women.  
 http://www.kaiserhealthnews.org/stories/2012/february/27/five-questions-health-law-mandate-birth-control.aspx
   If this article is wrong, someone please correct me.  But it would be 
 strange for the government to enforce a regulation covering only services for 
 women and then claim that the one who objects to it is engaged in sex 
 discrimination (when there is a good likelihood that the moral objections 
 would extend to relevant services for males).
 
 There is of course the argument for the importance of contraceptive access to 
 women's health, life-planning, and autonomy.  The government has made that 
 argument strenuously, and we'll see if it succeeds on these facts.  But it 
 seems to me that going further and framing the issue as sex discrimination by 
 the objectors faces problems.
 
 Tom
 
 P.S.  here is the relevant passage from the link above:
 
 1) Are male-based contraceptive methods, such as vasectomies or condoms, 
 covered by the rule?
 
 An HHS official said on Friday that women’s preventive services guidelines 
 apply to women only.
 
 Guidelines issued by the Health Resources and Services Administration, part 
 of HHS, require coverage without cost sharing for all Food and Drug 
 Administration-approved contraceptive methods, sterilization procedures and 
 patient education and counseling for all women with reproductive capacity as 
 prescribed by a provider, according to the Federal Register.
 
 The insurers' letter from September says they interpreted the rule to include 
 only female-based contraception and that the requirement to waive co-payments 
 does not apply to methods and procedures intended for males.
 
 But Adam Sonfield, senior public policy associate at the Guttmacher 
 Institute, a reproductive health research group, says the language is 
 unclear, and it would be foolish to exclude vasectomies. For one thing, he 
 says, they are less expensive and pose a lower risk of complications than 
 female surgical sterilization methods. Plus, he says, waiving co-payments for 
 services for one sex but not the other raises issues of discrimination.
 
 
 -
 Thomas C. Berg
 James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy
 University of St. Thomas School of Law
 MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
 Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
 Phone: 651 962 4918
 Fax: 651 962 4881
 E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edumailto:tcb...@stthomas.edu
 SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
 Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
 on behalf of Ira Lupu [icl...@law.gwu.edu]
 Sent: Wednesday, November 27, 2013 10:12 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Discrimination under Title VII and RFRA (was Patently 
 Frivolous)
 
 All of Marci's hypotheticals are loaded up, because they involve direct 
 imposition on women's behavior (wear head scarves, don't use certain 
 medicines or drugs) rather than just refusing to pay for the relevant goods.  
 And Marci's claim that Hobby Lobby and others are engaging in religious 
 discrimination seems wrong to me -- the refusal to cover affects every female 
 employee, regardless of her religious beliefs or affiliation or conduct.
 
 But Marci's argument that Hobby Lobby and others are engaging in sex 
 discrimination, in violation, of Title VII, seems much more persuasive  - the 
 coverage refusal affects all women and only women, and is 

Re: Discrimination under Title VII and RFRA (was Patently Frivolous)

2013-11-27 Thread Marci Hamilton
So how does it work?  The women need pre approval from their boss?  

And I thought the bishops oppose the Pill and these are devout Catholics.  

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Nov 27, 2013, at 12:46 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:

 They are not. 
 
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
 
 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Wednesday, November 27, 2013 12:32 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Discrimination under Title VII and RFRA (was Patently 
 Frivolous)
 
 Tom--  they are not opposed to the Pill?
 
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 
 
 
 On Nov 27, 2013, at 12:16 PM, Berg, Thomas C. tcb...@stthomas.edu wrote:
 
 In response to Chip,
 
 As to the plaintiffs in Hobby Lobby and Conestoga, they object only to 
 certain medicines/methods that they believe cause abortions of 
 fertilized embryos.  Unless opposition to abortion is a form of 
 statutory sex discrimination, which the Court rejected in Bray v. 
 Alexandria Women's Health Center, this element at least complicates 
 any argument that sex discrimination is the interest in these cases.  
 (The government asserts that abortion is not involved here, for both 
 legal and medical reasons, but this at least complicates the 
 matter--especially in a case where the question concerns the 
 objector's conscientious belief.)
 
 Moreover, as to the Catholic plaintiffs--those opposed to contraception as 
 well as abortion--all of the complaints, as I remember, state that 
 plaintiffs' object to paying for sterilization as well as for abortion and 
 contraception.  Presumably they would object to having to pay for 
 vasectomies--if the mandate required those, which it apparently does not.  
 This article from Kaiser Health News indicates that the relevant parts of 
 the mandate only covers preventive services for women.  
 http://www.kaiserhealthnews.org/stories/2012/february/27/five-questions-health-law-mandate-birth-control.aspx
   If this article is wrong, someone please correct me.  But it would be 
 strange for the government to enforce a regulation covering only services 
 for women and then claim that the one who objects to it is engaged in sex 
 discrimination (when there is a good likelihood that the moral objections 
 would extend to relevant services for males).
 
 There is of course the argument for the importance of contraceptive access 
 to women's health, life-planning, and autonomy.  The government has made 
 that argument strenuously, and we'll see if it succeeds on these facts.  But 
 it seems to me that going further and framing the issue as sex 
 discrimination by the objectors faces problems.
 
 Tom
 
 P.S.  here is the relevant passage from the link above:
 
 1) Are male-based contraceptive methods, such as vasectomies or condoms, 
 covered by the rule?
 
 An HHS official said on Friday that women’s preventive services guidelines 
 apply to women only.
 
 Guidelines issued by the Health Resources and Services Administration, part 
 of HHS, require coverage without cost sharing for all Food and Drug 
 Administration-approved contraceptive methods, sterilization procedures and 
 patient education and counseling for all women with reproductive capacity 
 as prescribed by a provider, according to the Federal Register.
 
 The insurers' letter from September says they interpreted the rule to 
 include only female-based contraception and that the requirement to waive 
 co-payments does not apply to methods and procedures intended for males.
 
 But Adam Sonfield, senior public policy associate at the Guttmacher 
 Institute, a reproductive health research group, says the language is 
 unclear, and it would be foolish to exclude vasectomies. For one thing, he 
 says, they are less expensive and pose a lower risk of complications than 
 female surgical sterilization methods. Plus, he says, waiving co-payments 
 for services for one sex but not the other raises issues of discrimination.
 
 
 -
 Thomas C. Berg
 James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy University of St. 
 Thomas School of Law MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
 Minneapolis, MN   55403-2015
 Phone: 651 962 4918
 Fax: 651 962 4881
 E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edumailto:tcb...@stthomas.edu
 SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
 Weblog: http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com
 --
 --
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [religionlaw-boun

Re: Contraception Mandate

2013-11-26 Thread Marci Hamilton
This isn't lunch-- it is medical treatment for women.  (Contraceptive meds may 
work against some Catholics' beliefs but they are often taken for 
non-contraceptive reasons, so the contraception label for this is 
religio-centric).   

And women have a civil right against these employers not to be discriminated 
against on gender or religion.  A benefit plan that carves out medical 
treatment based on the employer's religious beliefs and that only applies to 
women is discriminatory.

Let's say that the employer believes that all women should have their heads 
covered because of religious belief .  Again, discrimination based on religion 
and gender in violation of Title VII.

Or how about an employer who believes women belong in the home taking care of 
their kids, and therefore scales salary to deincentivize women and drive them 
from the workplace.   ( the answer that these employers wouldn't hire women is 
a factual dodge, that avoids the legal issue). Same problem

Or let's say that a religious company owner learns that an employee had an 
abortion (which is consistent w her religious beliefs) and fires her for doing 
what he believes is murder.   Discrimination on religion and gender.

In each of these cases I think the govt has a compelling interest in protecting 
women against such discrimination in these workplaces and that there is no less 
restrictive means than requiring cos covered by Title VII to cover women's 
health care, period.  Given that the woman makes an intervening choice whether 
to use it, burden on the employer is de minimis.
(I know that there is a claim that the very payment for the plan that includes 
contraception violates beliefs but the question is LRM and this is it)

Brad throws in a red herring -- the believer need not choose to have a 
for-profit company with over 50 employees.  Heading up a nonprofit or a smaller 
company escapes these civil rights.   There is no constitutional right to make 
money and engage in gender and religious discrimination.


Having said all that, the problem here is really RFRA, but I have written 
extensively on its shortcomings and won't belabor the point here.   

Marci


Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Nov 26, 2013, at 5:52 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 I don’t see that at all.  Say the government requires 
 employers to buy lunch for their employees, and a religiously vegetarian 
 employer orders only vegetarian food.  I don’t think that somehow constitutes 
 the employer discriminating based on religion against people who don’t share 
 his beliefs.
  
 Now say that the government requires employers to buy lunch 
 for their employees, and include meat (since that’s what the government sees 
 as part of a healthy, balanced lunch), but has an exemption for religious 
 employers.  I don’t think that would somehow violate the Establishment 
 Clause, on a Thornton theory.  Unlike in Thornton, the exemption wouldn’t 
 impose any legal coercion on an objecting nonbeliever, by “giv[ing] the force 
 of law” to a believer’s action (Amos’s explanation of Thornton).  It would 
 simply -- like in Amos or in Cutter, which are indeed relevant for purposes 
 of understanding the boundaries of Thornton -- exempt the employer from a 
 government-imposed requirement, and indeed a requirement that (more so than 
 in Amos) involves a government-imposed burden on the employer’s religious 
 practice.  That the employees no longer get a government-mandated benefit 
 does not make the exemption unconstitutional.
  
 So I don’t think there’s an Establishment Clause problem with 
 such exemptions, and likewise there wouldn’t be with any such exemption 
 recognized under RFRA.  To be sure, this doesn’t tell us whether the 
 exemption should still be denied, on the theory that the denial is necessary 
 to serve a compelling government interest.  But that’s a separate question 
 from whether the exemption would be outright unconstitutional.
  
 Eugene
  
 Marci wrote:
  
 The employer is insisting that employees accept benefit plans tailored to his 
 religious beliefs, even though they accepted employment, which under federal 
 law
 prohibits the employer from discriminating on the basis of religion (or 
 gender).   
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To 

Re: Contraception Mandate

2013-11-26 Thread Marci Hamilton
There is nothing in title VII that governs all of the companies involved here 
that involves food, lunch, or children. These issues are about adult women 
employees who are protected by Title VII from employers who make religion a 
prerequisite to employment or who, in my view, craft benefits and/or salaries 
based on religion or gender.   

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Nov 26, 2013, at 6:59 PM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:

 Obviously, I'm not degrading the interest in contraception; I just think 
 saying this isn't lunch is a weird thing to say given the importance of 
 food.
 
 
 On Tue, Nov 26, 2013 at 4:55 PM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:
 Marci--
 
 Would you think that a mandate that all (private, for-profit) schools buy 
 lunch for their students be more compelling than this case?  In both cases, 
 the third parties can buy food or contraception outside of the 
 employer/school relationship?
 You say This isn't lunch-- it is medical treatment for women.
 In essence, which is more essential-- free food or free contraception?
 
 Michael
 
 
 On Tue, Nov 26, 2013 at 4:37 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 This isn't lunch-- it is medical treatment for women.  (Contraceptive meds 
 may work against some Catholics' beliefs but they are often taken for 
 non-contraceptive reasons, so the contraception label for this is 
 religio-centric).   
 
 And women have a civil right against these employers not to be 
 discriminated against on gender or religion.  A benefit plan that carves 
 out medical treatment based on the employer's religious beliefs and that 
 only applies to women is discriminatory.
 
 Let's say that the employer believes that all women should have their heads 
 covered because of religious belief .  Again, discrimination based on 
 religion and gender in violation of Title VII.
 
 Or how about an employer who believes women belong in the home taking care 
 of their kids, and therefore scales salary to deincentivize women and drive 
 them from the workplace.   ( the answer that these employers wouldn't hire 
 women is a factual dodge, that avoids the legal issue). Same problem
 
 Or let's say that a religious company owner learns that an employee had an 
 abortion (which is consistent w her religious beliefs) and fires her for 
 doing what he believes is murder.   Discrimination on religion and gender.
 
 In each of these cases I think the govt has a compelling interest in 
 protecting women against such discrimination in these workplaces and that 
 there is no less restrictive means than requiring cos covered by Title VII 
 to cover women's health care, period.  Given that the woman makes an 
 intervening choice whether to use it, burden on the employer is de minimis.
 (I know that there is a claim that the very payment for the plan that 
 includes contraception violates beliefs but the question is LRM and this is 
 it)
 
 Brad throws in a red herring -- the believer need not choose to have a 
 for-profit company with over 50 employees.  Heading up a nonprofit or a 
 smaller company escapes these civil rights.   There is no constitutional 
 right to make money and engage in gender and religious discrimination.
 
 
 Having said all that, the problem here is really RFRA, but I have written 
 extensively on its shortcomings and won't belabor the point here.   
 
 Marci
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 
 
 
 On Nov 26, 2013, at 5:52 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 
 I don’t see that at all.  Say the government requires 
 employers to buy lunch for their employees, and a religiously vegetarian 
 employer orders only vegetarian food.  I don’t think that somehow 
 constitutes the employer discriminating based on religion against people 
 who don’t share his beliefs.
 
  
 
 Now say that the government requires employers to buy 
 lunch for their employees, and include meat (since that’s what the 
 government sees as part of a healthy, balanced lunch), but has an 
 exemption for religious employers.  I don’t think that would somehow 
 violate the Establishment Clause, on a Thornton theory.  Unlike in 
 Thornton, the exemption wouldn’t impose any legal coercion on an objecting 
 nonbeliever, by “giv[ing] the force of law” to a believer’s action (Amos’s 
 explanation of Thornton).  It would simply -- like in Amos or in Cutter, 
 which are indeed relevant for purposes of understanding the boundaries of 
 Thornton -- exempt the employer from a government-imposed requirement, and 
 indeed a requirement that (more so than in Amos) involves a 
 government-imposed burden on the employer’s religious practice.  That the 
 employees no longer get a government-mandated benefit does not make the 
 exemption unconstitutional

Re: A right not to be compelled to create expression?

2013-08-24 Thread Marci Hamilton
Point of law--  Most freelancers are subject to work for hire agreements that 
divest copyright and make the purchaser the owner of the speech for all 
purposes.   

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 24, 2013, at 12:37 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 Well, New Mexico law covers “any establishment that provides 
 or offers its services ... to the public, but does not include a[n] ... 
 establishment that is by its nature and use distinctly private.”  That does 
 mean that a freelance writer who only writes on behalf of a limited set of 
 clients, rather than offering his services to the public at large, wouldn’t 
 be covered by this particular statute.  But a freelance writer who does 
 promote his services to the public would qualify, even if he exercises some 
 selectivity.  (Indeed, Huguenin says that there are other photography 
 commissions she won’t take, such as for pornography, horror films, and the 
 like, though chances are that she won’t even be approached for them in the 
 first place.  Conversely, my sense is that many freelance writers who offer 
 to hire themselves out to the public will take the great majority of jobs 
 that come their way, even though they too would draw the line somewhere.)  So 
 I can’t see how such freelance writers would be immune.
  
 But in any event, even if a freelance writer or photographer 
 is unselective, I can’t see how that person’s expression isn’t “her own.”  To 
 be sure, the public might not see an unselective photographer’s/writer’s 
 speech as equally expressing her own ideology.  But the writer or 
 photographer would still be creating the expression herself, using her own 
 artistic and literary creative judgment.
  
 The question, then, is:  Should people have a right not to be 
 compelled to create expression they think is wrong, just as they have a right 
 not to be compelled to distribute expression they think is wrong?  It seems 
 to me that the logic of Wooley should extend equally to both rights.  If 
 Maynard can’t be required to carry the motto “Live Free or Die” on his car, 
 then a Maynard who is a generally will-take-most-commissions freelance writer 
 can’t be required to write a press release or organizational newsletter that 
 expresses the view “Scientology is good.”  Indeed, the requirement to 
 actually create expression seems much more burdensome than simply the 
 requirement to carry a slogan on one’s car.
  
 Finally, note that the New Mexico Supreme Court expressly 
 disclaimed any argument that mere wedding photography is just too banal to be 
 expressive for purposes of this analysis (not that Eduardo so argued below, 
 but I’ve seen that argument elsewhere).  “This determination [that Elane 
 Photography is subject to the public accommodations law] has no relation to 
 the artistic merit of photographs produced by Elane Photography.  If Annie 
 Leibovitz or Peter Lindbergh worked as public accommodations in New Mexico, 
 they would be subject to the provisions of the NMHRA.”
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Penalver, Eduardo
 Sent: Friday, August 23, 2013 12:23 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: New Mexico decision and other First Amendment expression
  
 It seems to me, the more selective they are, (1) the less likely they are 
 covered by the statute (the predicate for the 1A claim) and (2) the more the 
 speech is their own (which does seem relevant to a compelled speech claim).
 
 On Aug 22, 2013, at 11:23 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 
 My sense is that many freelance writers are indeed pretty 
 unselective.  But, in any event, why should the writer’s or photographer’s 
 selectivity or unselectivity affect the First Amendment compelled speech 
 analysis?  I would think that a freelance writer who picks and chooses – but 
 absolutely refuses to write things for the Church of Scientology – and the 
 freelance writer who takes 99% of his commissions but thinks that the Church 
 of Scientology is just beyond the pale should have the same First Amendment 
 rights not to create expression that they think is wrong (or maybe that they 
 think is just too far wrong).
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Penalver, Eduardo
 Sent: Thursday, August 22, 2013 9:05 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: New Mexico decision and other First Amendment expression
  
 Not necessarily.  I don't think your hypothetical writer would necessarily 
 count as having held himself out as open to the public to ply his trade as 
 you've described it.  That is, I don't think that advertising by itself would 
 be enough 

Re: A right not to be compelled to create expression?

2013-08-24 Thread Marci Hamilton
I advise such all the time.  Those conditions are almost always met.  
Freelancers of all sorts are treated terribly by the copyright system.

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 24, 2013, at 4:19 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 (1)  A freelancer’s work can be treated as a “work for hire” 
 only if there’s an agreement and the work falls into one of several classes: 
 “a work specially ordered or commissioned for use as a contribution to a 
 collective work, as a part of a motion picture or other audiovisual work, as 
 a translation, as a supplementary work, as a compilation, as an instructional 
 text, as a test, as answer material for a test, or as an atlas, if the 
 parties expressly agree in a written instrument signed by them that the work 
 shall be considered a work made for hire.”  17 USC 101.  A press release 
 would not be a work for hire, for instance.
  
 (2)  A photographer’s work would generally not qualify for 
 being a work for hire, either.
  
 (3)  Of course, even if a work isn’t a work for hire, the 
 copyright can be assigned by a signed writing.  But I don’t see what that has 
 to do with the compelled-creation-of-expression issue.  If I go into 
 freelance press release writing, I think I ought to be free to say to the 
 Church of Scientology, “No, I’m not going to write a press release for you 
 promoting your religious events, because I disapprove of your religion.”  And 
 that is true regardless of who would own the copyright in the resulting press 
 release.  My objection isn’t to being required to own a copyright.  My 
 objection is to having to write things that I think it’s wrong for me to 
 write.
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Saturday, August 24, 2013 10:26 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: A right not to be compelled to create expression?
  
 Point of law--  Most freelancers are subject to work for hire agreements that 
 divest copyright and make the purchaser the owner of the speech for all 
 purposes.   
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
  
  
 
 On Aug 24, 2013, at 12:37 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 
 Well, New Mexico law covers “any establishment that provides 
 or offers its services ... to the public, but does not include a[n] ... 
 establishment that is by its nature and use distinctly private.”  That does 
 mean that a freelance writer who only writes on behalf of a limited set of 
 clients, rather than offering his services to the public at large, wouldn’t 
 be covered by this particular statute.  But a freelance writer who does 
 promote his services to the public would qualify, even if he exercises some 
 selectivity.  (Indeed, Huguenin says that there are other photography 
 commissions she won’t take, such as for pornography, horror films, and the 
 like, though chances are that she won’t even be approached for them in the 
 first place.  Conversely, my sense is that many freelance writers who offer 
 to hire themselves out to the public will take the great majority of jobs 
 that come their way, even though they too would draw the line somewhere.)  So 
 I can’t see how such freelance writers would be immune.
  
 But in any event, even if a freelance writer or photographer 
 is unselective, I can’t see how that person’s expression isn’t “her own.”  To 
 be sure, the public might not see an unselective photographer’s/writer’s 
 speech as equally expressing her own ideology.  But the writer or 
 photographer would still be creating the expression herself, using her own 
 artistic and literary creative judgment.
  
 The question, then, is:  Should people have a right not to be 
 compelled to create expression they think is wrong, just as they have a right 
 not to be compelled to distribute expression they think is wrong?  It seems 
 to me that the logic of Wooley should extend equally to both rights.  If 
 Maynard can’t be required to carry the motto “Live Free or Die” on his car, 
 then a Maynard who is a generally will-take-most-commissions freelance writer 
 can’t be required to write a press release or organizational newsletter that 
 expresses the view “Scientology is good.”  Indeed, the requirement to 
 actually create expression seems much more burdensome than simply the 
 requirement to carry a slogan on one’s car.
  
 Finally, note that the New Mexico Supreme Court expressly 
 disclaimed any argument that mere wedding photography is just too banal to be 
 expressive for purposes of this analysis (not that Eduardo so argued below, 
 but I’ve seen

Re: New Mexico Supreme Court Rules Against Wedding Photographer Who Discriminated Against Gays

2013-08-23 Thread Marci Hamilton
Wedding photography is speech for money, and a lot of it.   The photographer 
who depicts the wedding in a non- joyous manner is not going to get paid, is 
going to receive terrible reviews online, and even be boycotted.   She or he 
will find themselves with no wedding jobs.  The photographer who shows up 
unhired (to express himself) to depict the wedding negatively is trespassing, 
and the Fred Phelps of weddings.

The fact they are not making the big money is because they engage in invidious 
discrimination.  I understand these times are difficult for those who are 
having to adjust to the civil rights of homosexuals, but adjust they must.  
They have lost the war on all fronts --medical, moral, and public policy

It isn't remotely compelled speech.   It is a chosen career.  The 
photographer of today in New Mexico who objects to same-sex wedding jobs is 
identical to the photographer after Loving objecting to mixed race marriages.   
Out of luck.

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 23, 2013, at 2:47 AM, Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu 
wrote:

 To follow up on Will's point, would the photographers violate the law, or the 
 contract the law requires them to make, if they did not attempt to portray 
 the wedding as a joyous celebration? I presume they would at least violate 
 the implied terms of the contract that is forced upon them. If so, then the 
 law is not just requiring artists (and wedding photographers are artists) to 
 create art with a particular content, but also requiring them to express a 
 viewpoint that is not theirs.
 
 It is puzzling to me, and disheartening, that list members do not seem to 
 think that this is coerced speech. Of course the auto mechanic's work is not 
 generally expressive -- almost never even rising to the level of symbolic 
 speech. A photographer creates art; the photographer's work is inherently, 
 traditionally, and (in the case of a wedding photographer) inescapably 
 expression, fully protected, except, it seems, in New Mexico, by the First 
 Amendment.
 
