RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-06 Thread Scarberry, Mark
Chip:

I don’t take kindly to threats. Say what you want to say, or don’t.

O’Brien doesn’t apply here, and no one is talking about spray painting anyone’s 
house.

A typical definition of “self-serving” is

“Serving one's own interests often in disregard of the truth or the interests 
of others.”

http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/self-serving.

You should not have used that derogatory term to refer to Doug or Tom.

Wedding photographers try to depict, through their artistic efforts, weddings 
as being beautiful events. You previously said that the photographer could be 
required to depict the ceremony as beautiful (and authentic, whatever that may 
mean). I gave that statement a generous interpretation which I could accept, to 
the effect that if she could, contrary to my views, be required to photograph 
the event, then she could not sabotage the depiction of the event, could not 
set out to make it seem that the parties did not care for each other, and would 
have to use appropriate technical skills (regular camera equipment, correcting 
for red-eye, etc.). Now you seem to say that the photographer must make the 
same effort to create beauty (whether or not successful) that the photographer 
would make with regard to other ceremonies. That is a demand that the 
photographer attempt to depict the ceremony (to the extent possible) as a 
beautiful thing, which violates the photographer’s right not to express the 
government’s view or anyone else’s view of that which is beautiful. The right 
to have one’s own beliefs as to the good, the true, and the beautiful – and the 
right to refrain from expressing anyone else’s beliefs – is a central component 
of freedom.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Sunday, April 05, 2015 1:58 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

Mark:

O'Brien fits any attempt to apply free speech principles to regulation of 
conduct that has non-communicative elements.  You can love the Lord, but you 
cannot spray paint that on the side of my house.  You can despise inter-faith 
marriage, but (if you are covered by public accommodations law), you cannot 
refuse to serve an inter-faith couple.  Of course the state cannot compel you 
to create beauty -- most of us are incapable of that.  But if you offer to 
create beauty for the general public, you can be held to an obligation to do so 
without discrimination.  I'm willing to consider taking photographers out from 
under that entire regime.  And still, I get insulted by you?  You are being the 
hothead.

Tom and Doug have written letters to a dozen or more state legislators seeking 
these exemptions or seeking RFRA's -- they have political motivations.  I write 
opposing letters, and I have political motivations.  I have seen at least one 
such letter, which you signed, that contained a factual assertion that I 
strongly believe is an untruth.  I called that to the attention of the 
signatories, but not to the list.  Please don't tempt me further to make that 
dispute public by being intemperate with me.

I hope you all take up the invitation that Jim and I have now proffered to 
discuss the non-profit situation.  The commercial vendor context is just too 
loaded with polarized views and quick triggers to anger, at least for me, so 
I'm out of it unless you insult me further.

Chip

On Sun, Apr 5, 2015 at 4:21 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
I am astonished and dismayed that Chip says the First Amendment allows the 
State to require a person to create art that depicts beauty. The authoritarian 
spirit arises: So what he says. Principles that get in the way of a preferred 
outcome must be discarded. Perhaps that is too harsh; he says that he is not 
*convinced* that the First Amendment does not provide protection against such 
compelled speech

Chip's accusation that Doug's and Tom's arguments are politically 
self-serving does not deserve a response, and I hope will be rejected by 
fair-minded members of this list.

Of course Chip's invocation of O'Brien would receive a very poor grade on a 
student's paper. Does *Chip* have a political agenda here, or is he perhaps 
just not thinking straight? I hope the latter is the case.

Here the photographer is required by the State to express a message; that was 
not the case in O'Brien. Here the photographer does not refuse to obey the law 
in order to communicate a message; she refuses to engage in an affirmative act 
of communicating a State-mandated message because it violates her religious 
conscience to do so. If an important state interest is sufficient to justify 
the state in compelling speech, then we are in very deeply authoritarian 
trouble. The need for commitment to the security of a nation

RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-06 Thread Graber, Mark
May I suggest that we return to the decorum that has more often than not 
characterized this list.  The best conclusion I can draw from the various 
emails is that the issues are more difficult to many of us than they appear to 
others and that RFRA is the classic example of a statue drawn with some 
examples in mind that is now being applied to circumstances some people claim 
is nearly identical to the original paradigm cases and some think is quite 
different.

MAG

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-06 Thread Ira Lupu
 wrote, a typical definition of “self-serving” is

“Serving one's own interests often in disregard of the truth or the
interests of others.”