 Mark Scarberry
 Pepperdine University School of Law
 
 Sent from my Verizon Wireless 4G LTE Smartphone
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: New Mexico Supreme Court Rules Against Wedding Photographer Who Discriminated Against Gays

2013-08-23 Thread Marci Hamilton
And if the NYT refused to include same- sex couples in its wedding section, it 
would be sued.   Or mixed race couples.   Or to sell to same-sex couples.

Except for the narrow issue in Hosanna Tabor, First Amendment rights do not 
immunize you from the civil rights laws.   

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 23, 2013, at 4:07 AM, Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu 
wrote:

 Of course it's also very clear that getting paid for your expressive efforts 
 doesn't reduce the level of 1st Am protection you are entitled to. The NY 
 Times, for example, still sells a few papers, and they charge for on-line 
 access, too, as my monthly credit card statement attests. 
 
 Mark Scarberry
 Pepperdine University School of Law
 
 
 Sent from my Verizon Wireless 4G LTE Smartphone
 
 
 
  Original message 
 From: Brad Pardee bp51...@windstream.net 
 Date: 08/23/2013 12:44 AM (GMT-08:00) 
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics' religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu 
 Subject: RE: New Mexico Supreme Court Rules Against Wedding Photographer Who 
 Discriminated Against Gays 
 
 
 We may have to agree to disagree on the role of the wedding photographer.  My 
 wife and I both considered the wedding photographs to be part and parcel of 
 the event and the photographer to be a member of the wedding party who was 
 most assuredly there to celebrate with us.  We would not have chosen a 
 photographer who would not see their role that way.  The same would be true 
 of the wedding planner, who is also providing a service for a fee.
  
 I have not the faintest idea what you are talking about with regards to the 
 nature landscape or wildlife photographers or how that ties in to the subject 
 at hand.
  
 Brad
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Jean Dudley
 Sent: Friday, August 23, 2013 2:28 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: New Mexico Supreme Court Rules Against Wedding Photographer Who 
 Discriminated Against Gays
  
  
 On Aug 22, 2013, at Thu, Aug 22,  9:06 PM, Brad Pardee 
 bp51...@windstream.net wrote:
 
 
 This is not correct.  The issue is neither the customers' identity or the 
 free market.  It is about the merchant being required to participate in 
 events that they cannot participate in by virtue of the tenets of thier faith 
 in order to engage in commerce. 
  
 Speaking as a photographer (although not a wedding photographer) you are not 
 participating in the wedding.  You are providing a service for a fee.  A 
 participant is a member of the wedding party.  You are not there to 
 celebrate, you are there to do a job.  A photographer isn't standing there 
 with a drink in one hand, and a piece of cake in the other.  A photographer 
 has a light meter in one hand, and a cable release in the other.  Eventually, 
 the photographer has their hand out for the check.  
  
 Wedding photography is a business.  If you are constrained by your religion 
 to refuse to do business based on sexual orientation, that is discrimination. 
  That's against the law.  
  
 BTW, I know of no nature/landscape/wildlife photogs who refuse to do their 
 job because trees have orgies in the spring, mountains refuse to multiply 
 and be fruitful, or swans are known to engage in lifelong same sex pairings. 
  
  
  
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: New Mexico decision and other First Amendment expression

2013-08-23 Thread Marci Hamilton
Where is the potential civil rights violation in this hypothetical?

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 23, 2013, at 8:45 AM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:

 Are people who support the decision in New Mexico also willing to support a 
 law forcing photographers who object to war to take pictures of army battle 
 drills if hired by a government contractor?  If not, what is the difference?  
 
 
 On Thu, Aug 22, 2013 at 10:20 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 My sense is that many freelance writers are indeed pretty 
 unselective.  But, in any event, why should the writer’s or photographer’s 
 selectivity or unselectivity affect the First Amendment compelled speech 
 analysis?  I would think that a freelance writer who picks and chooses – but 
 absolutely refuses to write things for the Church of Scientology – and the 
 freelance writer who takes 99% of his commissions but thinks that the Church 
 of Scientology is just beyond the pale should have the same First Amendment 
 rights not to create expression that they think is wrong (or maybe that they 
 think is just too far wrong).
 
  
 
 Eugene
 
  
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Penalver, Eduardo
 Sent: Thursday, August 22, 2013 9:05 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: New Mexico decision and other First Amendment expression
 
  
 
 Not necessarily.  I don't think your hypothetical writer would necessarily 
 count as having held himself out as open to the public to ply his trade as 
 you've described it.  That is, I don't think that advertising by itself 
 would be enough to count as holding oneself out.  Here, the photographer did 
 just that - held herself out as open to all comers (except the disfavored 
 group) at a price.  Apart from same sex couples, there's nothing in the 
 opinion suggesting much selectivity in her business model.  Her holding out 
 was an essential premise underlying the court's decision.  She did not 
 contest her status as a public accommodation, after all.
 
 
 On Aug 22, 2013, at 10:43 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 
 A quick question, focusing on the compelled speech side of 
 the issue rather than just the RFRA side.  The court’s logic isn’t limited 
 to sexual orientation discrimination (as opposed to other kinds of 
 discrimination) or to photographers (as opposed to other creators of 
 protected expression).  Say that a freelance writer, who advertises himself 
 to the public at large, is asked by the Church of Scientology (or the LDS 
 Church or any other religious group) to write promotional material for it. 
 
  
 
 He says no:  He refuses to create speech that he views as being factually or 
 morally false, for instance by glorifying as right, worthy, holy, or 
 beautiful that which he believes is morally corrupt.  Following 
 Solzhenitsyn, he wants to “Live Not by Lies” – to “not write, not sign, not 
 print through any means even a single phrase that distorts, in his opinion, 
 the truth,” to not, “in painting, sculpture, photography, music, or through 
 technological means” “depict, accompany, or retransmit even a single lying 
 thought, not a single distortion of the truth, that he recognizes” (quotes 
 are from Solzhenitsyn’s “Live Not by Lies” essay).
 
  
 
 The Scientologists then sue him for his discriminating against them based on 
 religion.  Am I right in thinking that, under the New Mexico Supreme Court’s 
 reasoning, requiring him to pay damages would be seen as constitutionally 
 permissible, and as not being an unconstitutional speech compulsion?  If so, 
 is that a constitutionally sound result?
 
  
 
 Eugene
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are 
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or 
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.
 
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are 
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or 
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.
 
 
 
 -- 
 Michael Worley
 BYU Law School, Class of 2014
 ___
 To post, send message to 

Re: New Mexico decision and other First Amendment expression

2013-08-23 Thread Marci Hamilton
Let me clarify: the issue in New Mexico is a conflict between the civil rights 
of same sex couples and for-profit photographers who hold themselves out as a 
public accommodation.The govt does not have civil rights.

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 23, 2013, at 8:45 AM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:

 Are people who support the decision in New Mexico also willing to support a 
 law forcing photographers who object to war to take pictures of army battle 
 drills if hired by a government contractor?  If not, what is the difference?  
 
 
 On Thu, Aug 22, 2013 at 10:20 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 My sense is that many freelance writers are indeed pretty 
 unselective.  But, in any event, why should the writer’s or photographer’s 
 selectivity or unselectivity affect the First Amendment compelled speech 
 analysis?  I would think that a freelance writer who picks and chooses – but 
 absolutely refuses to write things for the Church of Scientology – and the 
 freelance writer who takes 99% of his commissions but thinks that the Church 
 of Scientology is just beyond the pale should have the same First Amendment 
 rights not to create expression that they think is wrong (or maybe that they 
 think is just too far wrong).
 
  
 
 Eugene
 
  
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Penalver, Eduardo
 Sent: Thursday, August 22, 2013 9:05 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: New Mexico decision and other First Amendment expression
 
  
 
 Not necessarily.  I don't think your hypothetical writer would necessarily 
 count as having held himself out as open to the public to ply his trade as 
 you've described it.  That is, I don't think that advertising by itself 
 would be enough to count as holding oneself out.  Here, the photographer did 
 just that - held herself out as open to all comers (except the disfavored 
 group) at a price.  Apart from same sex couples, there's nothing in the 
 opinion suggesting much selectivity in her business model.  Her holding out 
 was an essential premise underlying the court's decision.  She did not 
 contest her status as a public accommodation, after all.
 
 
 On Aug 22, 2013, at 10:43 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 
 A quick question, focusing on the compelled speech side of 
 the issue rather than just the RFRA side.  The court’s logic isn’t limited 
 to sexual orientation discrimination (as opposed to other kinds of 
 discrimination) or to photographers (as opposed to other creators of 
 protected expression).  Say that a freelance writer, who advertises himself 
 to the public at large, is asked by the Church of Scientology (or the LDS 
 Church or any other religious group) to write promotional material for it. 
 
  
 
 He says no:  He refuses to create speech that he views as being factually or 
 morally false, for instance by glorifying as right, worthy, holy, or 
 beautiful that which he believes is morally corrupt.  Following 
 Solzhenitsyn, he wants to “Live Not by Lies” – to “not write, not sign, not 
 print through any means even a single phrase that distorts, in his opinion, 
 the truth,” to not, “in painting, sculpture, photography, music, or through 
 technological means” “depict, accompany, or retransmit even a single lying 
 thought, not a single distortion of the truth, that he recognizes” (quotes 
 are from Solzhenitsyn’s “Live Not by Lies” essay).
 
  
 
 The Scientologists then sue him for his discriminating against them based on 
 religion.  Am I right in thinking that, under the New Mexico Supreme Court’s 
 reasoning, requiring him to pay damages would be seen as constitutionally 
 permissible, and as not being an unconstitutional speech compulsion?  If so, 
 is that a constitutionally sound result?
 
  
 
 Eugene
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are 
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or 
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.
 
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are 
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or 
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.

Re: New Mexico Supreme Court Rules Against Wedding Photographer Who Discriminated Against Gays

2013-08-22 Thread Marci Hamilton
That's right, Brad, if you want to have a for-profit company in a free market 
economy, you shouldn't be able to choose your customers based on race, gender, 
sexual orientation, or religion.   Isn't that how the market works best-- being 
fueled by products and price, rather than purchaser's or seller's identity?   
The market driven by religion that Hobby Lobby and Elane's Photography would 
like to occupy is driven by identity, not the fair market.   

A Christian Scientist can't be a doctor.   If you can't fulfill the obligations 
of a trade due to your religious beliefs, you can't.   That is not an 
infringement of liberty by the state; it is an infringement of liberty by the 
religious belief/organization.   No constitutional violation.

Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 22, 2013, at 10:36 PM, Brad Pardee bp51...@windstream.net wrote:

 The problem with this rationale is that the religious liberty issue is about 
 being forced to be an active participant in a specific event.  If the 
 photographer refused to take school pictures, Christmas card photos, etc., of 
 homosexual  individuals, then there might be a question of discrimination.  
 But a wedding photographer is an active member of the wedding party and an 
 active participant in the wedding activities.  The parallel to a wedding 
 between people of different races is flawed because discriminating against 
 people whose skin is a different color makes no more sense than 
 discriminating between people whose hair is a different color or whose eyes 
 are a different color.  The difference between males and females, however is 
 quite substantive and not merely a matter of appearance.
  
 It's the same situation as in the recent story out of Oregon where the state 
 Attorney General is investigating a bakery that would not make a wedding cake 
 for a lesbian couple.  Unless the bakery refused to sell cookies, pies, other 
 cakes, etc. to homosexuals, there might be a question of discrimination.  
 But, much like the wedding photographer, the bakery that provides the wedding 
 cake is an active participant in the wedding activities.
  
 We have now established that, if your faith does not allow you to be a 
 participant in a same-sex wedding, you are not permitted to be a wedding 
 photographer for anybody.  You are not permitted to bake wedding cakes for 
 anybody.  We had a lengthy discussion here some time back about a woman who 
 was, if I recall correctly, kicked out of a graduate psychology program 
 because of what her faith teaches on the subject of sexual orientation.  And 
 this is what passes for religious freedom in today's climate.
  
 Brad Pardee
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Joel
 Sent: Thursday, August 22, 2013 2:28 PM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: New Mexico Supreme Court Rules Against Wedding Photographer Who 
 Discriminated Against Gays
  
  
 New Mexico Supreme Court Rules Against Wedding Photographer Who Discriminated 
 Against Gays
 Jonathan Higbee | August 22, 2013
  
 The New Mexico state Supreme Court has ruled against a photography business 
 that refused to photograph a gay couple's commitment ceremony because THE 
 BIBLE.
 Advertisement
  
 From an ACLU press release:
  
 The New Mexico Supreme Court ruled today that Elane Photography illegally 
 discriminated against a same-sex couple by refusing to photograph their 
 commitment ceremony due to the business owner’s religious beliefs.
  
 The opinion stated: “We conclude that a commercial photography business that 
 offers its services to the public, thereby increasing its visibility to 
 potential clients, is subject to the antidiscrimination provisions of the 
 [New Mexico Human Rights Act] and must serve same-sex couples on the same 
 basis that it serves opposite-sex couples. Therefore, when Elane Photography 
 refused to photograph a same-sex commitment ceremony, it violated the NMHRA 
 in the same way as if it had refused to photograph a wedding between people 
 of different races.”
  
 “When you open a business, you are opening your doors to all people in your 
 community, not just the select few who share your personal beliefs,” said 
 Louise Melling, deputy legal director of the American Civil Liberties Union. 
 “The Constitution guarantees religious freedom in this country, but we are 
 not entitled to use our beliefs as an excuse to discriminate against other 
 people.”
 - See more at: 
 http://instinctmagazine.com/post/new-mexico-supreme-court-rules-against-wedding-photographer-who-discriminated-against-gays#sthash.NqCIsH37.dpuf
  
  
  
  
 Joel L. Sogol
 Attorney at Law
 811 21st Ave.
 Tuscaloosa, Alabama  35401
 ph (205) 345-0966
 fx (205) 345-0971
 email:  jlsa...@wwisp.com
 website: www.joelsogol.com
  
 Ben Franklin observed that truth wins a fair fight - which is why we 

Re: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate

2013-08-18 Thread Marci Hamilton
The pill is widely prescribed for serious medical problems as I delineated 
earlier.  And the decision of when to have children is not remotely limited to 
pleasure.  

The govt has a compelling interest in ensuring the maximal availability of 
birth control for these medical reasons and to shore up the right of women to 
choose.

The govt also has a compelling interest in treating men and women equally.  
There is a strong argument by women that a health care system that does not 
include reproductive health care is discriminating against women.



Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 18, 2013, at 12:54 PM, mallamud malla...@camden.rutgers.edu wrote:

 Marci,
I have trouble seeing the compelling nature in the government's interest 
 to provide contraception.  The cost is too low, and basically, contraception 
 allows for pleasure and the enhancement of interpersonal relationships. The 
 health justification comes closer, but compared to the provision of needles 
 for drug use (I do not know if that is a compelling interest), there is 
 certainly not generally addiction involved.  Even with abortion, government 
 does not need to fund it--the compelling interest is in not making it illegal.
Jon
 
 On 2013-08-17 10:57, Marci Hamilton wrote:
 I agree w Chip and Jim on the baseline issue, but also the previous
 point about the point of the Religion Clauses is not just rights for
 the believer but also the path to peace in a diverse religious
 culture. Lee and Bowen v Roy stand for the proposition that if one
 chooses to employ or to take advantage of govt benefits, the Free
 Exercise Clause does not provide a way out of the obligations that
 come w the voluntary decision made by the believer. RFRA opens a door
 for believers to get past these sensible decisions, but I do not think
 that even if the parent who voluntarily chooses to cover his children
 over the age of majority could prove substantial burden, the govt does
 have a compelling interest in giving women the most realistic
 opportunity to choose for themselves whether to use contraception for
 any reason and to make sure those choices are as unhindered as men's
 decisions to pursue their own choices. The women are being protected
 by the govt from coercion by employers and parents.
 
 The govt also has a compelling interest in keeping health care costs
 under control. Chip mentions unwanted pregnancy; I mentioned some of
 the medical reasons reproductive health services are needed, which can
 affect GDP if untreated. And finally, there is the govt's legitimate
 compelling interest in ensuring the health care system does not
 discriminate on the basis of gender or religion and does enable
 women's choices. There is no less restrictive means of giving each
 woman her own choice regarding reproductive health than giving her a
 choice.
 
 The abortion decisions to date have all been about what the state can
 do to restrict women's rights. But those restrictions are not
 constitutionally required. Just because the government is not required
 to pay for reproductive health care does not mean the govt does not
 have a compelling interest in providing it. This is a new scenario
 where the govt is on the side of women and reproductive rights, which
 entails new ways of thinking.
 
 Marci
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton
 
 On Aug 17, 2013, at 8:54 AM, James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu [8]
 wrote:
 
 Eugene,
 
 No federal or state law required the Amish farmer in Lee to employ
 workers, but once he made that choice, the Supreme Court used the
 federal requirements governing employment benefits as the baseline
 for evaluating externalities (Granting an exemption from social
 security taxes to an employer operates to impose the employer's
 religious faith on the employees.).
 
 Likewise, although no federal or state law requires parents to put
 their adult children on their insurance, once they make that choice,
 the argument is that federal requirements governing health benefits
 should be used as the baseline for evaluating externalities.
 
 Of course, it's certainly possible to argue that the baseline should
 be set in a different place in parent/adult-child context than in
 the employer/employee context, or in the health insurance context
 than the employment context, but I think Chip is right that --
 wherever one ultimately comes out -- this is a classic baseline
 problem.
 
 - Jim
 
 Jim Oleske
 Lewis  Clark Law School
 SSRN Page: http://ssrn.com/author=357864 [3]
 Faculty Page: http://law.lclark.edu/faculty/james_oleske/ [4]
 
 On Fri, Aug 16, 2013 at 8:35 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu
 [5] wrote:
 
 But wait: How can you read ACA as setting a baseline that _the
 parents _should guarantee their adult children a full

Re: Harmony and the freedom of religion (RE: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate)

2013-08-18 Thread Marci Hamilton
Thanks, Ellis, for your valuable post.  Let's also add that the framing 
generation understood and articulated a distinction between liberty and 
licentiousness, as I have written before.   And set a boundary on religious 
liberty of safety and the public good.  Indeed, pastors preached abiding by the 
law
from the pulpit.

 The principle was ordered liberty from the beginning, not what I have come 
to think of as narcissistic liberty, which is that liberty that is supposed to 
be judged only from the inside of the believer's head and world view and fails 
to take truly seriously the culture's, third-party, and historical limits.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 16, 2013, at 3:54 PM, West, Ellis ew...@richmond.edu wrote:

 I fear that many of you will think I am pompous, if not arrogant, in saying 
 what follows, but I feel compelled to respond to Brad Pardee's post.  For 
 years now, I have been reading all the posts on this blog, most of which have 
 dealt with the issue of when, on the basis of religious liberty, persons have 
 a right to be exempt from having to obey valid secular that persons generally 
 have to obey.  Recently, I find myself just shaking my head, because the 
 debate goes on and on, and will continue to do so, because there is simply no 
 clear answer to the question.  The sad thing about the debate is that as it 
 has been structured, it is so unnecessary.  Of course, if legislatures want 
 to exempt certain persons from certain laws on the basis of certain criteria, 
 that is their prerogative.  The debate on this blog, however, has been based 
 on the assumption that religious freedom, at least under certain 
 circumstances, gives persons a right to be exempt from obeying valid civil 
 laws.  More specifically, too many entries assume, along with Brad, that the 
 essence of religious freedom is that a person is not forced to choose between 
 obeying their God and obeying their government and [t]hat's certainly at 
 the heart of free exercise.
 
 If, however, Brad is referring to the free exercise of religion guaranteed in 
 the First Amendment, then his understanding of religious freedom is way off 
 base.  Based on a thorough review of the historical evidence, I am finishing 
 a book on the original meaning of the free exercise clause, and I have yet to 
 find any early American advocate of religious liberty, except for some 
 Quakers, who understood it as meaning that persons could not be forced to 
 choose between obeying their God and obeying their government.  (There may be 
 such persons, but I have not found them.)  The issue of religion-based 
 exemptions from valid laws was simply not on their minds, and they did not 
 address it explicitly.  Rather the all-consuming issue was that of 
 establishments of religion, and freedom of religion meant freedom from such 
 establishments and all laws associated with them, i.e., freedom from laws 
 whose primary purpose was to favor one religion, religious belief or 
 practice, over another or to discriminate for and against persons because of 
 their religion.  Stated differently, the no establishment and free exercise 
 clauses were simply two different ways of saying the same thing.  To the 
 extent that early Americans implicitly addressed the issue, they emphasized 
 that religion could not be used as an excuse for obeying valid civil laws.  
 Only some Quakers would have agreed with Brad's understanding of religious 
 freedom, but as I showed years ago in an article in the Journal of Law and 
 Religion, when they attempted to get Pennsylvania to add a provision to its 
 constitution that would reflect their understanding, it was rejected.  
 Finally, contrary to what Brad says, the philosophy behind religious freedom 
 is not the same as the philosophy behind conscientious objection.  The former 
 pertains to what the government should not do, whereas the latter pertains to 
 whether an individual should follow his conscience regardless of what others, 
 including the government, may do to him or her.
 
 Ellis M. West
 Emeritus Professor of Political Science 
 University of Richmond, VA 23173
 804-289-8536
 ew...@richmond.edu
 
 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Brad Pardee
 Sent: Friday, August 16, 2013 2:36 PM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: Harmony and the freedom of religion (RE: New Twist On Challenge to 
 ACA Contraceptive Mandate)
 
 I'm not certain that this is a correct understanding of the purpose of 
 freedom of religion.  It's always been my understanding that the essence of 
 religious freedom is that a person is not forced to choose between obeying 
 their God and obeying their government.  That's certainly at the heart of 
 free exercise, where the government ought not to have a blank check to 
 

Re: Harmony and the freedom of religion (RE: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate)

2013-08-18 Thread Marci Hamilton
But if you take the restoration part of RFRA seriously, Lee and Bowen are the 
lead cases in these scenarios.  I don't think you can have it both ways that 
RFRA restores the prior case law and it requires radical new ways of reasoning 
w respect to large federal or state administrative programs.

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 16, 2013, at 4:21 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 I agree with Ellis that the Free Exercise Clause shouldn't 
 generally be read as mandating religious exemptions.  But the debate these 
 days (at least on this blog) is usually not about the Free Exercise Clause 
 but about RFRAs, which do involve legislatively created exemptions (albeit 
 ones created in bulk rather than on a statute-by-state basis).  The ACA 
 debate is mostly about the federal RFRA.  The Missouri legislator would, I 
 assume, be claiming the protection of the Missouri RFRA.  And those statutes 
 do seem to take the view that the essence of religious freedom is that a 
 person is not forced to choose between obeying their God and obeying their 
 government and [t]hat's certainly at the heart of free exercise” as secured 
 by the statutes, if not by the federal Free Exercise Clause.
  
 Eugene
  
  -Original Message-
  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
  boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of West, Ellis
  Sent: Friday, August 16, 2013 12:55 PM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Harmony and the freedom of religion (RE: New Twist On
  Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate)
 
  I fear that many of you will think I am pompous, if not arrogant, in saying
  what follows, but I feel compelled to respond to Brad Pardee's post.  For
  years now, I have been reading all the posts on this blog, most of which 
  have
  dealt with the issue of when, on the basis of religious liberty, persons 
  have a
  right to be exempt from having to obey valid secular that persons generally
  have to obey.  Recently, I find myself just shaking my head, because the
  debate goes on and on, and will continue to do so, because there is simply 
  no
  clear answer to the question.  The sad thing about the debate is that as it 
  has
  been structured, it is so unnecessary.  Of course, if legislatures want to
  exempt certain persons from certain laws on the basis of certain criteria, 
  that
  is their prerogative.  The debate on this blog, however, has been based on
  the assumption that religious freedom, at least under certain circumstances,
  gives persons a right to be exempt from obeying valid civil laws.  More
  specifically, too many entries assume, along with Brad, that the essence of
  religious freedom is that a person is not forced to choose between obeying
  their God and obeying their government and [t]hat's certainly at the heart
  of free exercise.
 
  If, however, Brad is referring to the free exercise of religion guaranteed 
  in
  the First Amendment, then his understanding of religious freedom is way off
  base.  Based on a thorough review of the historical evidence, I am 
  finishing a
  book on the original meaning of the free exercise clause, and I have yet to
  find any early American advocate of religious liberty, except for some
  Quakers, who understood it as meaning that persons could not be forced to
  choose between obeying their God and obeying their government.  (There
  may be such persons, but I have not found them.)  The issue of religion-
  based exemptions from valid laws was simply not on their minds, and they
  did not address it explicitly.  Rather the all-consuming issue was that of
  establishments of religion, and freedom of religion meant freedom from
  such establishments and all laws associated with them, i.e., freedom from
  laws whose primary purpose was to favor one religion, religious belief or
  practice, over another or to discriminate for and against persons because of
  their religion.  Stated differently, the no establishment and free exercise
  clauses were simply two different ways of saying the same thing.  To the
  extent that early Americans implicitly addressed the issue, they emphasized
  that religion could not be used as an excuse for obeying valid civil laws.  
  Only
  some Quakers would have agreed with Brad's understanding of religious
  freedom, but as I showed years ago in an article in the Journal of Law and
  Religion, when they attempted to get Pennsylvania to add a provision to its
  constitution that would reflect their understanding, it was rejected.  
  Finally,
  contrary to what Brad says, the philosophy behind religious freedom is not
  the same as the philosophy behind conscientious objection.  The former
  pertains to what the government should not do, whereas the latter pertains
  to whether an individual should follow his conscience regardless of what
  others, 

Re: Harmony and the freedom of religion (RE: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate)

2013-08-18 Thread Marci Hamilton
Reread the entirety of the memorial.
Madison was very concerned about the abusive power of the clergy.

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 18, 2013, at 6:20 PM, Richard Dougherty dou...@udallas.edu wrote:

 I would think that this would be a matter of significance only for
 those who afford some degree of significance to a jurisprudence of
 original intent.
 
 But if one does take such matters seriously, I would suggest that it
 is hard, indeed impossible, to read James Madison's Memorial and
 Remonstrance as not protecting the free exercise of religion, and not
 simply against the interference of what one might consider
 liberty-denying religion.  Just one passage, from the first paragraph:
 We maintain therefore that in matters of Religion, no man's right is
 abridged by the institution of Civil Society and that Religion is
 wholly exempt from its cognizance.
 
 Richard Dougherty
 
 On Fri, Aug 16, 2013 at 2:54 PM, West, Ellis ew...@richmond.edu wrote:
 
 I fear that many of you will think I am pompous, if not arrogant, in saying 
 what follows, but I feel compelled to respond to Brad Pardee's post.  For 
 years now, I have been reading all the posts on this blog, most of which 
 have dealt with the issue of when, on the basis of religious liberty, 
 persons have a right to be exempt from having to obey valid secular that 
 persons generally have to obey.  Recently, I find myself just shaking my 
 head, because the debate goes on and on, and will continue to do so, because 
 there is simply no clear answer to the question.  The sad thing about the 
 debate is that as it has been structured, it is so unnecessary.  Of course, 
 if legislatures want to exempt certain persons from certain laws on the 
 basis of certain criteria, that is their prerogative.  The debate on this 
 blog, however, has been based on the assumption that religious freedom, at 
 least under certain circumstances, gives persons a right to be exempt from 
 obeying valid civil laws.  More specifically, too many entries assume, along 
 with Brad, that the essence of religious freedom is that a person is not 
 forced to choose between obeying their God and obeying their government and 
 [t]hat's certainly at the heart of free exercise.
 
 If, however, Brad is referring to the free exercise of religion guaranteed 
 in the First Amendment, then his understanding of religious freedom is way 
 off base.  Based on a thorough review of the historical evidence, I am 
 finishing a book on the original meaning of the free exercise clause, and I 
 have yet to find any early American advocate of religious liberty, except 
 for some Quakers, who understood it as meaning that persons could not be 
 forced to choose between obeying their God and obeying their government.  
 (There may be such persons, but I have not found them.)  The issue of 
 religion-based exemptions from valid laws was simply not on their minds, and 
 they did not address it explicitly.  Rather the all-consuming issue was that 
 of establishments of religion, and freedom of religion meant freedom from 
 such establishments and all laws associated with them, i.e., freedom from 
 laws whose primary purpose was to favor one religion, religious belief or 
 practice, over another or to discriminate for and against persons because of 
 their religion.  Stated differently, the no establishment and free exercise 
 clauses were simply two different ways of saying the same thing.  To the 
 extent that early Americans implicitly addressed the issue, they emphasized 
 that religion could not be used as an excuse for obeying valid civil laws.  
 Only some Quakers would have agreed with Brad's understanding of religious 
 freedom, but as I showed years ago in an article in the Journal of Law and 
 Religion, when they attempted to get Pennsylvania to add a provision to its 
 constitution that would reflect their understanding, it was rejected.  
 Finally, contrary to what Brad says, the philosophy behind religious freedom 
 is not the same as the philosophy behind conscientious objection.  The 
 former pertains to what the government should not do, whereas the latter 
 pertains to whether an individual should follow his conscience regardless of 
 what others, including the government, may do to him or her.
 
 Ellis M. West
 Emeritus Professor of Political Science
 University of Richmond, VA 23173
 804-289-8536
 ew...@richmond.edu
 
 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Brad Pardee
 Sent: Friday, August 16, 2013 2:36 PM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: Harmony and the freedom of religion (RE: New Twist On Challenge to 
 ACA Contraceptive Mandate)
 
 I'm not certain that this is a correct understanding of the purpose of 
 freedom of religion.  It's always been my understanding that the essence of 
 

Re: Harmony and the freedom of religion (RE: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate)

2013-08-18 Thread Marci Hamilton
As I have said repeatedly, I strongly disagree with the notion that Smith 
created a new regime.  It was an accurate statement of the existing case law.  
RFRA is a new regime parading as a restoration.Applying Sherbert or the 
other unemployment compensation case to any other scenario is inconsistent w 
the prior case law.  So we have the Sherbert/Yoder standard being bandied about 
for facts that never would have received it.  That is why we have these strands 
of discussion that are incoherent at times.

Historical limits on free exercise provide a robust limitation to the current 
push for religious liberty, which is unprecedented in history.   My view is 
heavily influenced by Levy, who brilliantly showed how the Religion Clauses 
evolved over time to a stronger and stronger separation principle.  Therefore, 
wherever we started, it is not that the doctrine has naturally evolved to 
religious narcissism, but rather to concept of separation.   So original 
intent, read in light of the working out of the Religion Clauses, works against 
the RFRA/religious-believers-should win-all-(or most)-arguments approach.   
That is why RFRA could only happen legislatively ---  and not through the 
courts.   And why, in my view, it is unconstitutional and illegitimate.

I assume, though, that Mark's point was directed at the notion that substantive 
due process is a new right.   Speaking as a woman and a supporter of the 
Federalists' perspective at the framing, I don't think these rights are new 
but rather rights over our bodies that appropriately are recognized today.   
The Federalists were correct that the problem w a Bill of Rights is that it 
would be assumed that all rights were therefore enumerated, but it was humanly 
impossible to do so.   Their most important insight was that the Framers were 
fallible humans who could not possibly enumerate all rights. Or fully 
comprehend how this governing system would work out over time and how rights 
would need to be defined over time. Their bedrock belief that they could see 
only through a glass darkly is critical to understanding how the status and 
role of women could work itself out over time.   The bedrock principles were 
there even if the rights holders (slaves and women) were not apparent!
  at the time.

  This is at base a Hegelian approach toward the working out of rights, but one 
that in my view takes the best account of the many factors at play.

I apologize for going off topic, but thought I might as well explain myself.  

Marci


Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 18, 2013, at 6:54 PM, Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu 
wrote:

 In response to Marci, who has expressed strong support on this list for 
 abortion rights: 
 
 It is very difficult to square her commitment to historical limits on 
 individual rights with any robust version of abortion rights, as against 
 state laws. 
 
 Historical limits provide much less of a barrier to (or more likely a boost 
 to) robust protection of religious freedom (such as the protection given by 
 federal and state RFRAs, and to some degree by the Constitution, even under 
 the highly-restrictive post-Smith regime).
 
 Mark
 
 Mark S. Scarberry
 Professor of Law
 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
 
 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Sunday, August 18, 2013 3:03 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Harmony and the freedom of religion (RE: New Twist On Challenge 
 to ACA Contraceptive Mandate)
 
 Thanks, Ellis, for your valuable post.  Let's also add that the framing 
 generation understood and articulated a distinction between liberty and 
 licentiousness, as I have written before.   And set a boundary on religious 
 liberty of safety and the public good.  Indeed, pastors preached abiding by 
 the law
 from the pulpit.
 
 The principle was ordered liberty from the beginning, not what I have come 
 to think of as narcissistic liberty, which is that liberty that is supposed 
 to be judged only from the inside of the believer's head and world view and 
 fails to take truly seriously the culture's, third-party, and historical 
 limits.
 
 Marci
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages

Re: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate

2013-08-17 Thread Marci Hamilton
I agree w Chip and Jim on the baseline issue, but also the previous point about 
the point of the Religion Clauses is not just rights for the believer but also 
the path to peace in a diverse religious culture.   Lee and Bowen v Roy stand 
for the proposition that if one chooses to employ or to take advantage of govt 
benefits, the Free Exercise Clause does not provide a way out of the 
obligations that come w the voluntary decision made by the believer.  RFRA 
opens a door for believers to get past these sensible decisions, but I do not 
think that even if the parent who voluntarily chooses to cover his children 
over the age of majority could prove substantial burden, the govt does have a 
compelling interest in giving women the most realistic opportunity to choose 
for themselves whether to use contraception for any reason and to make sure 
those choices are as unhindered as men's decisions to pursue their own choices. 
  The women are being protected by the govt  from coercion by employers and 
parents.

The govt also has a compelling interest in keeping health care costs under 
control.   Chip mentions unwanted pregnancy; I mentioned some of the medical 
reasons reproductive health services are needed, which can affect GDP if 
untreated.  And finally, there is the govt's legitimate compelling interest in 
ensuring the health care system does not discriminate on the basis of gender or 
religion and does enable women's choices.   There is no less restrictive means 
of giving each woman her own choice regarding reproductive health than giving 
her a choice.

The abortion decisions to date have all been about what the state can do to 
restrict women's rights.  But those restrictions are not constitutionally 
required. Just because the government is not required to pay for reproductive 
health care does not mean the govt does not have a compelling interest in 
providing it.  This is a new scenario where the govt is on the side of women 
and reproductive rights, which entails new ways of thinking.


Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 17, 2013, at 8:54 AM, James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu wrote:

 Eugene,
 
 No federal or state law required the Amish farmer in Lee to employ workers, 
 but once he made that choice, the Supreme Court used the federal requirements 
 governing employment benefits as the baseline for evaluating externalities 
 (Granting an exemption from social security taxes to an employer operates to 
 impose the employer's religious faith on the employees.). 
 
 Likewise, although no federal or state law requires parents to put their 
 adult children on their insurance, once they make that choice, the argument 
 is that federal requirements governing health benefits should be used as the 
 baseline for evaluating externalities.
 
 Of course, it's certainly possible to argue that the baseline should be set 
 in a different place in parent/adult-child context than in the 
 employer/employee context, or in the health insurance context than the 
 employment context, but I think Chip is right that -- wherever one ultimately 
 comes out -- this is a classic baseline problem. 
 
 - Jim
 
 Jim Oleske
 Lewis  Clark Law School
 SSRN Page: http://ssrn.com/author=357864
 Faculty Page: http://law.lclark.edu/faculty/james_oleske/
 
 On Fri, Aug 16, 2013 at 8:35 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 But wait:  How can you read ACA as setting a baseline that 
 the parents should guarantee their adult children a full bundle of health 
 services?  The ACA doesn’t require parents to do this.  It allows parents to 
 do this, and many parents do indeed do this, but adult children have no 
 right vis-à-vis the parents to get insurance coverage.  The father is free 
 to just tell his children, “Sorry, I won’t get you health coverage”; that’s 
 not “taking” health coverage from them, it’s just choosing not to give 
 health coverage to them.  How is it “taking” for him to offer to give less 
 than complete health coverage to them?
 
  
 
 Eugene
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
 Sent: Friday, August 16, 2013 6:07 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate
 
  
 
 Eugene and I agree that this legislator is not substantially burdened in his 
 religious freedom, because he is under no duty to buy a family policy.  He 
 can avoid the burden without the government penalizing him.
 
 So he is in a different position than employers, like Hobby Lobby, who will 
 have to pay a penalty if they drop their health coverage of employees.
 
  
 
 But the question of imposing costs on his daughters is not as simple as 
 Eugene and others seem to want to make it.  This is a classic baseline 
 problem.  If the baseline for the daughters is no insurance 

Re: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate

2013-08-17 Thread Marci Hamilton
I was not suggesting only the burden on taxpayers, though when it comes to a 
national scheme of healthcare, I think the compelling interest standard is met 
by women's reproductive health.

I was also suggesting the govt has a compelling interest in (1)ensuring women 
have reasonable means of obtaining reproductive health care and (2) supporting 
women's constitutional right to choose by (a) making such health care 
affordable and (b) protecting women from being coerced in such decisions by 
their for-profit employers or parents.   It is not that the woman has a 
constitutional right to the health care coverage per se, but rather the govt 
has a compelling interest in creating the conditions where women will be able 
to exercise their choices over their bodies.

Sherbert and Yoder would have come out differently I believe if the Court had 
found the govt's interest was compelling.  W Sherbert, the interest wasnt 
persuasive because of the other secular exemptions.  I think the Court was just 
wrong in its compelling interest analysis of Yoder, but it is not the
Interest at stake here.


Also-- this thread  takes us back to the RFRAs' built-in constitutional 
defects.  The discussion about how Lee, Sherbert, and Yoder should control RFRA 
interpretation reinforces the argument (whether under the federal or state 
constitutions) that RFRA is nothing more than a constitutional amendment to the 
First Am passed via a simple majority without the obligations imposed by Art V 
(see the footnote in 

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 17, 2013, at 11:57 AM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 That is a different argument, and potentially a plausible one.  The concern 
 isn’t that the parent is trying to force his religion on his daughters, but 
 rather that taxpayers will be left holding the bag.  (I don’t think the 
 “temptation” argument suffices, at least under the strict scrutiny test, but 
 the burden on taxpayers one is different.)
  
 But doesn’t Sherbert suggest that (assuming a substantial burden is present), 
 avoiding any burden – even a relatively slight one – on taxpayers is not 
 necessarily a sufficient government interest?  Likewise, doesn’t Yoder 
 suggest that claims of burden on taxpayers have to be demonstrated to a 
 significant degree, and considered together with any countervailing fiscal 
 benefits that the group’s practices might have?  (The question of the net 
 fiscal cost of unwanted pregnancy, for instance, is complicated; unwanted 
 children cost the government money for prenatal care, and may burden the 
 social welfare system, but they may also grow up to be taxpayers who help 
 fund that social welfare system.)
  
 One merit of a pure Smith regime is that courts don’t have to get in to these 
 questions of deciding what is and what isn’t an externality, and what the 
 empirical effects of particular conduct are.  But if we are to have a RFRA 
 regime, then there has to be a limit to these sorts of 
 externalities-on-taxpayers arguments, it seems to me, at least if Sherbert 
 and Yoder are among the cases being “restored.”
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
 Sent: Saturday, August 17, 2013 5:32 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate
  
 The baseline set by the ACA is NOT a matter of obligation between parents and 
 children.  In that regard, the parent has no obligation to obtain health 
 coverage for his non-minor daughters (although the 12 year old, either now or 
 sometime later but before the age of majority, might need emergency 
 contraception for health reasons, and then the parent might indeed have some 
 obligation to cover or pay for the service).
  
 The baseline is the minimum coverage requirements (essential services, 
 which include pregnancy prevention services) for policies that will satisfy 
 the ACA.  In the Missouri case, allowing the parent to buy a policy that 
 excludes those services puts the insured daughters at increased risk of 
 unwanted pregnancy.  And I'm sure we all agree that unwanted pregnancies 
 impose substantial costs (many of which are not covered by health insurance) 
 on third parties, including but not limited to the women who experience such 
 pregnancies.
  
 Here's another analogy -- a parent wants to buy her non-minor child a car, 
 but the parent makes a religious freedom argument that she should be free to 
 buy a car without seat belts.  (Assume this is a sincere religious claim.)  
 The parent of course has no obligation to buy the car at all, but if we allow 
 that exemption, we allow the parent to put the child at increased risk of 
 serious injury.  Of course, we could frame the objection in terms of the 
 government's compelling interest in reducing the risk of that kind of 

Re: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate

2013-08-15 Thread Marci Hamilton
I assume they were serious and hope they were.  

If you are a woman with unstoppable bleeding as part of your periods, or 
excruciating cramps,
this is medication and treatment that is indeed compelling.  If you cannot go 
to work for 5 days every month because of the severity of your periods, there 
is a compelling interest for the employer, employee, and the govt to make such 
treatments available.  If your religious beliefs preclude you from having a 
family you cannot support, or if you carry a gene that could lead to 
devastating illness and disability in your child, and your religious beliefs 
counsel against pregnancy, there is also a compelling interest In all 3.

Apologies to those who are squeamish about what we are really talking about, 
but the abstract quality of the legal discourse largely carried on by men needs 
a reality check.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 15, 2013, at 11:53 AM, Tracey, Timothy ttra...@avemarialaw.edu wrote:

 I hope that neither you nor Eduardo are serious in your responses.  The 
 government's interest in ensuring basic medical care and lifesaving measures 
 is significantly different than whatever interest the government has in 
 forcing religious organizations to supply coverage of contraception, 
 sterilizations, and abortion.  The government obviously has a compelling 
 interest in the former but certainly not in the latter.  
 
 Timothy J. Tracey
 Associate Professor of Law
 Ave Maria School of Law
 
 On August 15, 2013 at 11:42:29 AM, Len (campquest...@comcast.net) wrote:
 
 Next up, a lawsuit seeking on religious liberty grounds the ability to 
 obtain a health insurance policy from his employer that does not cover 
 vaccinations or other medications, or surgery, but only covers healing 
 prayer.
 
  
 
  
 
  
 
 From: Eduardo Penalver penal...@uchicago.edu
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Thursday, August 15, 2013 11:06:49 AM
 Subject: Re: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate 
 
 Next up, a lawsuit demanding to be paid in currency that can't be used to 
 buy contraception.
 
 Eduardo
 
 
 
 
 
 From: Friedman, Howard M. howard.fried...@utoledo.edu
 Reply-To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
 religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Date: Thu, 15 Aug 2013 13:52:52 +
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate 
 
 In an interesting new lawsuit, a Missouri legislator (suing as an employee 
 of the state) seeks on religious liberty grounds the ability to obtain a 
 health insurance policy from his employer that does not cover contraception, 
 sterilization or abortifacients.  He particularly objects to coverage of 
 these in his policy for his 3 daughters, age 12, 18 and 19.  More on 
 Religion Clause blog-- 
 http://religionclause.blogspot.com/2013/08/new-contraceptive-coverage-challenge.html
 
 Howard Friedman
 ___ To post, send message to 
 Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get 
 password, see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private. Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others. 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are 
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or 
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.
 CONFIDENTIALITY NOTICE: This e-mail transmission is the property of Ave Maria 
 School of Law and may contain confidential or privileged information. It is 
 intended only for the addressee(s) named above. If you receive this e-mail in 
 error, please do not read, copy or disseminate it in any manner.  If you are 
 not the intended recipient, any disclosure, copying, distribution or use of 
 the contents of this information is prohibited and may be unlawful. Please 
 reply to the message immediately by informing the sender that the message was 
 misdirected. After replying, please erase it from your computer system. Your 
 assistance in correcting this error is appreciated.  If you or your employer 
 does not consent to internet e-mail messages of this kind, please notify us 
 immediately. All reasonable precautions have been taken to ensure no viruses 
 are present in this e-mail. Our company cannot accept responsibility for any 
 loss or 

Re: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate

2013-08-15 Thread Marci Hamilton
Well, we are debating the contents of the plan, equality, and fundamental 
fairness.  Those opposed to the mandate are arguing for a health system that 
excludes coverage for women's reproductive health needs, which are often 
compelling.   

Were there no comprehensive plan as backdrop, we would have a different 
discussion.   The question is whether women employees of employers who are 
already not permitted to discriminate in hiring on the basis of religion and 
gender can discriminate in their health care plans on the basis of religion and 
gender.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 15, 2013, at 12:57 PM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:

 If we were debating banning contraception, Marci's argument would work and 
 make perfect sense.  We are, instead, debating government-mandated funding of 
 contraception.
 
 Michael
 
 
 On Thu, Aug 15, 2013 at 10:52 AM, Michael Worley mwor...@byulaw.net wrote:
 As far as I understand the situation, no one legally objects to the health 
 (unrelated to reproduction) use of the pill.
 
 As to those whose religion requires contraception, religious adherents 
 cannot force the government to buy for them wine for sacraments, or even 
 bandaids for cuts, even if they are mandated by religion.  We do not have 
 laws forbidding reproduction by certain couples if there is a risk of 
 disability-- thus, while we approach the issue from different angles, 
 Marci's compelling interest arguments do not strike me as plausible given 
 present jurisprudence.  Unjust from a point of view, sure, but hardly a 
 compelling interest by the government-- certainly a personal compelling 
 interest, but so is three meals a day.
 