​So, yes, I accused Doug, Tom, you, and every other signatory of that
letter of being self-serving.  You wanted Indiana to enact the RFRA, and
you wanted to pre-empt criticism that RFRA's may cause harm to others (in
Hobby Lobby, an ongoing and continuing harm to many others.) And so you
disregarded the truth and the interests of others.

I invite others on the list to read your entire letter and make their own
determinations of whether my criticism is apt.

Chip ​


On Mon, Apr 6, 2015 at 3:06 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 Chip:



 I don’t take kindly to threats. Say what you want to say, or don’t.



 O’Brien doesn’t apply here, and no one is talking about spray painting
 anyone’s house.



 A typical definition of “self-serving” is



 “Serving one's own interests often in disregard of the truth or the
 interests of others.”



 http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/self-serving.



 You should not have used that derogatory term to refer to Doug or Tom.



 Wedding photographers try to depict, through their artistic efforts,
 weddings as being beautiful events. You previously said that the
 photographer could be required to depict the ceremony as beautiful (and
 authentic, whatever that may mean). I gave that statement a generous
 interpretation which I could accept, to the effect that if she could,
 contrary to my views, be required to photograph the event, then she could
 not sabotage the depiction of the event, could not set out to make it seem
 that the parties did not care for each other, and would have to use
 appropriate technical skills (regular camera equipment, correcting for
 red-eye, etc.). Now you seem to say that the photographer must make the
 same effort to create beauty (whether or not successful) that the
 photographer would make with regard to other ceremonies. That is a demand
 that the photographer attempt to depict the ceremony (to the extent
 possible) as a beautiful thing, which violates the photographer’s right not
 to express the government’s view or anyone else’s view of that which is
 beautiful. The right to have one’s own beliefs as to the good, the true,
 and the beautiful – and the right to refrain from expressing anyone else’s
 beliefs – is a central component of freedom.



 Mark



 Mark S. Scarberry

 Professor of Law

 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law





 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Ira Lupu
 *Sent:* Sunday, April 05, 2015 1:58 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 Mark:



 O'Brien fits any attempt to apply free speech principles to regulation of
 conduct that has non-communicative elements.  You can love the Lord, but
 you cannot spray paint that on the side of my house.  You can despise
 inter-faith marriage, but (if you are covered by public accommodations
 law), you cannot refuse to serve an inter-faith couple.  Of course the
 state cannot compel you to create beauty -- most of us are incapable of
 that.  But if you offer to create beauty for the general public, you can be
 held to an obligation to do so without discrimination.  I'm willing to
 consider taking photographers out from under that entire regime.  And
 still, I get insulted by you?  You are being the hothead.



 Tom and Doug have written letters to a dozen or more state legislators
 seeking these exemptions or seeking RFRA's -- they have political
 motivations.  I write opposing letters, and I have political motivations.
 I have seen at least one such letter, which you signed, that contained a
 factual assertion that I strongly believe is an untruth.  I called that to
 the attention of the signatories, but not to the list.  Please don't tempt
 me further to make that dispute public by being intemperate with me.



 I hope you all take up the invitation that Jim and I have now proffered to
 discuss the non-profit situation.  The commercial vendor context is just
 too loaded with polarized views and quick triggers to anger, at least for
 me, so I'm out of it unless you insult me further.



 Chip



 On Sun, Apr 5, 2015 at 4:21 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 I am astonished and dismayed that Chip says the First Amendment allows the
 State to require a person to create art that depicts beauty. The
 authoritarian spirit arises: So what he says. Principles that get in the
 way of a preferred outcome must be discarded. Perhaps that is too harsh; he
 says that he is not *convinced* that the First Amendment does not provide
 protection against such compelled speech



 Chip's accusation that Doug's and Tom's arguments are politically
 self-serving does not deserve a response, and I hope will be rejected by
 fair-minded members of this list

FW: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-06 Thread Doug Laycock
The alleged inaccuracy is a transitional issue that does not affect the basic 
point. And if the Court were to eventually strike down the non-profit solution, 
which I think quite unlikely, that would not be Hobby Lobby. That would be a 
decision that goes well beyond Hobby Lobby.

 

The Third, Sixth, Seventh, and DC Circuits have rejected challenges to the 
non-profit solution. Has any court of appeals struck it down? And given 
Kennedy’s concurrence in Hobby Lobby, I think it quite unlikely that he would 
vote to strike it down.

 

I assume that some of the sixteen signers of the letter supporting RFRA would 
also support the challenges to the non-profit solution; I have not polled them. 
At least one, and I think two signers, think that Hobby Lobby was wrongly 
decided but that we accurately described it. Speaking only for myself, I think 
that Hobby Lobby was rightly decided, and that the objections to the non-profit 
solution should be rejected, as they have been at the appellate level. 

 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu  
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Monday, April 06, 2015 5:57 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

 

Mark:

 

I don't take kindly to insults to my legal acumen (Chip's invocation of 
O'Brien would receive a very poor grade on a student's paper.), or the clarity 
of my thinking (is he perhaps just not thinking straight?).  FWIW, I note that 
the brief in opposition to certiorari in Elane Photography cited O'Brien, 
though it did not rely substantially on that case. The New Mexico Supreme Court 
rejected the compelled speech claim, and SCOTUS denied cert,, so the idea that 
my view of the case involves some Orwellian tyranny does seem a little 
far-fetched.  Still, as I have said in many posts, reasonable scholars can 
differ on the compelled speech issues, and exempting photographers from public 
accommodations law (rather than adjudicating artistic content, case by case, 
for all vendors) is an idea worth considering.

 

But, most of all, I do my best to speak and write, as a scholar, lawyer, and 
citizen, with honesty and integrity. 

 

​Sixteen scholars, including you, Doug Laycock, Tom Berg, and many other 
members of this list​, prepared and signed a letter to the Indiana Senate 
Judiciary Committee about Indiana's proposed RFRA.  The full letter, dated 
2/3/15 is available here: 

http://www.faithlafayette.org/uploads/Church/LetterSupportingReligiousFreedomRestoration.pdf

​.

The letter, anticipating correctly that opponents of the Indiana Bill would 
rely on the Supreme Court's decision in Hobby Lobby as evidence that RFRA's can 
cause harm to employees and others, devoted several paragraphs to discussing 
Hobby Lobby.  If Hobby Lobby had been a win-win situation (or even a win -- no 
loss situation) as the Court had suggested and Doug Laycock had often 
characterized it, religious liberty would have been protected and no one would 
have been harmed.

But, the story of Hobby Lobby and all the other challenges to the contraceptive 
mandate, as applied to for-profits, is one of continuing harm to female 
employees and female dependents (of child-bearing age) of all employees.  In 
these cases, the challenged coverages have not been provided to employees.  In 
some, like Hobby Lobby, the challenged contraceptives included emergency 
contraceptives and IUD's (the most effective and expensive contraceptive 
device). In other cases, like Gilardi v. HHS (DC Cir.), the employer challenged 
coverage of all contraceptives.  To the best of my knowledge, the employees of 
these challengers are without the challenged coverages.  (I'm happy to be 
corrected if I'm wrong about any of these employers.)

The Obama Administration has proposed extending the non-profit accommodation to 
for-profits, but has not made that policy final.  When it does, RFRA challenges 
are likely, and RFRA challenges remain very much alive with respect to that 
accommodation as applied to non-profits.  So thousands of women have been 
denied contraceptive coverage, partial or complete, by the Hobby Lobby decision 
and fall-out from it.  There is no guarantee they will ever get that coverage, 
and it won't be retroactive even if they do. They are suffering continuing 
harm, and it may go on for a long time.

Nevertheless, your letter included the following: 

the key to the Court’s decision was that the owners could be exempted from the 
regulation without affecting their female employees’ access to contraception. 
The Court, in other words, found a win-win solution. The owners got to follow 
their religious beliefs; their female employees got the contraception they 
needed

RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-06 Thread Scarberry, Mark
In line with Mark's suggestion, let me apologize to Chip for using such strong 
language to describe what I believe is an error in his analysis. I think I 
adequately explained why reliance on O'Brien is, in my opinion, clearly wrong 
in this case. List members can reach their own conclusions. Again let me 
apologize for using such strong language.

I continue to believe that requiring people to create art that sends a 
state-mandated message is more than troubling. Such a power in the state, if 
generalized, will eventually lead to a broader authoritarian result that few of 
us on this list - probably none - will like. I specifically said that Chip 
would not favor such an authoritarian result. 

With regard to the letter, I will add only a few comments to Doug's.

The Supreme Court did copy the non-profit accommodation in the relevant sense, 
as did Justice Kennedy in his concurrence: [T]here is an existing, recognized, 
workable, and already-implemented framework to provide coverage. I think it 
was clear that the Court was requiring the administration to give the same 
accommodation to Hobby Lobby and the Greens. It was also clear, I think, that 
the administration had not yet implemented it, else there would have been no 
need for the Court to rule against the administration. 