 We don't have a constitutional right to food (though government programs 
 thankfully assist with this).  To state someone's personal compelling 
 interest in purchasing a product translates to the state's compelling 
 interest in providing a product is not supported by case law.  Personal 
 interests provide governmental rational basis, of course, but not a 
 governmental compelling interest.
 
 Just my 2¢,
 
 Michael
 
 
 -- 
 Michael Worley
 BYU Law School, Class of 2014
 
 
 On Thu, Aug 15, 2013 at 10:33 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 I assume they were serious and hope they were.  
 
 If you are a woman with unstoppable bleeding as part of your periods, or 
 excruciating cramps,
 this is medication and treatment that is indeed compelling.  If you cannot 
 go to work for 5 days every month because of the severity of your periods, 
 there is a compelling interest for the employer, employee, and the govt to 
 make such treatments available.  If your religious beliefs preclude you 
 from having a family you cannot support, or if you carry a gene that could 
 lead to devastating illness and disability in your child, and your 
 religious beliefs counsel against pregnancy, there is also a compelling 
 interest In all 3.
 
 Apologies to those who are squeamish about what we are really talking 
 about, but the abstract quality of the legal discourse largely carried on 
 by men needs a reality check.
 
 Marci
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 
 
 
 On Aug 15, 2013, at 11:53 AM, Tracey, Timothy ttra...@avemarialaw.edu 
 wrote:
 
 I hope that neither you nor Eduardo are serious in your responses.  The 
 government's interest in ensuring basic medical care and lifesaving 
 measures is significantly different than whatever interest the government 
 has in forcing religious organizations to supply coverage of 
 contraception, sterilizations, and abortion.  The government obviously has 
 a compelling interest in the former but certainly not in the latter.  
 
 Timothy J. Tracey
 Associate Professor of Law
 Ave Maria School of Law
 
 On August 15, 2013 at 11:42:29 AM, Len (campquest...@comcast.net) wrote:
 
 Next up, a lawsuit seeking on religious liberty grounds the ability to 
 obtain a health insurance policy from his employer that does not cover 
 vaccinations or other medications, or surgery, but only covers healing 
 prayer.
 
  
 
  
 
  
 
 From: Eduardo Penalver penal...@uchicago.edu
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Thursday, August 15, 2013 11:06:49 AM
 Subject: Re: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate 
 
 Next up, a lawsuit demanding to be paid in currency that can't be used to 
 buy contraception.
 
 Eduardo
 
 
 
 
 
 From: Friedman, Howard M. howard.fried...@utoledo.edu
 Reply-To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
 religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Date: Thu, 15 Aug 2013 13:52:52 +
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: New Twist On Challenge to ACA Contraceptive Mandate 
 
 In an interesting new lawsuit, a Missouri legislator (suing as an 
 employee

Re: Contraception mandate

2013-08-02 Thread Marci Hamilton
My point yesterday is that the Coalition am the ACLU are not both sides.  Far 
from it

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 2, 2013, at 12:09 PM, James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu wrote:

 Marci - I agree that if one side or the other in the 1997 debate was 
 attempting to make after-the-fact legislative history for RFRA, that history 
 would be of marginal value. But that's not the theory of relevance that Doug 
 offers in his article and that I asked about yesterday. Doug offered the 
 theory that, if both sides in the 1997 had a common understanding about the 
 language common to RLPA and RFRA, that would be relevant to interpreting 
 RFRA. What's wrong with that theory as a general matter? To be sure, on the 
 specific issue of whether for-profit corporations can invoke a defense under 
 the language, the 1997 legislative history indicates that there was not a 
 common understanding. But in cases where there was a common understanding on 
 the record (as appears there might have been concerning individual 
 landlords), I'm not sure why that common understanding wouldn't be a relevant 
 interpretive tool (not the only tool, of course, but one such tool). 
 
 Marc - Prior to reading the ACLU testimony yesterday, I would have been 
 inclined to agree with your suggestion. But the ACLU testimony actually puts 
 the issue in precisely the same terms we seem to be discussing it today (The 
 question of whether a corporate employer or corporate landlord may raise a 
 religious liberty defense is less clear than whether an  individual serving 
 as an employer or landlord may raise that defense.). So I'm inclined to 
 think the 1997 legislative history is relevant to our discussion of cases 
 like Hobby Lobby case precisely because it shows that there was not a common 
 understanding about RFRA protecting for-profit corporations, but there may 
 have been a common understanding about RFRA protecting individuals engaged in 
 commercial activity. 
 
 On Fri, Aug 2, 2013 at 8:17 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 Except that 1997 itself is an irrelevant date.  The relevant dates are 
 1990-93, during the enactment of RFRA.
 
 Marci
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 
 
 
 On Aug 2, 2013, at 10:30 AM, Marc Stern ste...@ajc.org wrote:
 
 IS it possible that the search for legislative history on the question of 
 whether in 1997 Congress thought corporations could benefit from religious 
 liberty provisions is anachronistic .Today, that question is colored by 
 one’ s feelings towards Citizens United; in 1997 ( and especially when 
 arguing to a political body like Congress and in an effort to muster public 
 opinion) the issue was cast in less  abstract terms.
 
 Marc  Stern
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Contraception mandate

2013-08-02 Thread Marci Hamilton
Here are some unassailable facts about RFRAs enactment that make 1997 too late 
to bring for profit corps under RFRAs intended reach 

1.  The vast majority of RFRA's Legis history is not about its actual content 
but rather testimony critical of Smith and the Supreme Court.

2.  The Coalition had an express agreement not to tell members or the press 
what particular laws each hoped to overcome.   They needed to stay mum on their 
individual agendas to remain at the table together.

3.  The abstract constitutional law level of scrutiny formula drove discussion 
away from specifics.

4.  No one remotely hinted that it would be applicable to for-profit 
corporations or that there was any corporation in the US intent on avoiding 
laws through RFRA 

5.  Had the ACLU, Americans United, and People for the American Way and the 
Democrats understood RFRA at the time as the anti-civil rights bill the 10th 
Cir found it to be, it would have gone nowhere.  Inconceivable.  One of its 
virtues for members was anything loved by the left and right had to be good.  

6.  RFRA's feel-good, opaque formula led members not to challenge the lobbyists 
to explain its actual impact.  The few examples involved a minyan and autopsies.

Nothing in this history supports a claim that RFRA was intended to cover 
for-profit corporations.

Marci


Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 2, 2013, at 12:09 PM, James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu wrote:

 Marci - I agree that if one side or the other in the 1997 debate was 
 attempting to make after-the-fact legislative history for RFRA, that history 
 would be of marginal value. But that's not the theory of relevance that Doug 
 offers in his article and that I asked about yesterday. Doug offered the 
 theory that, if both sides in the 1997 had a common understanding about the 
 language common to RLPA and RFRA, that would be relevant to interpreting 
 RFRA. What's wrong with that theory as a general matter? To be sure, on the 
 specific issue of whether for-profit corporations can invoke a defense under 
 the language, the 1997 legislative history indicates that there was not a 
 common understanding. But in cases where there was a common understanding on 
 the record (as appears there might have been concerning individual 
 landlords), I'm not sure why that common understanding wouldn't be a relevant 
 interpretive tool (not the only tool, of course, but one such tool). 
 
 Marc - Prior to reading the ACLU testimony yesterday, I would have been 
 inclined to agree with your suggestion. But the ACLU testimony actually puts 
 the issue in precisely the same terms we seem to be discussing it today (The 
 question of whether a corporate employer or corporate landlord may raise a 
 religious liberty defense is less clear than whether an  individual serving 
 as an employer or landlord may raise that defense.). So I'm inclined to 
 think the 1997 legislative history is relevant to our discussion of cases 
 like Hobby Lobby case precisely because it shows that there was not a common 
 understanding about RFRA protecting for-profit corporations, but there may 
 have been a common understanding about RFRA protecting individuals engaged in 
 commercial activity. 
 
 On Fri, Aug 2, 2013 at 8:17 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 Except that 1997 itself is an irrelevant date.  The relevant dates are 
 1990-93, during the enactment of RFRA.
 
 Marci
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 
 
 
 On Aug 2, 2013, at 10:30 AM, Marc Stern ste...@ajc.org wrote:
 
 IS it possible that the search for legislative history on the question of 
 whether in 1997 Congress thought corporations could benefit from religious 
 liberty provisions is anachronistic .Today, that question is colored by 
 one’ s feelings towards Citizens United; in 1997 ( and especially when 
 arguing to a political body like Congress and in an effort to muster public 
 opinion) the issue was cast in less  abstract terms.
 
 Marc  Stern
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read

Re: Contraception mandate

2013-08-01 Thread Marci Hamilton
As I understand the process, Doug reassured folks on the left that RLPA as 
applied to land use law would not apply to the civil rights laws, particularly 
the fair housing laws.   Not sure how to square that w Doug's current 
statements.

I also find the in pari materia argument disingenuous at best.  When RFRA was 
being enacted, the Coalition had agreed amongst themselves not to disclose 
individual agendas.   And none of the very few examples used to support RFRA 
had anything remotely to do w for-profit companies.   As I say in my Justia.com 
column on the Hobby Lobby decision, had the members been informed that RFRA 
would open doors for Wal-Mart to get around laws, RFRA would have taken a very 
different path.

Despite being deeply involved in RFRA via Boerne, and educated by the many 
organizations that contacted me, I only learned that the CLS was intent on 
overcoming the fair housing laws when a memo re the CA state RFRA was 
inadvertently shared w me.   

Finally, the RCC at first opposed RFRA for fear it would undermine its pro-life 
position, but was reassured RFRA would not affect the abortion issue.  

All of these elements need to be explained to make the argument that RFRA was 
intended to apply to for-profit corporations.

Marci



Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 1, 2013, at 2:35 PM, James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu wrote:

 A few comments and one question upon an initial read of Professor Laycock and 
 Professor Dane's pieces.
 
 First, with respect to Professor Laycock's piece, I think it is difficult to 
 overstate the importance of one of the nation's most prominent and respected 
 advocates for a broad conception of religious liberty penning the following 
 words: 
 
 These Final Rules offer a serious plan to protect religious liberty without 
 depriving women of contraception These Final Rules are utterly 
 inconsistent with the common charge that the Obama Administration is engaged 
 in a 'war on religion.'
 
 Professor Laycock's piece does not spare the political left from similar 
 rebukes -- indeed, groups on the political left come in for more extensive 
 criticism in the Growing Hostility section of the piece than groups on the 
 political right. But Professor Laycock has previously offered strong 
 criticism of rhetoric on the left about religious issues. What is most 
 striking to me about about this piece is that it flatly rejects the central 
 talking point of some of those on the right who have relied most heavily on 
 Professor Laycock's scholarship about religious exemptions.
 
 Like Professor Laycock's piece, Professor Dane's piece finds fault with 
 overheated claims on both sides of the debate, but I'm most interested in the 
 doctrinal analysis Professor Dane offers in place of the heat. In particular, 
 on the issue of exemptions for for-profit institutions, Professor Dane's 
 analysis begins with a line that, while not explicitly discussing the case, 
 seems to track the approach of the Court in United States v. Lee: 
 
 I do think that the for-profit status of some religious objectors might be 
 relevant, but at the back end – in the analysis of compelling interest – 
 rather than the front end determination of substantial burden. 
 
 Professor Dane then notes that arguments can be made for and against making 
 distinctions between small and large businesses in determining the 
 government's interest in denying exemptions (I would only add that the denial 
 of an exemption to a very small employer in Lee may be relevant to further 
 exploration of these arguments). Professor Dane concludes his analysis by 
 stating that a vital proposition in the conception of religious liberty is 
 that believers have at least a presumptive right to live out the commitments 
 of their faith across the whole range of human activity, including the world 
 of business and commerce.
 
 It is this last point that I think would benefit most from being expanded to 
 account for the doctrinal significance of Lee, where the Court identified a 
 competing presumption that comes into play in for-profit cases due to impact 
 on third parties:
 
 When followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as a 
 matter of choice, the limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter of 
 conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on the statutory schemes 
 which are binding on others in that activity. Granting an exemption from 
 social security taxes to an employer operates to impose the employer's 
 religious faith on the employees. 
 
 I've previously criticized the Tenth Circuit majority in Hobby Lobby for 
 failing to address this language from Lee. Since then, the Third Circuit 
 majority in Conestoga Wood -- while coming to the opposite conclusion of the 
 Tenth Circuit -- has likewise neglected to engage the relevant language from 
 Lee (the dissents in both cases do at least 

Re: Contraception mandate

2013-08-01 Thread Marci Hamilton
I think it is critically important to remember that RLPA was rejected 
categorically by the members as much too broad.  The history w respect to 
anything other than land use and prisons are the only histories that have any 
reliable content to them for future interpretation.

Post-enactment legislative history is the least reliable and should never be 
accepted as evidence of legislative purpose by courts.   I would have thought 
that was where anyone analyzing RFRA and RLPA would start. 

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 1, 2013, at 5:39 PM, James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu wrote:

 Thanks for the reminder that Thomas, Swanner, and other similar housing cases 
 were part of the RLPA discussion. I see from a quick look at the RLPA House 
 Report that they were explicitly discussed there, and there is a footnote in 
 the same general discussion rejecting the argument that business 
 corporations would be categorically excluded from RPLA protection.
 
 But to be clear, my question isn't whether supporters of RLPA thought 
 for-profits would be categorically excluded from protection. It's clear they 
 didn't think that. My question is whether, when fears were raised of 
 commercial businesses being shielded by RLPA from civil rights laws, 
 supporters of RLPA argued that those defenses could be balanced and limited 
 by the courts consistent with Lee and its solicitude for the competing rights 
 of employees in the commercial context. 
 
 It sounds like the answer is probably no. The House report does not address 
 that issue and instead focuses on the issue of whether antidiscrimination 
 qualifies as a compelling interest, with the report's opinion seeming to be 
 yes for race, usually yes for sex, and TBD for everything else (citing 
 specifically the split in the lower courts over application of the compelling 
 interest test in the marital status cases like Thomas and Swanner, but not 
 expressing an opinion as to how those cases should turn out).
 
 On Thu, Aug 1, 2013 at 12:32 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu 
 wrote:
 Sorry. The first sentence below was supposed to say “there were cases that 
 the religious objectors deserved to win.”
 
  
 
 Douglas Laycock
 
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 
 University of Virginia Law School
 
 580 Massie Road
 
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
 
  434-243-8546
 
  
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
 Sent: Thursday, August 01, 2013 3:24 PM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: RE: Contraception mandate
 
  
 
 Supporters of RLPA said that civil rights claimants would win most of the 
 cases on compelling interest grounds, but that civil rights had come to be a 
 very broad  category, and there the religious objectors deserved to win. 
 They said the RLPA standard should be uniformly applied to all cases, as 
 with the RFRA standard.
 
  
 
 Supporters did not say that for-profit businesses would not have a RLPA 
 defense. This whole issue with respect to RLPA was triggered by a series of 
 cases about for-profit landlords and unmarried opposite-sex couples, 
 especially Thomas v. Anchorage Human Rights Commission in the Ninth Circuit. 
 Thomas was later vacated on other grounds, but the opinion is still on 
 Westlaw.
 
  
 
 If these articles and Professor Oleske’s post trigger a substantial 
 discussion, I regret that I will not be much of a participant. I’m on 
 deadline and behind the curve with another major project.
 
  
 
 Douglas Laycock
 
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 
 University of Virginia Law School
 
 580 Massie Road
 
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
 
  434-243-8546
 
  
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of James Oleske
 Sent: Thursday, August 01, 2013 2:36 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Contraception mandate
 
 [snip]
  
 One final question for Professor Laycock: In footnote 67 of your piece, you 
 point to the legislative history of RLPA as evidence that RFRA covers 
 for-profits, writing:
 Both sides in that debate believed that if enacted, RLPA would protect 
 for-profit businesses from civil rights claims that substantially burdened 
 the owner’s free exercise of religion. RLPA was in pari materia with RFRA, 
 and its operative language was identical to the language of RFRA. The 
 supporters of a civil-rights exception to RLPA were seeking an amendment 
 that they knew they needed, and that had not been part of RFRA.
 
 
 Did none of the supporters of RLPA try to reassure the civil rights 
 community that they did not need an exception because the Supreme Court's 
 pre-Smith jurisprudence that was being restored had already imposed 
 limitations on exemptions in the commercial arena? I haven't studied the 
 legislative 

Re: Contraception mandate

2013-08-01 Thread Marci Hamilton
There is no all in the legislative process.   There are only competing 
interests and conflicting sides. I am not going to belabor this for this 
exchange, but as someone who was as intimately involved in this as Doug, but on 
the opposite side, his description encompasses some but not all of what was 
happening.  He can certainly speak for those who started altogether on his side 
even if they split asunder later.   That would be the Coalition and the civil 
rights groups.

He cannot speak authoritatively for those who were on the other side, 
particularly when they ultimately prevailed.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Aug 1, 2013, at 9:48 PM, Marc Stern ste...@ajc.org wrote:

 An additional fact: the civil rights issue came into public view after the 
 ACLU wrote a letter to Congress-whether to the whole house or the judiciary 
 committee I don't recall- spelling out in detail the cases in which civil 
 liberties and religious liberty claims clashed. It was that letter that 
 sparked the nadler amendment and the breakup of the coalition that had 
 earlier  supported RFRA.
 Marc
 
 - Original Message -
 From: Douglas Laycock [mailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu]
 Sent: Thursday, August 01, 2013 09:30 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu; 
 hamilto...@aol.com hamilto...@aol.com
 Subject: Re: Contraception mandate
 
 RLUIPA does not apply to fair housing laws because it applies only to land 
 use regulation and institutionalized persons, and it exprssly defines land 
 use regulation as zoning and landmarking. Period. No mystery to explain. 
 
 My recollection is that that definition was added late in the process. I have 
 not checked that. 
 
 Before that amendment, neither I nor any other supporter assured opponents 
 that RLPA would not apply to fair housing laws. The whole fight was fueled by 
 fair housing laws.
 
 There were negotiations about exempting large landlords and protecting small 
 landlords. But these negotiations quickly broke down because the two sides 
 were too far apart on what the size limit should be.
 
 RLPA had other opponents, but the civil rights issue is what killed it. It is 
 not true that it was doomed by its overbreadth. It was not even obvious at 
 the time that it was doomed by the civil rights fight.
 
 The Nadler Amendment to exclude civil rights claims was defeated in the House 
 234-190. The unamended bill then passed the House 306-118. That lopsided yes 
 vote hardly suggests a doomed bill. Skeptics can find these votes at 145 
 Cong. Rec. H5607-08. The bill then died in the Senate without a vote. 
 
 Both sides in the debate over the Nadler Amendment, and in the earlier 
 debates in committee, were fighting about a live issue. No one thought they 
 were making post-enactment legislative history for RFRA. They were all acting 
 on a common understanding about what the language copied from RFRA meant.
 
 On Thu, 1 Aug 2013 20:20:28 -0400 (EDT)
 hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 
 I was not particularly interested in solely Doug's statements at the time, 
 but rather his reasoning in his new piece.   Marc and now Eugene have 
 personalized this.
 There is no need for that.
 
 
 Here is a fact:  Many following enactment of RLUIPA have stated 
 unequivocally that the land use provisions were not intended to apply to the 
 fair housing (i.e., civil rights) laws.  
 Since the only legis history on RLUIPA was RLPA, that assumption (that the 
 civil rights laws were beyond the new statute) had to come from the RLPA 
 proceedings.   
 What is the missing piece that explains how Doug and Marc have explained the 
 history?
 
 
 
 
 Marci
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003 
 (212) 790-0215 
 http://sol-reform.com
 
 
 
 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Thu, Aug 1, 2013 7:56 pm
 Subject: RE: Contraception mandate
 
 
 
   Indeed, Marci didn’t say Doug was “lying,” but when one says 
 of a first-hand witness that the “history, as I knew it, was distinctive 
 from his account,” and “Not sure how to square [Doug’s past reassurances] w 
 Doug's current statements,” the implicit accusation seems to me to be pretty 
 clear.
 
 But I should think that this could be clearly resolved:  If Marci wants to 
 produce some quotes from Doug that are at variance with his current 
 statements, that would be very interesting.  But until any such quotes are 
 produced, I’m inclined to trust Doug.
 
 And I agree that we should discuss facts on the listserv without stooping to 
 namecalling.
 
 Eugene
 
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
 

Re: RLUIPA and hair length in prison

2013-07-27 Thread Marci Hamilton
Michael--  how do you read Cutter's several statements that require deference 
to prison officials on safety?

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Jul 27, 2013, at 12:36 PM, Michael Masinter masin...@nova.edu wrote:

 The eleventh circuit's restatement of RLUIPA's compelling interest/narrowly 
 tailored standard based on a snippet of legislative history and some language 
 from Cutter v. Wilkinson respecting due deference would make George Orwell 
 proud:
 
 Although the RLUIPA protects, to a substantial degree, the religious 
 observances of institutionalized persons, it does not give courts carte 
 blanche to second-guess the reasoned judgments of prison officials. Indeed, 
 while Congress enacted the RLUIPA to address the many “frivolous or 
 arbitrary” barriers impeding institutionalized persons' religious exercise, 
 it nevertheless anticipated that courts entertaining RLUIPA challenges “would 
 accord ‘due deference to the experience and expertise of prison and jail 
 administrators.’ ” Cutter v. Wilkinson, 544 U.S. 709, 716–17 (2005) ( quoting 
 146 Cong. Rec. 16698, 16699 (2000) (joint statement of Sens. Hatch and 
 Kennedy on the RLUIPA)). The Supreme Court has cautioned that “[w]e do not 
 read RLUIPA to elevate accommodation of religious observances over an 
 institution's need to maintain order and safety,” and “an accommodation must 
 be measured so that it does not override other significant interests.” Id. at 
 722. The Court further instructed:
 
 We have no cause to believe that RLUIPA would not be applied in an 
 appropriately balanced way, with particular sensitivity to security concerns. 
 While the Act adopts a “compelling governmental interest” standard, context 
 matters in the application of that standard. Lawmakers supporting RLUIPA were 
 mindful of the urgency of discipline, order, safety, and security in penal 
 institutions. They anticipated that courts would apply the Act's standard 
 with due deference to the experience and expertise of prison and jail 
 administrators in establishing necessary regulations and procedures to 
 maintain good order, security and discipline, consistent with consideration 
 of costs and limited resources.
 
 Id. at 722–23 (internal quotation marks and citations omitted). This 
 deference is not, however, unlimited, and “policies grounded on mere 
 speculation, exaggerated fears, or post-hoc rationalizations will not suffice 
 to meet the act's requirements.” Rich v. Secretary, Florida Dep't of 
 Corrections, 716 F.3d 525, 533 (11th Cir.2013) (internal quotation marks 
 omitted).
 