I would have hoped that there might be more voices from those on the other side 
of this issue to temper the overstatements made by politicians and commentators 
with regard to the likely effect of a state RFRA. 

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Graber, Mark
Sent: Monday, April 06, 2015 3:48 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

May I suggest that we return to the decorum that has more often than not 
characterized this list.  The best conclusion I can draw from the various 
emails is that the issues are more difficult to many of us than they appear to 
others and that RFRA is the classic example of a statue drawn with some 
examples in mind that is now being applied to circumstances some people claim 
is nearly identical to the original paradigm cases and some think is quite 
different.

MAG

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, unsubscribe, 
change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: FW: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-06 Thread Marty Lederman
Thanks for that clarification, Doug.  Could you please offer greater detail
about why you think the courts should *reject *the RFRA objections to the
nonprofit compromise?  On substantial burden grounds?  Compelling
interest/no less restrictive alternative?

On Mon, Apr 6, 2015 at 6:37 PM, Doug Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:

 The alleged inaccuracy is a transitional issue that does not affect the
 basic point. And if the Court were to eventually strike down the non-profit
 solution, which I think quite unlikely, that would not be *Hobby Lobby*.
 That would be a decision that goes well beyond *Hobby Lobby*.



 The Third, Sixth, Seventh, and DC Circuits have rejected challenges to the
 non-profit solution. Has any court of appeals struck it down? And given
 Kennedy’s concurrence in *Hobby Lobby*, I think it quite unlikely that he
 would vote to strike it down.



 I assume that some of the sixteen signers of the letter supporting RFRA
 would also support the challenges to the non-profit solution; I have not
 polled them. At least one, and I think two signers, think that *Hobby
 Lobby* was wrongly decided but that we accurately described it. Speaking
 only for myself, I think that *Hobby Lobby* was rightly decided, and that
 the objections to the non-profit solution should be rejected, as they have
 been at the appellate level.





 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546



 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [
 mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Ira Lupu
 *Sent:* Monday, April 06, 2015 5:57 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 Mark:



 I don't take kindly to insults to my legal acumen (Chip's invocation of
 O'Brien would receive a very poor grade on a student's paper.), or the
 clarity of my thinking (is he perhaps just not thinking straight?).  FWIW,
 I note that the brief in opposition to certiorari in Elane Photography
 cited O'Brien, though it did not rely substantially on that case. The New
 Mexico Supreme Court rejected the compelled speech claim, and SCOTUS denied
 cert,, so the idea that my view of the case involves some Orwellian tyranny
 does seem a little far-fetched.  Still, as I have said in many posts,
 reasonable scholars can differ on the compelled speech issues, and
 exempting photographers from public accommodations law (rather than
 adjudicating artistic content, case by case, for all vendors) is an idea
 worth considering.



 But, most of all, I do my best to speak and write, as a scholar, lawyer,
 and citizen, with honesty and integrity.



 ​Sixteen scholars, including you, Doug Laycock, Tom Berg, and many other
 members of this list​, prepared and signed a letter to the Indiana Senate
 Judiciary Committee about Indiana's proposed RFRA.  The full letter, dated
 2/3/15 is available here:


 http://www.faithlafayette.org/uploads/Church/LetterSupportingReligiousFreedomRestoration.pdf

 ​.

 The letter, anticipating correctly that opponents of the Indiana Bill
 would rely on the Supreme Court's decision in Hobby Lobby as evidence that
 RFRA's can cause harm to employees and others, devoted several paragraphs
 to discussing Hobby Lobby.  If Hobby Lobby had been a win-win situation (or
 even a win -- no loss situation) as the Court had suggested and Doug
 Laycock had often characterized it, religious liberty would have been
 protected and no one would have been harmed.

 But, the story of Hobby Lobby and all the other challenges to the
 contraceptive mandate, as applied to for-profits, is one of continuing harm
 to female employees and female dependents (of child-bearing age) of all
 employees.  In these cases, the challenged coverages have not been provided
 to employees.  In some, like Hobby Lobby, the challenged contraceptives
 included emergency contraceptives and IUD's (the most effective and
 expensive contraceptive device). In other cases, like Gilardi v. HHS (DC
 Cir.), the employer challenged coverage of all contraceptives.  To the best
 of my knowledge, the employees of these challengers are without the
 challenged coverages.  (I'm happy to be corrected if I'm wrong about any of
 these employers.)

 The Obama Administration has proposed extending the non-profit
 accommodation to for-profits, but has not made that policy final.  When it
 does, RFRA challenges are likely, and RFRA challenges remain very much
 alive with respect to that accommodation as applied to non-profits.  So
 thousands of women have been denied contraceptive coverage, partial or
 complete, by the Hobby Lobby decision and fall-out from it.  There is no
 guarantee they will ever get that coverage, and it won't be retroactive
 even if they do. They are suffering continuing harm, and it may go on for a
 long time.

 Nevertheless

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-06 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
If one treats the issue as state mandated art (in the absence of conditional 
funding, at least), I agree with Mark S. Am I correct in assuming that Mark's 
caveat doesn't apply to the wedding cake, at least if we're talking about off 
the rack cakes?  I assume also this wouldn't apply to the caterers or tent 
rentals etc.  And do we have to decide who is a genuine artist?  Imagine a 
caricaturist who often draws pictures of wedding guests as amusing souvenirs. 
Would she be able to decline the offer of employment? 

If all of this intense and acrimonious discussion boils down to a few wedding 
photographers, I'm inclined to say that we who support same-sex marriage can 
afford to be magnanimous in what has clearly become our victory. But am I 
correct in this presumption?

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

 On Apr 6, 2015, at 6:38 PM, Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu 
 wrote:
 
 In line with Mark's suggestion, let me apologize to Chip for using such 
 strong language to describe what I believe is an error in his analysis. I 
 think I adequately explained why reliance on O'Brien is, in my opinion, 
 clearly wrong in this case. List members can reach their own conclusions. 
 Again let me apologize for using such strong language.
 
 I continue to believe that requiring people to create art that sends a 
 state-mandated message is more than troubling. Such a power in the state, if 
 generalized, will eventually lead to a broader authoritarian result that few 
 of us on this list - probably none - will like. I specifically said that Chip 
 would not favor such an authoritarian result. 
 
 With regard to the letter, I will add only a few comments to Doug's.
 
 The Supreme Court did copy the non-profit accommodation in the relevant 
 sense, as did Justice Kennedy in his concurrence: [T]here is an existing, 
 recognized, workable, and already-implemented framework to provide coverage. 
 I think it was clear that the Court was requiring the administration to give 
 the same accommodation to Hobby Lobby and the Greens. It was also clear, I 
 think, that the administration had not yet implemented it, else there would 
 have been no need for the Court to rule against the administration. 
 
 I would have hoped that there might be more voices from those on the other 
 side of this issue to temper the overstatements made by politicians and 
 commentators with regard to the likely effect of a state RFRA. 
 
 Mark
 
 Mark S. Scarberry
 Professor of Law
 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
 
 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Graber, Mark
 Sent: Monday, April 06, 2015 3:48 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights
 
 May I suggest that we return to the decorum that has more often than not 
 characterized this list.  The best conclusion I can draw from the various 
 emails is that the issues are more difficult to many of us than they appear 
 to others and that RFRA is the classic example of a statue drawn with some 
 examples in mind that is now being applied to circumstances some people claim 
 is nearly identical to the original paradigm cases and some think is quite 
 different.
 
 MAG
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, 
 unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-06 Thread Hillel Y. Levin
. Such a power in the state,
 if generalized, will eventually lead to a broader authoritarian result that
 few of us on this list - probably none - will like. I specifically said
 that Chip would not favor such an authoritarian result.
 
  With regard to the letter, I will add only a few comments to Doug's.
 
  The Supreme Court did copy the non-profit accommodation in the relevant
 sense, as did Justice Kennedy in his concurrence: [T]here is an existing,
 recognized, workable, and already-implemented framework to provide
 coverage. I think it was clear that the Court was requiring the
 administration to give the same accommodation to Hobby Lobby and the
 Greens. It was also clear, I think, that the administration had not yet
 implemented it, else there would have been no need for the Court to rule
 against the administration.
 
  I would have hoped that there might be more voices from those on the
 other side of this issue to temper the overstatements made by politicians
 and commentators with regard to the likely effect of a state RFRA.
 