 It would be hard to write a better statement of only slightly beefed up 
 rational basis review whenever discipline is in play.  As long as the 
 judgment of an administrator cannot be proven to be frivolous or arbitrary 
 or based on mere speculation, exaggerated fears, or post-hoc 
 rationalizations it will survive statutorily mandated strict scrutiny 
 review.  Perhaps the unstated premise that incarcerated felons are subhuman 
 will cabin the dilution of strict scrutiny, but perhaps not; in the national 
 security state, it's only a short leap from prison safety to public safety.
 
 
 Michael R. Masinter  3305 College Avenue
 Professor of Law Fort Lauderdale, FL 33314
 Nova Southeastern University 954.262.6151 (voice)
 masin...@nova.edu954.262.3835 (fax)
 
 
 
 Quoting Joel Sogol jlsa...@wwisp.com:
 
 
 
 http://j.st/HMg?utm_source=Justia+Lawutm_campaign=282bac825a-summary_newsl
 etters_jurisdictionsutm_medium=emailutm_term=0_92aabbfa32-282bac825a-40593
 7966 Knight, et al. v. Thompson, et al.
 
 
 Docket: 12-11926
 
 Opinion Date: July 26, 2013
 
 
 Judge: Schlesinger
 
 
 Areas of Law: Civil Rights, Constitutional Law, Criminal Law, Government 
 Administrative Law
 
 Plaintiffs, male inmates, filed suit under the Religious Land Use and
 Institutionalized Persons Act of 2000 (RLUIPA), 42 U.S.C. 2000cc et seq.,
 challenging an ADOC policy that forbids them from wearing their hair unshorn
 in accordance with the dictates of their Native American religion. The
 United States intervened on plaintiffs' behalf. The court affirmed the
 district court's judgment in favor of the ADOC because the ADOC carried its
 burden of demonstrating that its hair-length policy was the least restrict
 means of furthering its compelling governmental interests of prevention of
 contraband, facilitation of inmate identification, maintenance of good
 hygiene and health, and facilitation of prison discipline through
 uniformity.
 
 
 http://j.st/HMg
 http://j.st/HMg?utm_source=Justia+Lawutm_campaign=282bac825a-summary_newsl
 etters_jurisdictionsutm_medium=emailutm_term=0_92aabbfa32-282bac825a-40593
 7966
 
 
 http://j.st/HMg?utm_source=Justia+Lawutm_campaign=282bac825a-summary_newsl
 

Re: Marriage -- the Alito dissent

2013-06-29 Thread Marci Hamilton
Of course history (people) can make sectarian views nonsectarian and vice 
versa.   A religious belief under the Constitution is what the religious 
believer says it is right now,
not what history said it was or should be.   Alito is following Vatican 
(religious) dogma.   In current US society, the push against gay marriage is 
based on religious believers who believe it is sinful for same sex couples to 
marry.  That is the discourse regardless of the source of their current beliefs.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
Yeshiva University
@Marci_Hamilton 



On Jun 29, 2013, at 4:18 PM, Richard Dougherty dou...@udallas.edu wrote:

 I understand why it can seem that way, but history can't make a nonsectarian 
 view sectarian. The claim that the majority -- but not all -- of the 
 arguments one hears are sectarian is per se evidence that it is not 
 sectarian.  There is a reason why the arguments track, but are not derived 
 from, Vatican teaching, and that is that the Vatican teaching is largely 
 drawn from philosophical principles, not theological ones. The natural law is 
 the common source.
 
 Richard Dougherty
 
 On Sat, Jun 29, 2013 at 11:25 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilton.ma...@gmail.com 
 wrote:
 At this stage in history, Alito's view is in fact decisively sectarian.  The 
 vast majority of opposition is theological w theological sources. That is 
 the political reality.  And his sources and arguments are derived directly 
 from Vatican doctrine.  
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo Law School
 Yeshiva University
 @Marci_Hamilton 
 
 
 
 On Jun 29, 2013, at 12:10 PM, Richard Dougherty dou...@udallas.edu wrote:
 
  
 Well, I don't know what Alito may say about Posner's characterization, but 
 I'm guessing he would not embrace the view he forwarded as emotional and 
 sectarian, rather than rational. Indeed, I'm finding it hard to imagine 
 that anyone would characterize their own view that way. (Well, maybe 
 Westboro Baptist, but Alito is not of that persuasion, I would imagine.)  
 While it may be true that the view he suggests is close to the Vatican's 
 view (which Posner derisively calls its sex doctrine), it is also the 
 dominant view of marriage over the past thousands of years.  There's 
 nothing necessarily sectarian about it, and it's certainly not 
 non-rational.  It might not be persuasive to all, or to many, but it would 
 be an injustice to dismiss it so cavalierly.
 Richard Dougherty
 On Sat, Jun 29, 2013 at 10:19 AM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 
 wrote:
 As a couple of you have pointed out to me, Judge Posner has addressed the 
 Alito dissent; in Slate 
 (http://www.slate.com/articles/news_and_politics/the_breakfast_table/features/2013/supreme_court_2013/supreme_court_and_doma_justice_alito_s_defense_is_all_emotion.html),
  he writes:
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Marci Hamilton wants to share new pictures with you :)

2012-08-25 Thread Marci Hamilton
Title: An Email from Zoosk




	
	


	
		
			

			
		
		
			

	

	
		
			Marci Hamilton has added you as a friend on Zoosk.
		
	
	
	
		
				
		
		
			Is Marci Hamilton your friend?
			
			
			Yes
			No
			
		
		
	

			
		
		



		
		This message was sent by a Zoosk user who entered your email address.		If you'd prefer not to receive emails when other people send you emails through Zoosk, click here	
		
		You have received this message at the email address: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
	
		
		Copyright  2007-2012 Zoosk, 989 Market St, San Francisco, CA 94103 USA.	
		
		Privacy Policy
	

	

	


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: What religion is an 8-day-old?

2012-07-10 Thread Marci Hamilton
As long as it is a case-by-case analysis, I am on board.  But I think the 
presumption of religion as good is folly for the vulnerable.

Marci

On Jul 10, 2012, at 10:10 AM, Andrew M M Koppelman 
akoppel...@law.northwestern.edu wrote:

 I said that the value of religion sometimes outweighs other considerations.  
 I didn't say it always does so.  Marci has compiled some mighty persuasive 
 horror stories showing that the balance is often struck with excessive 
 deference to religion.  But that doesn't answer the circumcision question.  
 In that context, it's doubtful whether the child is harmed at all, and the 
 religious values on the other side are substantial.  
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
 on behalf of hamilto...@aol.com [hamilto...@aol.com]
 Sent: Monday, July 09, 2012 10:36 AM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Re: What religion is an 8-day-old?
 
 With all due respect to Andrew, but in complete seriousness, religion is 
 often not a good thing even under the law, and often a deadly and permanently
 disfiguring or disabling thing for children, the disabled, and emotionally 
 disabled adults.  A focus on religion as a good thing rather
 than a focus on the best interest of the child is precisely what has led to 
 the deep suffering of far too many children.   I find it
 astonishing that anyone would still be  talking in this era in these 
 generalities to protect religion when it is harming children.
 
 Now, if one wants to argue that religion is good when it is not harming the 
 vulnerable, that is a different topic, but it has nothing
 to do with the circumcision debate that has gone on on this thread, which has 
 revolved basically around a fact question: is it
 harmful, even though a fair amount of theory has surrounded this fact 
 discussion.
 
 Having said that, I also agree that much of this discussion has had an unreal 
 quality to it, but mainly because of my original
 point that these issues are best described and analyzed under a best interest 
 of the child analysis, case-by-case, and simply
 not amenable to these theoretical generalities.  And under our pre-existing 
 criminal and tort laws.  Those are the laws that have
 held religious organizations and leaders (e.g., Msgr. Lynn) to account for 
 the cover up of serial child predators to protect religious
 identity, wealth, and power.  These civil laws are the main reason we have 
 any justice in this field.  This law has not treated religion
 as valuable or good but rather as a no-good defense to harm.  (Except in 
 a diminishing number of states.)   And it is no
 argument in response that no religious groups believe in child sex abuse.  
 That is not true, e.g., Tony Alamo (yes, it's a cult, still a religion);
 FLDS, and the many religious organizations who have theological tenets 
 requiring the cover up of abuse which then multiplies the
 number of victims by enabling predators.
 
 There are some legal areans where religion has been treated as good, e.g., 
 NY state law on land use.  But it is dangerous
 to legal analysis to take them at face value.  As religious land use has 
 changed and expanded, however, this presumption has become
 increasingly difficult to defend.
 
 Marci
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003
 (212) 790-0215
 hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com
 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Andrew M M Koppelman akoppel...@law.northwestern.edu
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Mon, Jul 9, 2012 10:42 am
 Subject: RE: What religion is an 8-day-old?
 
 This discussion is fascinating, but it has a curiously unreal quality, 
 because everyone seems to want, in typically lawyerly fashion, to subsume 
 under some broad and generally applicable principle a practice that is in 
 fact unique and exceedingly unlikely to generate analogous cases.  This is 
 another case where I think it's helpful to recognize that American law treats 
 religion as valuable, in a way that sometimes outweighs other considerations. 
  I elaborate in my forthcoming book:  
 http://www.hup.harvard.edu/catalog.php?isbn=9780674066465.  If religion is a 
 good thing, and two of the major religions of America practice circumcision, 
 then we have a strong reason not to interfere.  This, I think, is what is 
 actually going on, not the application of some Wechslerian neutral principle 
 about parental rights or individual religious rights or whatever.  This 
 discussion has made clear that neither of those principles fits the practice 
 in question very well.
 
 
 
 From: 
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
  on behalf of Volokh, Eugene 

Re: Parental rights and physical conduct

2012-07-06 Thread Marci Hamilton
But we do know-- the best interests of the child is based on a totality of the 
circumstances.  A one-time sip of beer does not harm a child   A full beer 
would.  Most of these cases are just common sense.  Your example is a straw man

Marci

On Jul 5, 2012, at 10:44 PM, Eric Rassbach erassb...@becketfund.org wrote:

 
 My Dad gave me a sip of Dome foam at an Astros game when I was fairly 
 young, which had the (almost certainly intended) effect of putting me off of 
 beer until later than many of my peers. The sad part is that we will never 
 know whether that act was in the best interests of the child or whether Dad 
 should've been locked up.
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
 On Behalf Of Ira Lupu [icl...@law.gwu.edu]
 Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 9:26 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Parental rights and physical conduct
 
 I am wondering if Marci thinks Troxel v. Granville (unconstitutional for 
 legislature to provide for grandparent visitation rights over objection of 
 custodial parent) is correctly decided, or consistent with her views. Her 
 assertion that Children are increasingly being treated as independent 
 persons whose interests must be examined separately is awfully vague -- 16 
 year olds involved in custody fights?  What's the context to which you are 
 referring?
 
 Now I have to go watch the Nationals and drink some beer with my younger son 
 -- he'll be 22 in a few weeks.  I have a 13 year old grandson coming to visit 
 tomorrow, and I'll have to think twice about offering him a bottle.
 
 On Thu, Jul 5, 2012 at 8:19 PM, Marci Hamilton 
 hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 I would disagree with Chip that the concept of best interest of the child 
 continues to afford a presumption that parents act in the best interest of 
 the child.  Children are increasingly being treated as independent persons 
 whose interests must be examined separately.
 
 I do agree w Chip, though, that religious reasons should never be adequate as 
 reasons to water down the best interest inquiry or create a defense in a case 
 involving harm to a child.
 
 Marci
 
 On Jul 5, 2012, at 3:34 PM, Ira Lupu 
 icl...@law.gwu.edumailto:icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
 
 Our ordinary, wide-spread, and long-standing presumption is that 
 parents/guardians act in the best interests of their minor children.  The 
 state may intervene -- overcome that presumption -- when parents/guardians 
 inflict significant harm on their children.  Of course, we can all argue 
 about what constitutes such harm (e.g., Eric' s example of Amish families 
 keeping their children on the farm, or Alan's example of a parent providing 
 a child with small amounts of alcohol).  I am not trying to settle what 
 constitutes harm sufficient to justify intervention.  I am trying to reject 
 the idea that religion will EVER appropriately affect that judgment by the 
 state.  There is no room for play in the joints on these questions, because 
 the interests of third parties are involved.  If the state singles out 
 religiously motivated conduct for an exemption from a prohibition on what is 
 otherwise abusive or neglectful, that violates the Establishment Clause.  And 
 if If the state singles out religiously motivated conduct for punishment in 
 cases where the same conduct with secular motivation is not considered 
 abusive or neglectful, that violates the Free Exercise Clause.   So, Alan, 
 the answer is yes, both parents who provide alcohol to their children should 
 have to operate under the same rules -- if a Jewish parent's Seder practices 
 are OK (and I'm sure that the vast majority of such parents don't abusively 
 or neglectfully ply their minor children with alcohol), then likewise for the 
 parent who provides the same amount of alcohol, over the same number of 
 hours, with the same frequency on the calendar (once a year).   Doing this at 
 every Sabbath, or every Sunday during NFL season, might be abuse or neglect, 
 but the standard for state intervention would be the same for both parents.
 
 On Thu, Jul 5, 2012 at 2:59 PM, Marci Hamilton 
 hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 I would like some clarification from those relying on purported parental 
 rights. The use of the term parental right  is freighted w social and 
 cultural value but very little legal value.
 
 Pierce v Society of Sisters is balanced by Prince.  So the use of right in 
 this context is a dead end in my view.
 
 The best interest of the child is not in the context of parental rights as 
 much as it is intended to treat the child as a separate person who deserves 
 protection and respect even in opposition to a parent's demands or needs.
 
 Marci
 
 On Jul 5, 2012, at 12:42 PM, Eric Rassbach 
 erassb...@becketfund.orgmailto:erassb...@becketfund.org wrote:
 
 
 Eugene --
 
 I don't think this makes sense because

Re: Parental rights and physical conduct

2012-07-05 Thread Marci Hamilton
I would disagree with Chip that the concept of best interest of the child 
continues to afford a presumption that parents act in the best interest of the 
child.  Children are increasingly being treated as independent persons whose 
interests must be examined separately. 

I do agree w Chip, though, that religious reasons should never be adequate as 
reasons to water down the best interest inquiry or create a defense in a case 
involving harm to a child.

Marci

On Jul 5, 2012, at 3:34 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

 Our ordinary, wide-spread, and long-standing presumption is that 
 parents/guardians act in the best interests of their minor children.  The 
 state may intervene -- overcome that presumption -- when parents/guardians 
 inflict significant harm on their children.  Of course, we can all argue 
 about what constitutes such harm (e.g., Eric' s example of Amish families 
 keeping their children on the farm, or Alan's example of a parent providing 
 a child with small amounts of alcohol).  I am not trying to settle what 
 constitutes harm sufficient to justify intervention.  I am trying to reject 
 the idea that religion will EVER appropriately affect that judgment by the 
 state.  There is no room for play in the joints on these questions, because 
 the interests of third parties are involved.  If the state singles out 
 religiously motivated conduct for an exemption from a prohibition on what is 
 otherwise abusive or neglectful, that violates the Establishment Clause.  And 
 if If the state singles out religiously motivated conduct for punishment in 
 cases where the same conduct with secular motivation is not considered 
 abusive or neglectful, that violates the Free Exercise Clause.   So, Alan, 
 the answer is yes, both parents who provide alcohol to their children should 
 have to operate under the same rules -- if a Jewish parent's Seder practices 
 are OK (and I'm sure that the vast majority of such parents don't abusively 
 or neglectfully ply their minor children with alcohol), then likewise for the 
 parent who provides the same amount of alcohol, over the same number of 
 hours, with the same frequency on the calendar (once a year).   Doing this at 
 every Sabbath, or every Sunday during NFL season, might be abuse or neglect, 
 but the standard for state intervention would be the same for both parents.   
 
 On Thu, Jul 5, 2012 at 2:59 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 I would like some clarification from those relying on purported parental 
 rights. The use of the term parental right  is freighted w social and 
 cultural value but very little legal value.
 
 Pierce v Society of Sisters is balanced by Prince.  So the use of right in 
 this context is a dead end in my view.
 
 The best interest of the child is not in the context of parental rights as 
 much as it is intended to treat the child as a separate person who deserves 
 protection and respect even in opposition to a parent's demands or needs.
 
 Marci
 
 On Jul 5, 2012, at 12:42 PM, Eric Rassbach erassb...@becketfund.org wrote:
 
 
  Eugene --
 
  I don't think this makes sense because it posits an impossible universe of 
  zero-risk parenting. It is far riskier to drive your child on the freeway 
  (not to mention take him/her skiing, or letting him/her play soccer, or 
  play football (esp. in Texas)) than it is to baptize him/her. All those 
  risks are well within the set of risks that parents take in the normal 
  course of parenting. Indeed, for the state to interfere with the ability of 
  parents to expose children to those risks would be a gross interference 
  with parental rights. And I imagine that the danger to infants from either 
  circumcision or full immersion baptism is far lower than driving them 
  around town, though I claim no actuarial expertise on the matter.
 
  Eric
 
  
  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
  [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene 
  [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
  Sent: Thursday, July 05, 2012 12:31 PM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Parental rights and physical conduct
 
 I appreciate Howard’s point, but the question is:  Why 
  should some children who by definition do not share a religious belief 
  drown – or otherwise be injured – for the sake of the beliefs of the adults 
  who do have that belief (and even for the sake of those children who, later 
  in life, will wish that they had been so baptized)?  I have great sympathy 
  for people’s rights to risk their own lives (in the baptism example) or 
  alter their own bodies (in the circumcision example) for the sake of their 
  religious beliefs, or for that matter for the sake of their secular 
  beliefs.  But why does it follow that they should have the right to impose 
  such risks on others, even others to whom they are genetically linked?
 
 Eugene
 
  From: religionlaw-boun

Re: Parental rights and physical conduct

2012-07-05 Thread Marci Hamilton
I do think Troxel and Yoder particularly were wrongly decided.  The more 
egregious was Yoder, which was based on a romantic view of a religious 
community that does not operate in the best interest of the child in far too 
many situations

On the increasing rights of children, I am talking about the sexual abuse 
context generally, but specifically the increasing number of states that now 
reject First Am defenses in the context and the states rolling back the 
indefensible clergy exceptions to child sex abuse reporting.  

I would add to that the slowdown in medical neglect exemptions and the death of 
the ND RFRA by child
Advocates arguing for the welfare of children to defeat a RFRA. 

Finally, the turn around in the criminal justice system in favor of child
victims against priests/bishops (Philly Msgr. Lynn conviction + rejection of 
request for house arrest) and today's acquittal of the victim accused of 
assaulting the priest who sexually assaulted him.

Plus the defensive posture of Brooklyn DA Hynes who cooperated in the rabbis' 
coverup of abuse in the Hasidim community.

The Zeitgeist has shifted decisively in favor of children and against religious 
actors who harm children.   

Marci 

On Jul 5, 2012, at 9:26 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

 I am wondering if Marci thinks Troxel v. Granville (unconstitutional for 
 legislature to provide for grandparent visitation rights over objection of 
 custodial parent) is correctly decided, or consistent with her views. Her 
 assertion that Children are increasingly being treated as independent 
 persons whose interests must be examined separately is awfully vague -- 16 
 year olds involved in custody fights?  What's the context to which you are 
 referring?
 
 Now I have to go watch the Nationals and drink some beer with my younger son 
 -- he'll be 22 in a few weeks.  I have a 13 year old grandson coming to visit 
 tomorrow, and I'll have to think twice about offering him a bottle.
 
 On Thu, Jul 5, 2012 at 8:19 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 I would disagree with Chip that the concept of best interest of the child 
 continues to afford a presumption that parents act in the best interest of 
 the child.  Children are increasingly being treated as independent persons 
 whose interests must be examined separately. 
 
 I do agree w Chip, though, that religious reasons should never be adequate as 
 reasons to water down the best interest inquiry or create a defense in a case 
 involving harm to a child.
 
 Marci
 
 On Jul 5, 2012, at 3:34 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
 
 Our ordinary, wide-spread, and long-standing presumption is that 
 parents/guardians act in the best interests of their minor children.  The 
 state may intervene -- overcome that presumption -- when parents/guardians 
 inflict significant harm on their children.  Of course, we can all argue 
 about what constitutes such harm (e.g., Eric' s example of Amish families 
 keeping their children on the farm, or Alan's example of a parent 
 providing a child with small amounts of alcohol).  I am not trying to settle 
 what constitutes harm sufficient to justify intervention.  I am trying to 
 reject the idea that religion will EVER appropriately affect that judgment 
 by the state.  There is no room for play in the joints on these questions, 
 because the interests of third parties are involved.  If the state singles 
 out religiously motivated conduct for an exemption from a prohibition on 
 what is otherwise abusive or neglectful, that violates the Establishment 
 Clause.  And if If the state singles out religiously motivated conduct for 
 punishment in cases where the same conduct with secular motivation is not 
 considered abusive or neglectful, that violates the Free Exercise Clause.   
 So, Alan, the answer is yes, both parents who provide alcohol to their 
 children should have to operate under the same rules -- if a Jewish parent's 
 Seder practices are OK (and I'm sure that the vast majority of such parents 
 don't abusively or neglectfully ply their minor children with alcohol), then 
 likewise for the parent who provides the same amount of alcohol, over the 
 same number of hours, with the same frequency on the calendar (once a year). 
   Doing this at every Sabbath, or every Sunday during NFL season, might be 
 abuse or neglect, but the standard for state intervention would be the same 
 for both parents.   
 
 On Thu, Jul 5, 2012 at 2:59 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 I would like some clarification from those relying on purported parental 
 rights. The use of the term parental right  is freighted w social and 
 cultural value but very little legal value.
 
 Pierce v Society of Sisters is balanced by Prince.  So the use of right in 
 this context is a dead end in my view.
 
 The best interest of the child is not in the context of parental rights as 
 much as it is intended to treat the child as a separate person who deserves

Re: Providing public school credits for release-time religious classes

2012-06-30 Thread Marci Hamilton
Marty is undoubtedly correct under current doctrine.  The release time program 
exists I assume to avoid Establishment Cl problems.  To now argue entanglement 
is a problem is a constitutional sleight of hand to avoid a violation.   

The entanglement argument is particularly weak given the description of the 
program

I also think the entanglement argument is specious given that public and 
private schools set requirements and criteria to accept credit from other 
schools all the time.  A school does not need to nor does it normally blindly 
accept courses and/or credits from other schools, private or public.

I am at a loss to understand how this decision is salutary from an academic 
perspective.  Sounds to me like it is potentially watering down the 3Rs

Marci





On Jun 30, 2012, at 11:11 AM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:

 I should add that, wholly apart from whether the particular Spartanburg Bible 
 School class was in any way, as Rick suggests, of some secular educational 
 value (which was, I repeat, not the basis for the court's holding), the South 
 Carolina statute at issue expressly provides that [a] school district board 
 of trustees may award high school students no more than two elective Carnegie 
 units for the completion of released time classes in religious instruction.
 