  Mark
 
  Mark S. Scarberry
  Professor of Law
  Pepperdine Univ. School of Law
 
  -Original Message-
  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu javascript:; [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu javascript:;] On Behalf Of Graber,
 Mark
  Sent: Monday, April 06, 2015 3:48 PM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights
 
  May I suggest that we return to the decorum that has more often than not
 characterized this list.  The best conclusion I can draw from the various
 emails is that the issues are more difficult to many of us than they appear
 to others and that RFRA is the classic example of a statue drawn with some
 examples in mind that is now being applied to circumstances some people
 claim is nearly identical to the original paradigm cases and some think is
 quite different.
 
  MAG
 
  ___
  To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu javascript:; To
 subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
  Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.
  ___
  To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu javascript:;
  To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
  Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu javascript:;
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.



-- 
Hillel Y. Levin
Associate Professor
University of Georgia
School of Law
120 Herty Dr.
Athens, GA 30602
(678) 641-7452
hle...@uga.edu
hillelle...@gmail.com
SSRN Author Page:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=466645
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-06 Thread Alan E Brownstein
 reliance on O'Brien is, in my opinion, 
 clearly wrong in this case. List members can reach their own conclusions. 
 Again let me apologize for using such strong language.

 I continue to believe that requiring people to create art that sends a 
 state-mandated message is more than troubling. Such a power in the state, if 
 generalized, will eventually lead to a broader authoritarian result that few 
 of us on this list - probably none - will like. I specifically said that Chip 
 would not favor such an authoritarian result.

 With regard to the letter, I will add only a few comments to Doug's.

 The Supreme Court did copy the non-profit accommodation in the relevant 
 sense, as did Justice Kennedy in his concurrence: [T]here is an existing, 
 recognized, workable, and already-implemented framework to provide coverage. 
 I think it was clear that the Court was requiring the administration to give 
 the same accommodation to Hobby Lobby and the Greens. It was also clear, I 
 think, that the administration had not yet implemented it, else there would 
 have been no need for the Court to rule against the administration.

 I would have hoped that there might be more voices from those on the other 
 side of this issue to temper the overstatements made by politicians and 
 commentators with regard to the likely effect of a state RFRA.

 Mark

 Mark S. Scarberry
 Professor of Law
 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edujavascript:; 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edujavascript:;] On Behalf Of 
 Graber, Mark
 Sent: Monday, April 06, 2015 3:48 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

 May I suggest that we return to the decorum that has more often than not 
 characterized this list.  The best conclusion I can draw from the various 
 emails is that the issues are more difficult to many of us than they appear 
 to others and that RFRA is the classic example of a statue drawn with some 
 examples in mind that is now being applied to circumstances some people claim 
 is nearly identical to the original paradigm cases and some think is quite 
 different.

 MAG

 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edujavascript:; To 
 subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edujavascript:;
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edujavascript:;
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


--
Hillel Y. Levin
Associate Professor
University of Georgia
School of Law
120 Herty Dr.
Athens, GA 30602
(678) 641-7452
hle...@uga.edumailto:hle...@uga.edu
hillelle...@gmail.commailto:hillelle...@gmail.com
SSRN Author Page: http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=466645

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward

Re: FW: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-06 Thread Douglas Laycock
Fundamentally for the reason Tom Berg gave in a somewhat later post: this claim 
does not seek merely to exempt the religious objector, but also to prevent 
anyone else from delivering contraception either. I think the claim of burden 
is too attenuated to be substantial, but the attempt to prevent others from 
delivering contraception turns it into more of a clear line and not just an 
assessment of attenuation.

And as I think Posner was the first to point out: the employer sending the 
notice does not trigger the insurer's obligation to provide contraception. The 
insurer already has that obligation, in all its plans. The employer's notice 
triggers only the obligation to remove contraception from the employer's plan, 
and to provide it outside the plan instead of inside.

And I would be quite content with a holding that there is a compelling interest 
in having somebody provide contraception. That is quite different from a claim 
of compelling interest in requiring the religious objector to do it.
 

 

On Mon, 6 Apr 2015 18:53:50 -0400
 Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
Thanks for that clarification, Doug.  Could you please offer greater detail
about why you think the courts should *reject *the RFRA objections to the
nonprofit compromise?  On substantial burden grounds?  Compelling
interest/no less restrictive alternative?

On Mon, Apr 6, 2015 at 6:37 PM, Doug Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:

 The alleged inaccuracy is a transitional issue that does not affect the
 basic point. And if the Court were to eventually strike down the non-profit
 solution, which I think quite unlikely, that would not be *Hobby Lobby*.
 That would be a decision that goes well beyond *Hobby Lobby*.