 That is to say, the credits are specifically and unequivocally being awarded 
 for the religious instruction as such.
 
 On Sat, Jun 30, 2012 at 10:47 AM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 
 wrote:
 Rick,
 
 The statute says that the school district must use secular criteria to 
 determine whether the release time education qualifies for credits, but those 
 criteria have nothing to do with fulfillment of any of the secular 
 educational objectives of the school (they include the number of hours of 
 instruction; a syllabus that reflects course requirements; a method of 
 assessment used by the religious school teachers; and whether the teachers 
 are certified).  The School District here, for admirable nonentanglement 
 reasons, entered into an arrangement with Oakbrook Preparatory School, an 
 accredited private Christian school, by which Spartanburg Bible School could 
 submit its grades through Oakbrook to Spartanburg High School. Under the 
 arrangement, Oakbrook agreed to review and monitor Spar- tanburg Bible 
 School’s curriculum, its teacher qualifications, and educational objectives, 
 and to award course credit and grades given by the Bible School before 
 transferring them to Spartanburg High School. In carrying out the 
 arrangement, Oakbrook reviewed syllabi, spoke with instructors, suggested 
 minor curricular adjustments, and satisfied itself that the Spar- tanburg 
 Bible School course was academically rigorous.
 
 To my mind, this delegation raises a serious Larkin problem.  But that aside, 
 the fact that the accredited school is an intermediary that transfers the 
 grades based on an assessment that the religious course was academically 
 rigorous does not cure the problem, which is that this education is designed 
 to be religious in nature, and not to advance any of the secular objectives 
 of the public schools.
 
 You quote with apparent approval Judge Niemeyer's governing principle that 
 private religious education is an integral part of the American school 
 system.  But that stated principle is the problem, not a virtue.  
 Providing families with the option of achieving the society's secular 
 educational objectives at a private school of their choice, religious or 
 secular, is a governing principle of the American school system.  (And 
 securing the freedom of families to provide or obtain a private religious 
 education outside the American school system is surely a governing 
 principle of our constitutional order (Meyer, Pierce, etc.).)  But 
 religious education as such not only is not an integral part of the 
 American school system -- as a constitutional matter, it can't be part of 
 that system at all.  
 
 On Sat, Jun 30, 2012 at 10:29 AM, Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:
 Dear Marty,
  
 In this case, if I am reading the opinion correctly, the credits in question 
 are coming from Oakbrook Preparatory
 School, an accredited private Christian school. 
 
  
 In my view, the decision is welcome because -- as Marc says, below -- I 
 think it would be the wrong approach to say that, when a student transfers 
 from a non-state school to a state school, he or she may only receive 
 credit for courses with the requisite secular content.  As Judge Niemeyer 
 wrote:
 Also important to our conclusion is the governing principle
 
 that private religious education is an integral part of the
 
 American school system. Indeed, States are constitutionally
 
 obligated to allow children and parents to choose whether to
 
 fulfill their compulsory education obligations by attending a
 
 secular public school or a religious private school.
 
 See Pierce
 v. Soc’y 

Re: Providing public school credits for release-time religious classes

2012-06-30 Thread Marci Hamilton
As a product of public schools who has chosen where to live based on the 
excellence of the public schools for my children, I cannot let Rick get away 
with his shot at the public schools without comment!  But like him, I will move 
on.

On the merits, I don't see why or how the public schools can take frankly 
ecclesiastical courses from frankly religious schools for credit under existing 
doctrine.  

Now, if the argument is that the Court should and may abandon the Establishment 
Clause, let's be honest about that.   It is well known that those hostile to 
separation are hoping this new Court will cut back on the Est Cl

Under existing doctrine, these credits are a violation of the separation of 
church and state and the Memorial and Remonstrance. 


Marci



On Jun 30, 2012, at 2:52 PM, Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:

 Dear Marty,
  
 I think we can all unite in support of (and I'd also welcome a meaningful 
 commitment to enhancing) the 3 Rs in our public schools.   (I'm pretty 
 confident that those R's are better promoted, generally speaking, in 
 religious schools, but I realize that's a debate for another day.)  
  
 In any event, I'm not sure why the question is whether or not the fourth R 
 is integral to the public schools' mission (I'm not sure we really know 
 what the public school's mission is and, again, I suspect that whatever it is 
 is at least as well achieved in religious schools as in public schools.)  
 Instead, I'd ask does it 'establish religion' for a public school to allow 
 two credits for religious education courses taken pursuant to a release-time 
 statute, when those courses are approved by an accredited private school and 
 when the state is not involved in any way in the religious instruction?  I 
 think the answer to this latter question, both doctrinally and (more 
 important) morally and historically, should be no.  There's no 
 entanglement, endorsement, coercion, etc., here.  We allow credits for 
 all kinds of courses with debatable connection to the 3-Rs, let alone the 
 public schools' mission.  It seems to me that -- again, given that the 
 government is not pushing the release-time option, and is not involved in 
 religious instruction -- it is fine for the political community to, in this 
 very small way, which does not subtract meaningfully from the few affected 
 students' secular course of study and which imposes burdens on no one, 
 accommodate the fact that, for many, religious education is education and 
 perhaps acknowledge the possibility that a child's healthy development is 
 advanced as much by (non-state-provided) religious education as by, say, 
 for-credit classes in pottery, or P.E., or high-school sociology. 
  
 I'll quit being a bore now, and sign off on this thread, but am always happy 
 to chat offline, if anyone wants to. 
  
 All the best,
  
 Rick
  
  
 Richard W. Garnett
 Professor of Law  Associate Dean
 Notre Dame Law School
 P.O. Box 780
 Notre Dame, IN  46556-0780
  
 574-631-6981 (office)
 574-631-4197 (fax)
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
 On Behalf Of Marty Lederman [lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
 Sent: Saturday, June 30, 2012 2:05 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Providing public school credits for release-time religious 
 classes
 
 Unless, like Niemeyer, you think that four Rs, not three, are integral to 
 the public school mission.
 
 Sent from my iPhone
 
 On Jun 30, 2012, at 1:55 PM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 
 Marty is undoubtedly correct under current doctrine.  The release time 
 program exists I assume to avoid Establishment Cl problems.  To now argue 
 entanglement is a problem is a constitutional sleight of hand to avoid a 
 violation.   
 
 The entanglement argument is particularly weak given the description of the 
 program
 
 I also think the entanglement argument is specious given that public and 
 private schools set requirements and criteria to accept credit from other 
 schools all the time.  A school does not need to nor does it normally 
 blindly accept courses and/or credits from other schools, private or public.
 
 I am at a loss to understand how this decision is salutary from an academic 
 perspective.  Sounds to me like it is potentially watering down the 3Rs
 
 Marci
 
 
 
 
 
 On Jun 30, 2012, at 11:11 AM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com 
 wrote:
 
 I should add that, wholly apart from whether the particular Spartanburg 
 Bible School class was in any way, as Rick suggests, of some secular 
 educational value (which was, I repeat, not the basis for the court's 
 holding), the South Carolina statute at issue expressly provides that [a] 
 school district board of trustees may award high school students no more 
 than two elective Carnegie units for the completion of released time 
 classes in religious instruction.
 
 That is to say, the credits

Re: Religious exemptions in ND

2012-06-15 Thread Marci Hamilton
The Sherbert/Yoder test was never treated by the 
Supreme Court as a test available across the 
board.   So NARAL's concerns and CHILD 's
Issues would not have been controlled by it

The concern is not over enforcement but rather enforcement
Giving religious groups more power to endanger children is
not a good idea.   

Marci



On Jun 14, 2012, at 11:34 PM, Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu wrote:

 Connecticut and Alabama use “burden” instead of “substantial burden” in their 
 state RFRAs.  Rhode Island, New Mexico, and Missouri speak of “restrictions 
 on religious liberty.”  But I really don’t know how much the difference in 
 language ends up mattering.  Connecticut is a “burden” state, like North 
 Dakota would have been.  But the lower courts in Connecticut have interpreted 
 Connecticut’s RFRA to be equivalent to the standard laid out in Employment 
 Division v. Smith.  It’s hard to see how that is even possible, given what 
 state RFRAs were designed to do.  But there it is.  My South Dakota piece 
 (which Doug referred to earlier) provides the details. 
  
 Given all this, it’s hard for me to understand these fears of dramatic 
 overenforcement.  Even with explicit authorization from state legislatures, 
 we can’t even seem to get back to Sherbert/Yoder—and it’s not as if the 
 Sherbert/Yoder regime led to the horrible things that NARAL was fearing.
  
 Best, Chris
 ___
 Christopher C. Lund
 Assistant Professor of Law
 Wayne State University Law School
 471 West Palmer St.
 Detroit, MI  48202
 l...@wayne.edu
 (313) 577-4046 (phone)
 (313) 577-9016 (fax)
 Website—http://law.wayne.edu/profile/christopher.lund/
 Papers—http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=363402
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Roman P. Storzer
 Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 9:45 PM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND
  
 I believe that New Mexico's speaks in terms of restrict[ing] a person's free 
 exercise of religion.
  
 Roman
  
 Storzer  Greene, P.L.L.C.
  
 1025 Connecticut Avenue, Northwest
 Suite One Thousand
 Washington, D.C. 20011
 Tel: (202) 857-9766
 Fax: (202) 315-3996
  
 110 Wall Street
 Eleventh Floor
 New York, N.Y. 10005
 Tel: (212) 943-4343
 Fax: (202) 315-3996
 
 http://www.storzerandgreene.com
 stor...@storzerandgreene.com
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
 Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 9:32 PM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu; b...@jmcenter.org
 Subject: Re: Religious exemptions in ND
 
 Other than Conn and Alabama, I'm not aware of another state that eliminated 
 substantial from the formulation.
 Are there others?
  
  
 I don't know that all bets would need to be off in any case, since other 
 state 
 RFRAs have long used burden rather than substantial burden, e.g. 
 Connecticut's.
  
 
  
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003
 (212) 790-0215
 hamilto...@aol.com
  
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Eric Rassbach erassb...@becketfund.org
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu; bob 
 b...@jmcenter.org
 Sent: Thu, Jun 14, 2012 9:26 pm
 Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND
 
  
  
 I don't know that all bets would need to be off in any case, since other 
 state 
 RFRAs have long used burden rather than substantial burden, e.g. 
 Connecticut's.
  
  
  
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
 On 
 Behalf Of Douglas Laycock [dlayc...@virginia.edu]
 Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 9:15 PM
 To: b...@jmcenter.org; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Religious exemptions in ND
  
 The Supreme Court of the United states would have had nothing to say about 
 the 
 meaning of Measure 3. It would have been a state law issue.
  
  
  
 On Thu, 14 Jun 2012 20:50:43 -0400 (EDT)
  b...@jmcenter.org b...@jmcenter.org wrote:
 Eric,
  
 Glad to see you focusing on the claims made with respect to Measure 3. I've 
 been
 counseling a nontheistic North Dakota group for over a year on Measure 3 and 
 its
 predecessor. My primary concern has been the potential use of Measure 3 to
 legalize discrimination against atheists, members of minority religions and
 LGBT. Considering the fact that Justice Scalia doesn't believe the 
 Establishment
 Clause protects atheists, Justice Thomas doesn't believe in incorporation and
 six of nine justices self-identify themselves as Catholic, all bets are off 
 what
 would have benn protected by mere burden in Measure 3.
  
 Bob Ritter
 Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty
 A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter
 Falls Church, VA
 703-533-0236
  
  
 On June 14, 2012 at 4:42 PM Eric Rassbach 

Re: Religious exemptions and child sexual abuse

2012-06-15 Thread Marci Hamilton
To be sure church autonomy arguments outpace RFRA arguments, but less than half 
the states have rfras
I don't actually get Doug's point -- a RFRA is irrelevant if it is not the 
dispositive issue in most cases?  It adds a layer of argument in these cases.   
And from the perspective of child protection, it is bad policy.

In any event, Marty has under reported the prevalence of these issues in child 
sex abuse cases. For a summary of the cases and issues, see my cert petition in 
John Doe AP, which I have posted on my Cardozo web page

 http://www.cardozo.yu.edu/uploadedFiles/Cardozo/Profiles/hamilton02-447/MOJohnDoeAPcertpetn.pdf
 
 
 For the most recent case, see the Tennessee Supreme Court decision, Redwing 
 v. Catholic Bishop for the Diocese of Memphis
 


 -
 

On Jun 15, 2012, at 11:31 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:

 Martin Nussbaum’s response on the alleged prevalence of state RFRA arguments 
 and church autonomy arguments:
  
 My previous comments were not about the bankruptcies where federal law, the 
 U.S. Bankruptcy Code, is operative, and RFRA arguments are made and sometimes 
 prevail.
  
 Second, it is one thing to plead an affirmative defense.  It is quite another 
 to file a dispositive motion.  Professor Hamilton writes, Just this week I 
 have seen autonomy argued in Illinois, Hawaii, and California cases.  If she 
 saw the arguments, there must be briefs.  Might she share those three 
 briefs with the group?
  
 The information I have suggests that counsel, at least in Hawaii and 
 California, are not filing dispositive motions arguing that the church 
 autonomy doctrine bars ecclesiastical negligent supervision claims.  Last 
 evening, the leading ecclesiastical defense counsel in California (who has 
 himself handled over 500 cases and who is daily communications with others 
 from that defense bar) told me that he is unaware of defense counsel in 
 California filing dispositive motions contending that tort liability is 
 precluded by the church autonomy doctrine.  I suspect that the practical 
 unavailability of a church autonomy argument against negligent ecclesiastical 
 supervision claims in California has something to do with Church defendants 
 paying out around $1.5 billion in settlements in that state.  The leading 
 ecclesiastical defense counsel in Hawaii also informed me that he is unaware 
 of church autonomy arguments being briefed in Hawaii to bar ecclesiastical 
 negligent supervision claims.  I have not recently conferred with church 
 counsel in Illinois.
  
 Finally, Professor Hamilton only claims that state RFRAs are plead, not 
 argued, in those states with such laws.  This is consistent with what I've 
 seen.
  
 Martin Nussbaum
  
  
 PLEASE TAKE NOTICE, the information contained in this electronic 
 communication and any document attached hereto or transmitted herewith, 
 including metadata, is attorney-client privileged, work product, private or 
 otherwise confidential, and is intended for the exclusive use of the 
 individual or entity named above.  The information transmitted in this e-mail 
 and any attachment is intended only for the personal and confidential use of 
 the intended recipients and is covered by the Electronic Communications 
 Privacy Act, 18 U.S.C. §2510-2521.  If the reader of this message is not the 
 intended recipient or the employee or agent responsible for delivering it to 
 the intended recipient, you are hereby notified that any examination, use, 
 dissemination, distribution, or copying of this communication or any part 
 thereof is strictly prohibited.  If you have received this communication in 
 error, please immediately notify the sender by telephone or reply e-mail and 
 delete this communication.  You are further notified that all personal 
 messages express views solely of the sender which are not to be attributed to 
 Rothgerber Johnson  Lyons LLP and may not be copied or distributed without 
 this disclaimer.
  
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 6:44 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Religious exemptions and child sexual abuse
  
 There is a significant federal RFRA litigation burden in the diocesan 
 bankruptcies.  Marty and I have been on opposite sides litigating it.   I 
 currently represent the victims in the Milwaukee Archdiocesan bankruptcy on 
 the RFRA and First Amendment issues.
  
 I have seen state rfras pled in many cases.   These cases typically settle so 
 decisions are rare.   The trend is definitely against their theories but they 
 are part of the fabric of these cases nonetheless.   
  
 Autonomy theories are persistent in these cases

Re: Religious exemptions in ND

2012-06-15 Thread Marci Hamilton
Public schools should also be held to the same standard as any private 
institution and it should be child-protective

Marci

On Jun 15, 2012, at 11:04 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:

 It is not just other constitutional interests that limit liability for harm 
 to children. It is also other public policies.
  
 For example, in Missouri, where Gibson v. Brewer limits the church’s 
 liability to cases where they knew about abuse and failed to act, public 
 schools have no state-law liability at all in sex abuse cases. See Mo. Stat. 
 §537.600; Letlow v. Evans, 857 F. Supp. 676 (W.D. Mo. 1994); Doe v. Special 
 School District, 637 F. Supp. 1138 (E.D. Mo. 1986). And they would have no 
 federal liability unless an official with authority to act had “actual 
 knowledge” and made “an official decision” not to do anything. Gebser v. Lago 
 Vista Independent School District, 524 U.S. 274, 290 (1998).
  
 The should-have-known liability now imposed on churches in many states, and 
 the should-have-known-there-was-an-elevated-risk liability that is often 
 alleged and sometimes imposed, goes far beyond the liability rules applicable 
 to most public schools.
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Graber, Mark
 Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 9:46 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Religious exemptions in ND
  
 May I suggest this is too strong.  A great many constitutional rights 
 increase to some degree the possibility that child abuse will occur, not be 
 detected and not be adequately punished.  Consider in this respect the Fourth 
 and Fifth Amendments, at least as presently interpreted (and I suspect most 
 of us would not agree with an interpretive rule that said government does not 
 violate the Fourth and Fifth Amendment whenever doing so might increase to 
 any degree the possibility that a crime will not be committed, not be 
 detected, and not be punished.  So we might assume that a) protections for 
 religious freedom will have some negative consequences, including some severe 
 negative consequences but b) that this is true for pretty much all 
 constitutional rights.
  
 So the issue is how much do we risk because we value religious freedom 
 (remembering that a strategy of risk nothing will have other severe bad 
 consequences.
  
 In this vein, may I suggest that the present alternatives are not helpful.  
 SMITH seems to suggest a rational basis test that would allow government to 
 severely burden religious practice whenever doing so has any appreciable 
 tendency to prevent, detect, or punish crime.  Many RFRAs suggest a 
 compelling interest test that probably puts too high a burden on government 
 to do a variety of acts (not just in the area of criminal justice—so even if 
 you think, as I do, that preventing child abuse is obviously a compelling 
 government interest, you might still think the compelling interest standard 
 too strong in other cases).
  
 Strikes me that one thing we might discuss is what that in-between standard 
 looks like.
  
 Mark A. Graber
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Religious exemptions in ND

2012-06-15 Thread Marci Hamilton
That is an inaccurate analysis of my last post -- The attempts to treat these 
issues as de minimis are wrong.  Read my cert petition and the Redwing case out 
of Tennessee

I don't in any way back off of my statement that rfras open the door to more 
child sex abuse and less deterrence.   They don't stand alone but they do.   
Child safety should be excluded from all such laws.

Safe to say they are unlikely to be passed anyway at this point because gay 
rights and women's rights groups have come to understand they are adverse to 
their interests as well.  The danger of the RFRA as I have stated before is its 
blanket blind approach.   It hides the actual agendas of those who seek them.  
Far better for the vulnerable that exemptions be publicly debated.   

Marci

On Jun 15, 2012, at 1:57 PM, lawyer2...@aol.com wrote:

 Agreed.
  
 But in order for there to be a cost of immunity from tort law there first 
 has to be immunity from tort law and, particular to this discussion, 
 immunity from tort law in child sex abuse cases.
  
 This discussion started with the assertion that RFRA's open the door to 
 child sex abuse, lessen deterrence of it, and that RFRA arguments to this 
 end were being made by churches and their lawyers all the time
  
 When that was questioned, the limitless  assertions devolved to RFRA's 
 adding a layer of argument during the course of litigation
  
 --Don Clark
   Nationwide Special Counsel
   United Church of Christ
  
  
  
 In a message dated 6/15/2012 12:40:08 P.M. Central Daylight Time, 
 vol...@law.ucla.edu writes:
 No, actually I think the quote was an unnecessarily pugnacious 
 attempt to capture an important point.  Some religious groups have apparently 
 failed to reasonably investigate and monitor people whom they put in 
 positions of influence over children, and some of those people have used that 
 influence to molest children.  It's at least plausible that holding religious 
 groups liable for negligent hiring, retention, and supervision would provide 
 an extra incentive for such monitoring and investigation in the future.  
 Conversely, it's at least plausible that immunizing those groups from such 
 employer liability would make it easy for them to endanger children -- not 
 through deliberate attempts to harm children, of course, but through failure 
 to protect the children.
 
  
 
 As I've mentioned, I'm skeptical that RFRAs will provide such 
 immunity.  But some states have indeed interpreted the First Amendment as 
 providing such immunity – and even if that is nonetheless the correct result, 
 for non-entanglement reasons or other reasons – it does seem to facilitate 
 religious groups’ failure to take proper care to protect children.  As I 
 said, I think both sides of the discussion have at times put things more 
 pugnaciously than is helpful.  But the basic point of the cost of immunity 
 from tort law is one that should be taken seriously.
 
  
 
 Eugene
 
  
 
  -Original Message-
 
  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-
 
  boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of lawyer2...@aol.com
 
  Sent: Friday, June 15, 2012 3:42 AM
 
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 
  Subject: Re: Religious exemptions in ND
 
 
 
  Giving religious groups more power to endanger children
 
 
 
  Wow
 
 
 
  To be charitable, I will chalk that one up to the lateness of the hour in 
  which it
 
  was written.
 
 
 
  -Don Clark
 
Nationwide Special Counsel
 
United Church of Christ
 
  Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry
 
 
 
  -Original Message-
 
  From: Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com
 
  Sender: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
 
  Date: Fri, 15 Jun 2012 03:08:48
 
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 
  Reply-To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 
  religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 
  Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 
  Subject: Re: Religious exemptions in ND
 
 
 
  ___
 
  To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe,
 
  unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-
 
  bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 
 
  Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
  private.
 
  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people
 
  can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward
 
  the messages to others.
 
  ___
 
  To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe,
 
  unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-
 
  bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 
 
  Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
  private.
 
  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people
 
  can read

Re: Religious exemptions and child sexual abuse

2012-06-14 Thread Marci Hamilton
I was talking about the facts of how these cases are litigated. I represent 
many victims in numerous cases around the country on the First Am and RFRA 
issues.  The RCC and LDS on particular push the religious freedom claims hard 
in such cases. Sometimes together


  Gibson v Brewer out of Missouri Is a good case to start with

Marci

On Jun 14, 2012, at 9:31 AM, Arthur Spitzer artspit...@gmail.com wrote:

 Marci - I don't believe you've stated the facts of a single case. I'd say the 
 same thing if you were a man.
 Art
 
 On Thu, Jun 14, 2012 at 7:27 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 
 I'm not sure why stating the facts in these cases is rhetoric   I sincerely 
 hope it is not because a woman is pointing out the facts rather than a man.  
 This last statement also is not rhetoric but an honest observation.
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Religious exemptions and child sexual abuse

2012-06-14 Thread Marci Hamilton
Doug-- your downplaying of rfras' effect is inaccurate and misleading.   The 
rfras can apply and they are invoked in these casesJust because a case 
comes down on common law theory doesn't mean rfras don't apply.  