 The Third, Sixth, Seventh, and DC Circuits have rejected challenges to the
 non-profit solution. Has any court of appeals struck it down? And given
 Kennedy’s concurrence in *Hobby Lobby*, I think it quite unlikely that he
 would vote to strike it down.



 I assume that some of the sixteen signers of the letter supporting RFRA
 would also support the challenges to the non-profit solution; I have not
 polled them. At least one, and I think two signers, think that *Hobby
 Lobby* was wrongly decided but that we accurately described it. Speaking
 only for myself, I think that *Hobby Lobby* was rightly decided, and that
 the objections to the non-profit solution should be rejected, as they have
 been at the appellate level.


Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: FW: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-06 Thread Ira Lupu
I accept Mark's apology.

His point about RFRA critics overstating the potential downside is
precisely met by commenting about how RFRA's friends tend to understate the
potential harmful effects, which include encouraging discrimination as much
as actually legalizing it..  We all know that it is impossible to predict,
with 100% confidence, future RFRA interpretations. Or, as I told a Wa Po
reporter, RFRA's are a Rorschach test, on which everyone can project their
hopes and fears, and cannot be proven wrong until the courts resolve
particular questions (and even the resolutions are fact-specific, so we
don't learn much from RFRA judicial precedents.).  A version of that shows
up in this on-line story:
http://www.washingtonpost.com/blogs/govbeat/wp/2015/04/06/what-everybody-missed-during-the-fight-over-religious-freedom-laws-this-year/

​Doug and Tom just underline my point in their posts about the legality of
the accommodation.  They would both draw the line between Hobby Lobby (a
RFRA violation) and Notre Dame (no violation).  But somewhere 0 and 9
Justices don't agree with that line; even AMK may rule in favor of Notre
Dame.  The other 8 4-4) might say Hobby Lobby and Notre Dame should both
win, or both lose. Perhaps no Justice would draw the line where Tom and
Doug draw it.

This is among the reasons why, in the Symposium that Tom references, I say
religious exemptions under a generic regime, with vague standards, are a
dubious enterprise. ​
http://harvardjlg.com/wp-content/uploads/2015/01/Hobby-Lobby-and-the-Dubious-Enterprise-of-Religious-Exemptions.pdf.
I also say that the Hobby Lobby principle will wither in its strength over
time, the way Sherbert-Yoder-Thomas did on the path to Emp. Div. v. Smith.
But who can possibly be sure about such things?  So it's fine to write to
legislators that a RFRA might produce bad results, though we hope it won't;
or that RFRA will protect only small wedding vendors, and only then when
there are adequate alternatives.  Those are hedged predictions, not
falsehoods about facts on the ground.


On Mon, Apr 6, 2015 at 8:59 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
wrote:

 Fundamentally for the reason Tom Berg gave in a somewhat later post: this
 claim does not seek merely to exempt the religious objector, but also to
 prevent anyone else from delivering contraception either. I think the claim
 of burden is too attenuated to be substantial, but the attempt to prevent
 others from delivering contraception turns it into more of a clear line and
 not just an assessment of attenuation.

 And as I think Posner was the first to point out: the employer sending the
 notice does not trigger the insurer's obligation to provide contraception.
 The insurer already has that obligation, in all its plans. The employer's
 notice triggers only the obligation to remove contraception from the
 employer's plan, and to provide it outside the plan instead of inside.

 And I would be quite content with a holding that there is a compelling
 interest in having somebody provide contraception. That is quite different
 from a claim of compelling interest in requiring the religious objector to
 do it.




 On Mon, 6 Apr 2015 18:53:50 -0400
  Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
 Thanks for that clarification, Doug.  Could you please offer greater
 detail
 about why you think the courts should *reject *the RFRA objections to the
 nonprofit compromise?  On substantial burden grounds?  Compelling
 interest/no less restrictive alternative?
 
 On Mon, Apr 6, 2015 at 6:37 PM, Doug Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu
 wrote:
 
  The alleged inaccuracy is a transitional issue that does not affect the
  basic point. And if the Court were to eventually strike down the
 non-profit
  solution, which I think quite unlikely, that would not be *Hobby Lobby*.
  That would be a decision that goes well beyond *Hobby Lobby*.
 
 
 
  The Third, Sixth, Seventh, and DC Circuits have rejected challenges to
 the
  non-profit solution. Has any court of appeals struck it down? And given
  Kennedy’s concurrence in *Hobby Lobby*, I think it quite unlikely that
 he
  would vote to strike it down.
 