I think you have sidestepped the issues.  Obviously, rfras  can be invoked  in 
these cases   Are you opposed to exempting child safety from the RFRAs?   

And what is your view on a RFRA without substantial modifying burden?  

Marci

On Jun 14, 2012, at 11:01 AM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:

 Gibson v. Brewer is an outlier, giving the church more protection than most 
 states provide. And the protection Gibson provides is roughly equivalent to 
 what state and federal law provides the public schools in similar 
 circumstances. No state has even considered giving religious liberty 
 protection to abusers. The only dispute is with respect to entities who 
 weren’t there and didn’t do it, but might have been able to prevent it. And 
 most of those cases are decided under common law rules uninfluenced by RFRAs 
 or free exercise clauses.
  
 I have written about Gibson v. Brewer in Michigan in 2007.
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 10:02 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Religious exemptions and child sexual abuse
  
 I was talking about the facts of how these cases are litigated. I represent 
 many victims in numerous cases around the country on the First Am and RFRA 
 issues.  The RCC and LDS on particular push the religious freedom claims hard 
 in such cases. Sometimes together
  
  
   Gibson v Brewer out of Missouri Is a good case to start with
  
 Marci
 
 On Jun 14, 2012, at 9:31 AM, Arthur Spitzer artspit...@gmail.com wrote:
 
 Marci - I don't believe you've stated the facts of a single case. I'd say the 
 same thing if you were a man.
 Art
 
 On Thu, Jun 14, 2012 at 7:27 AM, Marci Hamilton hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 
 I'm not sure why stating the facts in these cases is rhetoric   I sincerely 
 hope it is not because a woman is pointing out the facts rather than a man.  
 This last statement also is not rhetoric but an honest observation.
  
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Religious exemptions and child sexual abuse

2012-06-14 Thread Marci Hamilton
There is a significant federal RFRA litigation burden in the diocesan 
bankruptcies.  Marty and I have been on opposite sides litigating it.   I 
currently represent the victims in the Milwaukee Archdiocesan bankruptcy on the 
RFRA and First Amendment issues.

I have seen state rfras pled in many cases.   These cases typically settle so 
decisions are rare.   The trend is definitely against their theories but they 
are part of the fabric of these cases nonetheless.   

Autonomy theories are persistent in these cases.   Marty may not have seen the 
briefing but I see such issues from around the country on a daily basis.  Just 
this week I have seen autonomy argued in Illinois, Hawaii, and California cases.

Marci  


On Jun 14, 2012, at 6:01 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:

 I don’t think there is much of a litigation burden from RFRA defenses in 
 sexual abuse cases. The principal news about state RFRAs is that they are 
 seriously underutilized and seriously underenforced when utilized. Chris Lund 
 documents this at 55 S.D. L. Rev. 466 (2010). This is not a good thing, but 
 it’s a fact.
  
 I am not aware of state RFRAs being used at all in sexual abuse cases. Chris 
 mentions no such case, and he cites no case with a Doe or Roe plaintiff. But 
 as Vance says, things can go on in trial courts that law professors don’t 
 know about. So I asked Martin Nussbaum at the Rothgerber firm in Denver 
 whether anyone is using state RFRAs in sexual abuse cases. Martin has 
 represented churches in many sexual abuse cases. Here is what he said:
  
 “I am aware of only one church defense counsel in the past five years, who 
 has filed a dispositive motion based on church autonomy or other religious 
 freedom grounds.   That motion was filed in the past year.  It was not based 
 on a state RFRA argument.  It was unsuccessful.  While the First Amendment 
 precedents are still split on this issue, the majority of such First 
 Amendment arguments after 1-1-02 have lost. 
  
 I am aware of some arguments being made that seek to limit the scope of 
 discovery that invoke confidences mandated by church law and contend that 
 civil courts should respect such confidences due to First Amendment, state 
 confidential clergy communications statutes, and, conceivably, state RFRAs.  
 I cannot point though to instances where an advocate invoked state RFRA laws 
 to limit such discovery.  It may have happened.  I just don't know about it.”
  
 The significance of 2002, of course, is that that is when the news from 
 Boston broke.
  
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Vance R. Koven
 Sent: Thursday, June 14, 2012 1:57 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Religious exemptions and child sexual abuse
  
 I think someone needs to raise a word in defense of Marci here. The 
 perspective of someone who actively litigates these cases has to be different 
 from that of someone who sits in an office reading the decisions and 
 synthesizing the rationales of the cases.
 
 The fact that religious-institution defendants raise RFRAs as a defense to 
 causes of action or to discovery means that the plaintiffs have to go to that 
 much more work (and legal expense) to counter the arguments. In that sense, 
 whether the defenses work or not, there is an additional burden on 
 litigants in having that extra string on the defendant's bow.
 
 
 Vance
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Defeat of RFRA constitutional amendment in North Dakota

2012-06-13 Thread Marci Hamilton
The truth is that gay rights and child protection communities went all out in 
North Dakota.  Most Americans when they understand that a RFRA opens the door 
to discrimination or child sex abuse or medical neglect quickly cool on the 
extremism of a RFRA.   The difference is public education

Marci

On Jun 13, 2012, at 4:39 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:

 NARAL and Planned Parenthood spent a lot of money in a small market to defeat 
 this. They did not spend that kind of money in Alabama, so far as I know. 
 There have been shrill opponents in of state RFRAs in various legislatures, 
 but I am not aware of this kind of effort by NARAL or Planned Parenthood.
  
 Why now and not before? The polarization over sexual morality is the larger 
 cause, and the pending religious liberty claims specifically about 
 contraception and emergency contraception are the most immediate and obvious 
 cause. NARAL and Planned Parenthood now view religious liberty as a bad 
 thing, because it empowers the enemy and puts outside limits on their agenda.
  
 Shameless plug: I wrote about this in general terms, pre North Dakota, in 
 Sex, Atheism, and the Free Exercise of Religion, 88 U. Detroit Mercy L. Rev. 
 407 (2011):
  
 http://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?handle=hein.journals/udetmr88id=417collection=usjournalsindex=journals/udetmr
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Vance R. Koven
 Sent: Wednesday, June 13, 2012 4:23 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Defeat of RFRA constitutional amendment in North Dakota
  
 Behind NARAL's many inaccuracies lies a hint of what I believe may be the 
 sociological basis for answering Eugene's question. What follows is purely 
 speculative on my part, so just treat it as a hypothesis.
 
 The initial RFRA push was, speaking broadly, in line with a sense by 
 evangelical Christians that their agendas, of various types, were threatened 
 by secularists ascendant in Washington and among other political elites.That 
 was then and this is now. 
 
 Apart from liberal Connecticut and Catholic-dominated Rhode Island, most of 
 the state RFRA enactments were in fairly conservative, heartland states. 
 Since a lot of other states have achieved the same effect by judicial 
 decision or existing constitutional provisions, the leftovers have to be 
 looked at as a discrete grouping. The cross-hatched states, with the 
 exception of New Hampshire, are all liberal, secularist places where you 
 would expect Smith to be popular among policy-makers and not totally anathema 
 to voters.
 
 The remaining states without any RFRA-like policies but that haven't firmly 
 declared themselves as following Smith, with the exceptions of California, 
 Hawaii and Vermont, are also mostly conservative heartland states, but they 
 now have a different actuating fear, which I think is the fear (rational or 
 not) of Islamic demands for religious-cultural exceptions from generally 
 applicable laws. This fear directly offsets the fears of evangelical 
 Christians, and is probably shared by a good number of them. NARAL's 
 reference to domestic violence and child abuse look, in that context, like 
 code words for the domestic-relations aspects of Sharia. Obviously, no RFRA 
 statute immunizes domestic violence, but if NARAL said in so many words what 
 it thought the voters really wanted to hear, its anti-Islamic thrust would be 
 too obvious.
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Minister convicted for teaching parishioners to punish children by hitting them on the bare buttocks with wooden dowels

2012-05-15 Thread Marci Hamilton
 parishioners. But if the 
 pastor's instructions to his parishioners are to do something unlawful if a 
 certain pre-condition is satisfied and the pre-condition is sufficiently 
 common that it will almost certainly occur in the very near future, I'm not 
 sure I see the Brandenburg problem. Infants will cry and will fail to sit 
 still. If a speaker instructs a group of parents with very young children to 
 stick their children's hand in boiling water if they cry or fail to sit 
 still, that seems pretty imminent to me. 
  
 If the parishioners follow his instructions and he ratifies their conduct and 
 tells them to continue to do so, I think  that's more than abstract advocacy.
  
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
 on behalf of Volokh, Eugene [vol...@law.ucla.edu]
 Sent: Sunday, May 13, 2012 4:31 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Minister convicted for teaching parishioners to punish children 
 by hitting them on the bare buttocks with wooden dowels
 
 I don’t think that strict scrutiny can justify restrictions 
 that are forbidden by Brandenburg.  After all, in most advocacy-of-crime 
 cases there’s a compelling interest in preventing crime, and a plausible 
 argument that alternatives to suppression of advocacy – e.g., counterspeech 
 and punishment of the criminal conduct – aren’t going to be as effective as 
 suppression (plus those alternatives).  Brandenburg, I think, is a judgment 
 that speech restriction is just not a permissible means of serving the 
 compelling interests, see generally 
 http://www.law.ucla.edu/volokh/scrutiny.htm pts. II.B  III (Freedom of 
 Speech, Permissible Tailoring and Transcending Strict Scrutiny, 144 U. Pa. L. 
 Rev. 2417 (1997)).  And I think that’s as true for speech advocating child 
 abuse as for speech praising rioters, speech advocating the propriety of holy 
 war, and the like.
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Sunday, May 13, 2012 4:24 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Minister convicted for teaching parishioners to punish children 
 by hitting them on the bare buttocks with wooden dowels
  
 Eugene-what about strict scrutiny?
 I think there is a compelling interest in protecting children from being hit 
 with wooden dowels
  
   Given the hidden nature of most such abuse, there is unlikely to be a 
 lesser restrictive method to ensure children are not harmed.  
  
 Marci
 
 On May 13, 2012, at 7:10 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 
 I would think that such a conviction would likely be 
 unconstitutional under the Free Speech Clause, given Brandenburg v. Ohio, 
 even without regard to any special religious freedom claim (note that 
 Wisconsin courts read the Wisconsin Constitution following Sherbert/Yoder).  
 It seems to me that teaching parishioners the propriety of such conduct – 
 even illegal conduct – doesn’t fit within the Brandenburg exception, because 
 it isn’t intended to yield imminent lawless conduct; and I don’t think the 
 general teachings would fit within the United States v. Williams solicitation 
 exception, since no specific act is being discussed.  On the other hand, it’s 
 possible that pastoral counseling of a specific parent, telling the parent to 
 engage in illegal child abuse (assuming the discipline is indeed illegal) 
 might qualify as solicitation of crime and not just abstract advocacy.  Or is 
 this analysis mistaken?
  
 Relatedly, could ministers of churches that teach that 
 marijuana is a sacrament be prosecuted for conspiracy to engage in criminal 
 possession or receipt of marijuana?  Could imams who preach the propriety of 
 jihad be prosecuted for conspiracy to engage in jihad, just based on the 
 teaching alone?
  
 Eugene
  
  
  
 http://host.madison.com/wsj/news/local/crime_and_courts/motion-to-dismiss-charges-against-black-earth-pastor-denied/article_3c17db6a-9b01-11e1-967a-001a4bcf887a.html
  
 A Dane County judge on Thursday denied a motion to dismiss charges against a 
 Black Earth pastor convicted of conspiracy to commit child abuse for 
 advocating the use of wooden rods to spank children as young as 2 months old.
  
 Philip Caminiti, 55, pastor of the Aleitheia Bible Church, was convicted in 
 March of eight counts of conspiracy to commit child abuse for instructing 
 church members to punish children by hitting them on the bare buttocks with 
 wooden dowels to teach them to behave correctly, in keeping with the church's 
 literal interpretation of the Bible.
  
 The motion to dismiss the charges alleged Caminiti had been deprived of his 
 constitutional right to religious freedom.
  
 Circuit Judge Maryann Sumi found that Caminiti had a sincerely held 
 religious belief

Re: Minister convicted for teaching parishioners to punish children by hitting them on the bare buttocks with wooden dowels

2012-05-14 Thread Marci Hamilton
Eugene-what about strict scrutiny?
I think there is a compelling interest in protecting children from being hit 
with wooden dowels

  Given the hidden nature of most such abuse, there is unlikely to be a lesser 
restrictive method to ensure children are not harmed.  

Marci

On May 13, 2012, at 7:10 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 I would think that such a conviction would likely be 
 unconstitutional under the Free Speech Clause, given Brandenburg v. Ohio, 
 even without regard to any special religious freedom claim (note that 
 Wisconsin courts read the Wisconsin Constitution following Sherbert/Yoder).  
 It seems to me that teaching parishioners the propriety of such conduct – 
 even illegal conduct – doesn’t fit within the Brandenburg exception, because 
 it isn’t intended to yield imminent lawless conduct; and I don’t think the 
 general teachings would fit within the United States v. Williams solicitation 
 exception, since no specific act is being discussed.  On the other hand, it’s 
 possible that pastoral counseling of a specific parent, telling the parent to 
 engage in illegal child abuse (assuming the discipline is indeed illegal) 
 might qualify as solicitation of crime and not just abstract advocacy.  Or is 
 this analysis mistaken?
  
 Relatedly, could ministers of churches that teach that 
 marijuana is a sacrament be prosecuted for conspiracy to engage in criminal 
 possession or receipt of marijuana?  Could imams who preach the propriety of 
 jihad be prosecuted for conspiracy to engage in jihad, just based on the 
 teaching alone?
  
 Eugene
  
  
  
 http://host.madison.com/wsj/news/local/crime_and_courts/motion-to-dismiss-charges-against-black-earth-pastor-denied/article_3c17db6a-9b01-11e1-967a-001a4bcf887a.html
  
 A Dane County judge on Thursday denied a motion to dismiss charges against a 
 Black Earth pastor convicted of conspiracy to commit child abuse for 
 advocating the use of wooden rods to spank children as young as 2 months old.
  
 Philip Caminiti, 55, pastor of the Aleitheia Bible Church, was convicted in 
 March of eight counts of conspiracy to commit child abuse for instructing 
 church members to punish children by hitting them on the bare buttocks with 
 wooden dowels to teach them to behave correctly, in keeping with the church's 
 literal interpretation of the Bible.
  
 The motion to dismiss the charges alleged Caminiti had been deprived of his 
 constitutional right to religious freedom.
  
 Circuit Judge Maryann Sumi found that Caminiti had a sincerely held 
 religious belief as a Christian fundamentalist that requires using a rod to 
 discipline children beginning at a young age. But Sumi said Caminiti failed 
 to show the state's child abuse statute places a burden on his sincerely 
 held religious belief.
  
 Scripture doesn't specify how and when the rod should be used, Sumi said, 
 adding that Caminiti also was willing to modify the church's practices to 
 comply with the law
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause challenge

2012-04-18 Thread Marci Hamilton
Eugene-- that does not respond to my point.   Cutter is a narrow opinion saying 
RLUIPA does not on its face violate the Establishment Clause.  It does not say 
that every program considered under RLUIPA is safe from Establishment Clause 
attack.  

Marci

On Apr 16, 2012, at 5:54 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 Well, Ellis was arguing that “the issue” was whether “RFRA 
 and RLUIPA ... are secular in purpose and effect.”  I read Cutter as 
 concluding that they are, though indeed particular accommodations implemented 
 out of a desire to avoid RLUIPA litigation might not be.
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Monday, April 16, 2012 1:33 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
 challenge
  
 Cutter only addressed the facial Establishment  Clause attack on the prison 
 provisions of RLUIPA.  It did not protect any particular program or exemption 
 from attack
  
 Marci
 
 On Apr 12, 2012, at 7:19 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 
 Maybe it would and maybe it wouldn’t, but I don’t think that 
 makes the purpose religious, or makes the effect primarily the advancement of 
 religion (whatever “primary effect” might mean); it just suggests that the 
 policy might prove counterproductive relative to the secular government 
 purpose.
  
 As to RLUIPA being “secular in purpose and effect,” the 
 Supreme Court unanimously said in Cutter that RLUIPA is constitutional.  
 Maybe one can imagine contrary arguments, but they didn’t impress any of the 
 Justices, even Stevens.
  
 But even if RLUIPA didn’t exist, the no-pork policy would be 
 permissible for the reasons Doug mentions.  Likewise, a uniform vegetarian 
 diet policy would also be constitutionally permissible.
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of West, Ellis
 Sent: Thursday, April 12, 2012 2:39 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
 challenge
  
 I should have added to the post below that the policy might create as much 
 conflict as it eliminates, just as would a vegetarian diet.
  
 Ellis M. West
 Emeritus Professor of Political Science
 University of Richmond, VA 23173
 804-289-8536
 ew...@richmond.edu
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of West, Ellis
 Sent: Thursday, April 12, 2012 5:21 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
 challenge
  
 Sure avoiding litigation is a secular purpose, but only if one assumes that 
 RFRA and RLUIPA, the basis of the litigation, are secular in purpose and 
 effect, but that is precisely the issue.  Suppose these two laws did not 
 exist.  Then would the prison policy in question be secular in nature?  The 
 avoidance of conflict might also be a secular purpose, but it would justify 
 all kinds of exemptions, not just religion-based exemptions, because persons 
 object to all kinds of laws for all kinds of reasons.  For example, as Prof 
 Levinson suggested in an earlier post, it would justify a uniform vegetarian 
 diet for all prisoners.
  
 Ellis M. West
 Emeritus Professor of Political Science
 University of Richmond, VA 23173
 804-289-8536
 ew...@richmond.edu
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
 Sent: Thursday, April 12, 2012 4:36 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
 challenge
  
 Avoiding litigation (and there are many, many RLUIPA and free exercise cases 
 about prison diets) and other forms of conflict, and having the efficiencies 
 of a uniform diet for all prisoners, sound like secular purposes to me.
 
 On Thu, Apr 12, 2012 at 3:34 PM, West, Ellis ew...@richmond.edu wrote:
 Although the District Court may be correct in saying that the primary purpose 
 of the policy is not “to establish the religion of Islam” or to “promote the 
 practice of Islam,” it does concede that the policy “makes accommodating a 
 multitude of religious practices and beliefs easier and more economical.”  
 Would someone explain to me how that purpose and/or effect is “secular” in 
 nature?  Even though Prof. Lupu may be correct in saying that this particular 
 policy is good way of accommodating religious beliefs/practices, his comment 
 simply assumes that a policy of accommodating religious beliefs/practices is 
 secular in nature.  How so?
  
 Ellis M. West

Re: Statement on Religious Liberty from USCCB

2012-04-16 Thread Marci Hamilton
This is a statement of their preferred public policy not constitutional law.   

Marci


On Apr 13, 2012, at 6:47 AM, Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:

 The Conference of Catholic Bishops just issued this major Statement on 
 Religious Liberty:
 
 http://usccb.org/issues-and-action/religious-liberty/upload/Our_First_Most_Cherished_Liberty.pdf
 
 I'd be curious to hear what others think of it.  Its basic thrust is that 
 religious liberty is now acutely under attack in the U.S., in a way it has 
 not been in quite a while.  Indeed, what is at stake is no less than 
 whether America will continue to have a free, creative, and robust civil 
 society—or whether the state alone will determine who gets to contribute to 
 the common good, and how they get to do it.  Do you think they've made the 
 case for such an indictment?
 
 Furthermore, it quotes liberally from Dr. King's letter from the Birmingham 
 jail, and urges citizens to have the courage not to obey the laws that 
 allegedly are presenting this profound threat.  (What are the odds there will 
 be much civil disobedience of the laws they have in mind? -- not a rhetorical 
 question.)  And it invokes  Lincoln at Gettysburg in asking for a fast for a 
 new birth of freedom in our beloved country.
 
 Thoughts?
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause challenge

2012-04-16 Thread Marci Hamilton
Cutter only addressed the facial Establishment  Clause attack on the prison 
provisions of RLUIPA.  It did not protect any particular program or exemption 
from attack

Marci

On Apr 12, 2012, at 7:19 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 Maybe it would and maybe it wouldn’t, but I don’t think that 
 makes the purpose religious, or makes the effect primarily the advancement of 
 religion (whatever “primary effect” might mean); it just suggests that the 
 policy might prove counterproductive relative to the secular government 
 purpose.
  
 As to RLUIPA being “secular in purpose and effect,” the 
 Supreme Court unanimously said in Cutter that RLUIPA is constitutional.  
 Maybe one can imagine contrary arguments, but they didn’t impress any of the 
 Justices, even Stevens.
  
 But even if RLUIPA didn’t exist, the no-pork policy would be 
 permissible for the reasons Doug mentions.  Likewise, a uniform vegetarian 
 diet policy would also be constitutionally permissible.
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of West, Ellis
 Sent: Thursday, April 12, 2012 2:39 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
 challenge
  
 I should have added to the post below that the policy might create as much 
 conflict as it eliminates, just as would a vegetarian diet.
  
 Ellis M. West
 Emeritus Professor of Political Science
 University of Richmond, VA 23173
 804-289-8536
 ew...@richmond.edu
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of West, Ellis
 Sent: Thursday, April 12, 2012 5:21 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
 challenge
  
 Sure avoiding litigation is a secular purpose, but only if one assumes that 
 RFRA and RLUIPA, the basis of the litigation, are secular in purpose and 
 effect, but that is precisely the issue.  Suppose these two laws did not 
 exist.  Then would the prison policy in question be secular in nature?  The 
 avoidance of conflict might also be a secular purpose, but it would justify 
 all kinds of exemptions, not just religion-based exemptions, because persons 
 object to all kinds of laws for all kinds of reasons.  For example, as Prof 
 Levinson suggested in an earlier post, it would justify a uniform vegetarian 
 diet for all prisoners.
  
 Ellis M. West
 Emeritus Professor of Political Science
 University of Richmond, VA 23173
 804-289-8536
 ew...@richmond.edu
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
 Sent: Thursday, April 12, 2012 4:36 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
 challenge
  
 Avoiding litigation (and there are many, many RLUIPA and free exercise cases 
 about prison diets) and other forms of conflict, and having the efficiencies 
 of a uniform diet for all prisoners, sound like secular purposes to me.
 
 On Thu, Apr 12, 2012 at 3:34 PM, West, Ellis ew...@richmond.edu wrote:
 Although the District Court may be correct in saying that the primary purpose 
 of the policy is not “to establish the religion of Islam” or to “promote the 
 practice of Islam,” it does concede that the policy “makes accommodating a 
 multitude of religious practices and beliefs easier and more economical.”  
 Would someone explain to me how that purpose and/or effect is “secular” in 
 nature?  Even though Prof. Lupu may be correct in saying that this particular 
 policy is good way of accommodating religious beliefs/practices, his comment 
 simply assumes that a policy of accommodating religious beliefs/practices is 
 secular in nature.  How so?
  
 Ellis M. West
 Emeritus Professor of Political Science
 University of Richmond, VA 23173
 804-289-8536
 ew...@richmond.edu
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
 Sent: Wednesday, April 11, 2012 7:32 PM
 
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Court upholds prison no-pork policy against Establishment Clause 
 challenge
  
 Is this outcome surprising in any way?  Does anyone on the list believe that 
 the court got this wrong? (I certainly don't).
  
 If Congress overrode HHS and eliminated pregnancy prevention services from 
 mandatory coverage by employers under the Affordable Care Act, wouldn't the 
 analysis be just the same (imposition of a uniform policy to avoid religious 
 conflict, avoid any need to create controversial exceptions for religious 
 entities, avoid piece-meal litigation, and ease administration of the overall 
 scheme), even though the impetus for change derived from a demand by some for 
 religious accommodation?
 
 On 

Re: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their actions

2012-03-08 Thread Marci Hamilton
I have to say that I find Steve's analysis more sound and based on common 
sense.   


Marci

On Mar 7, 2012, at 3:07 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 I think the analysis below is mistaken:  Whether or not cabbies’ refusal to 
 carry alcohol should be barred by some general common-carriage requirement, 
 it shouldn’t be treated as religious discrimination.  What’s more, I think 
 the argument that such a refusal is religious discrimination itself calls for 
 discrimination against those with religious motivations for their actions.
  
 1.  To begin with, as others have pointed out, the cabbies’ actions affected 
 Christians, Jews, Muslims, the irreligious, and anyone else who carried 
 alcohol.  Moreover, they didn’t affect Christian, Jews, Muslims, the 
 irreligious, and anyone else who didn’t carry alcohol.
  
 2.  Now I take it that the response is that the really devout Muslims of the 
 same religious views as the cabbies generally wouldn’t be affected (just as, 
 I suppose, Mormons or Methodists wouldn’t be affected), because they 
 generally wouldn’t carry alcohol.  But that analysis strikes me as unsound, 
 and here’s why.
  
 Imagine a case closely modeled on Rasmussen v. Glass (Minn. Ct. App. 1993) 
 (review granted but appeal later dismissed), 
 http://scholar.google.com/scholar_case?case=648897692635049631.  A restaurant 
 owner refuses to deliver food to a doctor who performs abortions, because the 
 owner believes abortions are evil, and doesn’t want to provide any help, even 
 indirect, to such evil.  And say the restaurant owner’s is irreligious, and 
 his opposition to abortion is based on his own personal moral views (e.g., he 
 follows Nat Hentoff, 
 http://groups.csail.mit.edu/mac/users/rauch/nvp/consistent/indivisible.html). 
  I take it that we would all agree that the restaurant owner is not 
 discriminating based on religion.  To be sure, devout Catholics, and devout 
 members of other anti-abortion religious groups, wouldn’t perform abortions.  
 But that doesn’t mean the restaurant owner is discriminating based on the 
 would-be customers’ religions – he’s discriminating based on their secular 
 actions.
  
 Now say that another restaurant owner acts precisely the same way, but his 
 opposition to abortion is based on his religious views.  As I understand the 
 argument below, he would be seen as discriminating based on religion, because 
 the performing of abortion is “a badge of a religion different from yours.”  
 And thus he would be presumptively required to deliver to the doctor’s 
 office, if state public accommodations law covers discrimination based on 
 religion in restaurant delivery.  But this would mean that the law itself has 
 become religiously discriminatory:  The secular anti-abortion restaurant 
 owner is free to do something (here, refusing to deliver to an abortion 
 provider), but the religious anti-abortion restaurant owner is barred from 
 doing precisely the same thing.
  
 3.  I think the same applies to the alcohol example.  A secular cab driver 
 who opposes alcohol on secular grounds would presumably not be treated as 
 discriminating based on religion.  But to treat the religious cab driver who 
 opposes alcohol on religious grounds would be treated as discriminating based 
 on religion, and would thus be potentially violating relevant public 
 accommodations bans.  Yet such an approach would itself impermissibly 
 discriminate (in violation of Lukumi Babalu) against the religious cab driver 
 based on the religiosity of his motivation for his conduct.  Or am I missing 
 something here?
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
 Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 7:10 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Cabbies vs. lawyers
  
 Of course it is a proxy -- just like a collar or burka or yarmulke -- a badge 
 of a religion different from yours -- only in this case it is alcohol 
 possession -- a badge of a religion different from yours.  The dodge of oh, 
 I'm not against their religion, just against their conduct can't be allowed 
 can it?  The person transporting the alcohol is the passenger, not the cab 
 driver.  The fact of hidden vs. open possession of the bottle of wine gives 
 it away, doesn't it -- it is not about the action, it is about the religious 
 nature of the action -- the violation of the religious beliefs of the driver 
 by the religious beliefs (ok to have and transport alcohol) by the passenger.
  
 It is action based on a difference of religious belief.  That is 
 discrimination no matter how one twists it.
  
 Maybe we should allow this discrimination, just like maybe we should allow 
 discrimination in allowing landlords to discriminate against gays based on 
 the landlord's religious beliefs, but that is still religious-based 
 discrimination.  
  
 You can't suddenly say that motivation doesn't matter just 

Re: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for their actions

2012-03-07 Thread Marci Hamilton
Eugene--I'm going to focus on the third, relevant issue.   The restaurant 
examples are not analogous because one can do the act and the other cannot do 
it.   In the cabbie situation neither can

 The cabbie who refuses to carry alcohol for secular reasons loses his job 
because he is refusing to do his job.  The cabbie who refuses for religious 
reasons is subject to the same rule.   The only question is whether there 
should be an exemption.   Under Smith and Hershberger even, I think the 
religious cabbie loses.  So then it is just a matter of public policy.I 
will leave that to the lawmakers

I would add that Hershberger was decided at the height of the misleading 
doctrinal hysteria over Smith.  It is unfortunate that the state Courts were 
persuaded to make either/or decisions about free exercise in that context   
They like Congress were given a false choice

You have to give her credit--  Justice OConnor conceded that there were 
definite arenas where SS had not applied  

Since then, there has been a lot more public education about the actual impact 
of SS on the vulnerable and affected.   That is why the state rfras slowed down 
considerably and the W Va version is going nowhere.   

I apologize for going so far off topic


Marci





On Mar 7, 2012, at 6:55 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 So let me make sure I understand your view correctly:
  
 1.  A secular restaurant owner who refuses to deliver to an 
 abortion provider for secular reasons is not guilty of religious 
 discrimination in violation of public accommodations laws.  (Assume such laws 
 generally apply to discrimination based on religion in restaurant deliveries.)
  
 2.  A religious restaurant owner who refuses to deliver to an 
 abortion provider for religious reasons is indeed guilty of religious 
 discrimination in violation of public accommodations laws.  (Assume such laws 
 generally apply to discrimination based on religion in restaurant deliveries.)
  
 Is that so?  And, if so, doesn’t that make the law itself 
 into an unconstitutional religious discrimination, given that it treats 
 precisely the same conduct differently based on the religious motivation of 
 the actor, in violation of the Lukumi Babalu principle?
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marci Hamilton
 Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 3:39 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Discrimination against people with religious motivations for 
 their actions
  
 I have to say that I find Steve's analysis more sound and based on common 
 sense.   
  
  
 Marci
 
 On Mar 7, 2012, at 3:07 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
 
 I think the analysis below is mistaken:  Whether or not cabbies’ refusal to 
 carry alcohol should be barred by some general common-carriage requirement, 
 it shouldn’t be treated as religious discrimination.  What’s more, I think 
 the argument that such a refusal is religious discrimination itself calls for 
 discrimination against those with religious motivations for their actions.
  
 1.  To begin with, as others have pointed out, the cabbies’ actions affected 
 Christians, Jews, Muslims, the irreligious, and anyone else who carried 
 alcohol.  Moreover, they didn’t affect Christian, Jews, Muslims, the 
 irreligious, and anyone else who didn’t carry alcohol.
  
 2.  Now I take it that the response is that the really devout Muslims of the 
 same religious views as the cabbies generally wouldn’t be affected (just as, 
 I suppose, Mormons or Methodists wouldn’t be affected), because they 
 generally wouldn’t carry alcohol.  But that analysis strikes me as unsound, 
 and here’s why.
  
 Imagine a case closely modeled on Rasmussen v. Glass (Minn. Ct. App. 1993) 
 (review granted but appeal later dismissed), 
 http://scholar.google.com/scholar_case?case=648897692635049631.  A restaurant 
 owner refuses to deliver food to a doctor who performs abortions, because the 
 owner believes abortions are evil, and doesn’t want to provide any help, even 
 indirect, to such evil.  And say the restaurant owner’s is irreligious, and 
 his opposition to abortion is based on his own personal moral views (e.g., he 
 follows Nat Hentoff, 
 http://groups.csail.mit.edu/mac/users/rauch/nvp/consistent/indivisible.html). 
  I take it that we would all agree that the restaurant owner is not 
 discriminating based on religion.  To be sure, devout Catholics, and devout 
 members of other anti-abortion religious groups, wouldn’t perform abortions.  
 But that doesn’t mean the restaurant owner is discriminating based on the 
 would-be customers’ religions – he’s discriminating based on their secular 
 actions.
  
 Now say that another restaurant owner acts precisely the same way, but his 
 opposition to abortion

Re: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath

2012-03-07 Thread Marci Hamilton
So only those practices that are mandatory are relevant?  Isn't that a 
centrality requirement?  

Marci

On Mar 3, 2012, at 4:50 PM, Alan Armstrong alanarmstrong@verizon.net 
wrote:

 I think that is not relevant.
 
 I thought the Saturday afternoon/evening mass was for those who could not 
 make it to church Sunday morning.
 
 An Orange County Register columnist, Frank Mickadeit, called it the slakers' 
 mass.
 
 Alan
 
 Law Office of Alan Leigh Armstrong
 Office 18652 Florida St., Suite 225
 Huntington Beach CA 92648-6006
 Mail 16835 Algonquin St., Suite 454
 Huntington Beach CA 92649-3810
 714 375 1147 fax 714 782 6007
 a...@alanarmstrong.com
 Serving the family and small business since 1984
 NOTICE: 
  Any tax advice in this e-mail, including attachments, can not be used to
 avoid penalties or for the promotion of a tax related matter.
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 On Mar 3, 2012, at 12:21 PM, Marci Hamilton wrote:
 
 Lots of Catholics go to Saturday evening mass.   Relevant?
 
 On Mar 3, 2012, at 2:55 PM, Alan Armstrong alanarmstrong@verizon.net 
 wrote:
 
 My understanding is that Jewish and 7th day adventists consider sabbath as 
 going from sundown on Friday to sundown on Saturday. I do not know of any 
 christian denominations that use sundown Saturday to sundown on Sunday as 
 the Lord's day.Therefore a Saturday night game should be acceptable to all.
 
 A little thought and common sense and we would need fewer lawyers.
 
 Alan
 
 Law Office of Alan Leigh Armstrong
 Office 18652 Florida St., Suite 225
 Huntington Beach CA 92648-6006
 Mail 16835 Algonquin St., Suite 454
 Huntington Beach CA 92649-3810
 714 375 1147 fax 714 782 6007
 a...@alanarmstrong.com
 Serving the family and small business since 1984
 NOTICE: 
  Any tax advice in this e-mail, including attachments, can not be used to
 avoid penalties or for the promotion of a tax related matter.
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 On Mar 2, 2012, at 11:48 AM, Douglas Laycock wrote:
 
 Some of you may have seen the story in the Times the other day about the 
 Beren Hebrew Academy in Houston, whose basketball team has reached the 
 state semi-finals of the Texas Association of Private and Parochial 
 Schools tournament. The semifinal game was scheduled for tonight; the 
 Academy is Orthodox and observant, and could not play.  The other school 
 was willing to reschedule, but the TAPPS Board voted 8-0 not to allow 
 that. Most TAPPS members are church affiliated, and as a matter of policy, 
 it never schedules games on Sunday.
  
 Beren parents and students filed a lawsuit this morning in the Northern 
 District of Texas, alleging unconstitutional religious discrimination, 
 Texas RFRA, and breach of contract (based on a provision in the TAPPS 
 bylaws). The complaint’s state action theory was that the game was 
 scheduled to be played in a public school gym, which is surely not enough. 
 The contract claim looked stronger, judging only by the complaint.
  
 Richard Friedman at Michigan tells me that TAPPS caved as soon as the 
 complaint was filed, and that the game will begin imminently and will be 
 completed before sunset.  If your position is utterly untenable as a 
 matter of public relations, it may not matter that the other side’s state 
 action theory is very weak. But they had to file the lawsuit before common 
 sense could prevail.
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
  
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are 
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or 
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are 
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or 
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are 
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or 
 wrongly) forward the messages to others

Re: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?

2012-03-07 Thread Marci Hamilton
Eugene-- just a point of information--is there a lead MN Sup Court case that 
applying  strict scrutiny in cases involving neutral generally applicable laws 
and worship conduct that is illegal? 

Thanks! 

On Mar 7, 2012, at 3:11 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 But the Minnesota Constitution has been interpreted as 
 following Sherbert and Yoder, so isn’t the question indeed why the cab 
 drivers aren’t constitutionally entitled to an exemption?  As it happens, I 
 oppose constitutional exemption regimes, at the state and federal levels, and 
 support jurisdiction-by-jurisdiction RFRAs, which means the question becomes 
 statutory, and trumpable by the state legislature.  But the Minnesota rule is 
 one of constitutionally mandated exemptions, unless strict scrutiny is 
 satisfied, no?
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Steven Jamar
 Sent: Wednesday, March 07, 2012 7:22 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Requirement that cabbies transport alcohol = tiny burden?
  
 For the record, I was in favor of the accommodation attempted for the Somali 
 Muslim cab drivers in Minneapolis and am in favor of most accommodations of 
 religion done by employers and public agencies and the government in general 
 -- even quite odd ones like this particular interpretation of the Quran by 
 this group of Somalis.
  
 But that is quite different from positing that there is a right in the 
 Somalis to engage in this sort of discrimination let alone a constitutional 
 right to do so.  
  
 Doug is right -- sometimes hostility to religious accommodation is motivated 
 by a universalist thrust that we should in fact all be treated equally -- the 
 same sort of hostility one sees against affirmative action for Blacks.  And 
 Doug is also right that sometimes the hostility is directed against a 
 religion and members of that religion -- as JWs, Muslims, Jews, and in some 
 settings and some times, Catholics and others have experienced (19th Century 
 Baptist prayer -- God save us from the Unitarians who at the time had 
 circuit riders and were quite evangelical, unlike today).  
  
 No doubt both of these played into this event -- especially hostility to 
 Islam.
  
 But the subtextual motivation of hostility to the religion cannot make what 
 is otherwise lawful discrimination unlawful, or does it?  Is there a 
 constitutionally meaningful distinction between -- I don't like your 
 religion and therefor will not accommodate you  and I don't think you are 
 entitled to an accommodation as a matter of constitutional right -- where 
 there is in fact no constitutional right to accommodation, as here.
  
 Steve
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath

2012-03-06 Thread Marci Hamilton
Frankly, common sense or at least a full evaluation of all of the non religious 
interests seems lacking on the side of those claims accommodation.   

On Mar 3, 2012, at 6:41 PM, Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:

 The trouble with “common sense” is that it often points in 
 different directions.  Common sense tells us there is real value to following 
 rules with no exceptions, so that one doesn’t have to later deal with 
 questions of “you accommodated them, why don’t you accommodate” us (even when 
 the future request for accommodation might be different from the current 
 one), and also to having a schedule that is predictable, especially given 
 that team members and others related to the team may often plan their 
 schedules around the preannounced playing schedule.  Common sense also tells 
 us that there is real value to being flexible, especially for what could be a 
 once-in-a-lifetime event for the kids in whose interest the league is 
 supposed to be operating. 
  
 Likewise, respect for others sometimes includes changing your plans for 
 others – and sometimes not insisting that others change their plans for you.  
 On balance, I’m pleased with TAPPS’ ultimate decision to accommodate the 
 Jewish team, but I’m not sure that “common sense” and “respect” by themselves 
 resolve this question.
  
 Eugene
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Finkelman, Paul 
 paul.finkel...@albanylaw.edu
 Sent: Saturday, March 03, 2012 12:32 PM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Re: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath
  
 The common sense is what is often lacking and with a sense of fairness and 
 toleration.  Apparently for the leaders of the TAPP common sense means 
 everyone is a Christian and all people have a Sunday sabbath.  The lawyers 
 serve as educator to teach common sense and respect for other religions. 
 
 Connected by DROID on Verizon Wireless
 
 
 -Original message-
 From: Alan Armstrong alanarmstrong@verizon.net
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Sent: Sat, Mar 3, 2012 19:56:56 GMT+00:00
 Subject: Re: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath
 
 My understanding is that Jewish and 7th day adventists consider sabbath as 
 going from sundown on Friday to sundown on Saturday. I do not know of any 
 christian denominations that use sundown Saturday to sundown on Sunday as the 
 Lord's day.Therefore a Saturday night game should be acceptable to all.
  
 A little thought and common sense and we would need fewer lawyers.
  
 Alan
  
 Law Office of Alan Leigh Armstrong
 Office 18652 Florida St., Suite 225
 Huntington Beach CA 92648-6006
 Mail 16835 Algonquin St., Suite 454
 Huntington Beach CA 92649-3810
 714 375 1147 fax 714 782 6007
 a...@alanarmstrong.com
 Serving the family and small business since 1984
 NOTICE: 
  Any tax advice in this e-mail, including attachments, can not be used to
 avoid penalties or for the promotion of a tax related matter.
  
  
  
  
  
 
 
  
 On Mar 2, 2012, at 11:48 AM, Douglas Laycock wrote:
 
 
 Some of you may have seen the story in the Times the other day about the 
 Beren Hebrew Academy in Houston, whose basketball team has reached the state 
 semi-finals of the Texas Association of Private and Parochial Schools 
 tournament. The semifinal game was scheduled for tonight; the Academy is 
 Orthodox and observant, and could not play.  The other school was willing to 
 reschedule, but the TAPPS Board voted 8-0 not to allow that. Most TAPPS 
 members are church affiliated, and as a matter of policy, it never schedules 
 games on Sunday.
  
 Beren parents and students filed a lawsuit this morning in the Northern 
 District of Texas, alleging unconstitutional religious discrimination, Texas 
 RFRA, and breach of contract (based on a provision in the TAPPS bylaws). The 
 complaint’s state action theory was that the game was scheduled to be played 
 in a public school gym, which is surely not enough. The contract claim looked 
 stronger, judging only by the complaint.
  
 Richard Friedman at Michigan tells me that TAPPS caved as soon as the 
 complaint was filed, and that the game will begin imminently and will be 
 completed before sunset.  If your position is utterly untenable as a matter 
 of public relations, it may not matter that the other side’s state action 
 theory is very weak. But they had to file the lawsuit before common sense 
 could prevail.
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 = div=
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the 

Re: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath

2012-03-06 Thread Marci Hamilton
There is significant precedent for one-religion sporting events, which I assume 
everyone agrees is fine.Catholic Leagues exist in numerous cities   And the 
Maccabiah Games feature only Jewish athletes.  

TAPPs' first mistake appears to have been opening itself up to religious 
organizations with different religious needs and demands.  

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University 
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY.  10003
(212) 790-0215



On Mar 4, 2012, at 9:51 PM, Paul Horwitz phorw...@hotmail.com wrote:

 I agree that the word liberty may be problematic here. Of course it depends 
 on the circumstances: some set of facts, or some particular state law regime, 
 might involve a public sports league, or some set of religious rights of 
 non-discrimination in a place of public accommodation. (Although, even if a 
 public accommodation law were involved, that doesn't seem to me, a supporter 
 of BSA v. Dale, to answer the question whether a largely religious sporting 
 association would be obliged to accommodate others.) I didn't do very much 
 research on this, but I didn't immediately spot relevant laws in Texas on 
 this subject, and TAPPS is a private league. So liberty is not the best word 
 here.
 
 Pluralism, on the other hand, goes some of the way, given the facts, 
 especially as it relates to the word hospitality, which Eugene uses. Groups 
 might choose to stay small and insular in order to avoid these kinds of 
 scheduling problems and other conflicts. If, on the other hand, they are 
 interested in expanding their reach, for a variety of reasons (among others, 
 pre-collegiate athletics, including interleague exhibition and championship 
 play, is becoming an increasingly profitable and organized activity across 
 the country; the New Yorker recently ran an interesting story on that 
 subject), then they ought to know at some point that doing so will bring them 
 in contact with other religious groups and individuals with other needs. As 
 long as they are interested in hosting such play, they ought to think in a 
 forward-looking and, I hope, accommodating way about these issues, and 
 anticipate them rather than stumble into them. As to the questionnaire to 
 Muslim schools, I honestly don't know enough about the facts to do anything 
 other than wonder what they were thinking. 
 
 I should add that I'm quoted in yesterday's Times story, and the quote is 
 accurate enough, but in light of this exchange I must emphasize that the 
 primary point I made in talking to the reporter was not one about the law, 
 but about the increasing likelihood that more leagues will deal with more 
 issues of religious conflict or accommodation as they grow larger, the need 
 for those leagues to figure out how much their own sectarianism matters to 
 them and how much having a broader field of members and competitors does, and 
 in either case the need to think through their mission first and act 
 accordingly. Of course there are law-and-religion issues and overtones here, 
 but we are better off thinking through what pluralism demands in any event, 
 whether the law is at issue or not. The answer won't always be that pluralism 
 demands accommodation, at least by private actors; but it may be that private 
 actors of this kind that are interested in interacting with other groups, 
 including inviting other teams with other beliefs to compete in play, are 
 indeed obliged to accommodate, or at least to try to. 
 
 Best,
 
 Paul Horwitz
 University of Alabama School of Law
  
 
  From: vol...@law.ucla.edu
  To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
  Date: Sun, 4 Mar 2012 14:17:32 -0800
  Subject: RE: Basketball tournaments on the Sabbath
  
  I wonder whether religious liberty is exactly the right term here, where 
  we're talking about access to a privately provided program, and one that is 
  hardly essential for life or livelihood. The question isn't just whether 
  Orthodox Jews are free to live as good Orthodox Jews, or even are free to 
  get broadly available benefits of the welfare state that are important to 
  survival (such as unemployment compensation). Rather, the question is 
  whether other private parties should adapt their behavior -- their exercise 
  of their own liberty -- to accommodate Orthodox Jews' felt religious 
  obligations. That's an interesting question, and the answer might well be 
  that they should so adapt their behavior, if it's a low-cost adaptation, 
  out of hospitality or kindness or application of the Golden Rule or some 
  such. But I think that talk of liberty here is not very helpful.
  
  Eugene
  
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 

  1   2   >