 
 
  I assume that some of the sixteen signers of the letter supporting RFRA
  would also support the challenges to the non-profit solution; I have not
  polled them. At least one, and I think two signers, think that *Hobby
  Lobby* was wrongly decided but that we accurately described it. Speaking
  only for myself, I think that *Hobby Lobby* was rightly decided, and
 that
  the objections to the non-profit solution should be rejected, as they
 have
  been at the appellate level.
 

 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-05 Thread Ira Lupu
Mark:

O'Brien fits any attempt to apply free speech principles to regulation of
conduct that has non-communicative elements.  You can love the Lord, but
you cannot spray paint that on the side of my house.  You can despise
inter-faith marriage, but (if you are covered by public accommodations
law), you cannot refuse to serve an inter-faith couple.  Of course the
state cannot compel you to create beauty -- most of us are incapable of
that.  But if you offer to create beauty for the general public, you can be
held to an obligation to do so without discrimination.  I'm willing to
consider taking photographers out from under that entire regime.  And
still, I get insulted by you?  You are being the hothead.

Tom and Doug have written letters to a dozen or more state legislators
seeking these exemptions or seeking RFRA's -- they have political
motivations.  I write opposing letters, and I have political motivations.
I have seen at least one such letter, which you signed, that contained a
factual assertion that I strongly believe is an untruth.  I called that to
the attention of the signatories, but not to the list.  Please don't tempt
me further to make that dispute public by being intemperate with me.

I hope you all take up the invitation that Jim and I have now proffered to
discuss the non-profit situation.  The commercial vendor context is just
too loaded with polarized views and quick triggers to anger, at least for
me, so I'm out of it unless you insult me further.

Chip

On Sun, Apr 5, 2015 at 4:21 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 I am astonished and dismayed that Chip says the First Amendment allows the
 State to require a person to create art that depicts beauty. The
 authoritarian spirit arises: So what he says. Principles that get in the
 way of a preferred outcome must be discarded. Perhaps that is too harsh; he
 says that he is not *convinced* that the First Amendment does not provide
 protection against such compelled speech

 Chip's accusation that Doug's and Tom's arguments are politically
 self-serving does not deserve a response, and I hope will be rejected by
 fair-minded members of this list.

 Of course Chip's invocation of O'Brien would receive a very poor grade on
 a student's paper. Does *Chip* have a political agenda here, or is he
 perhaps just not thinking straight? I hope the latter is the case.

 Here the photographer is required by the State to express a message; that
 was not the case in O'Brien. Here the photographer does not refuse to obey
 the law in order to communicate a message; she refuses to engage in an
 affirmative act of communicating a State-mandated message because it
 violates her religious conscience to do so. If an important state interest
 is sufficient to justify the state in compelling speech, then we are in
 very deeply authoritarian trouble. The need for commitment to the security
 of a nation is certainly an important state interest.

 Perhaps, then, film-makers can be required to create films celebrating the
 State, portraying the nation as just and good, and portraying its enemies
 as evil; Oceania and Eurasia. Should I be comforted that Chip finds
 regulation of the content of films and newspapers to be much more
 troubling than regulation of food presentations? Perhaps authoritarians
 who regulate media content in the future (fairness doctrine?) will be
 troubled when they do so, but freedom of expression must not stand in the
 way of accomplishing the State's goals.

 Mark

 Mark S. Scarberry
 Pepperdine University School of Law


 Sent from my iPad

 On Apr 5, 2015, at 9:38 AM, Doug Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:

 Chip says:



 “(Cf. the doctors who refuse to provide infertility treatments to lesbian
 couples; those are real cases, not scare hypotheticals.)”



 Well, they’re real cases in the sense that at least one has been
 litigated. It remains the case that the religious objector has never won
 such a case, even when the treatment was offered by a different doc in the
 same medical practice.



 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546



 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [
 mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Ira Lupu
 *Sent:* Sunday, April 05, 2015 10:51 AM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 Mark and I agree on fewer legal premises than he thinks.  Yes, the wedding
 photographer creates art.  And I'm sure that the best wedding caterers,
 planners, florists, and bakers also have artistic elements in their work.
 So what?  Davey O'Brien created political theater when he burned his draft
 card; his actions could be regulated because they threatened legitimate
 state interests (in an orderly selective service system), independent

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-05 Thread Ira Lupu
 comers doesn't raise compelled speech issues. He has much
 less need to express his political and social views in the restaurant to
 avoid becoming the state's mouthpiece, because he isn't being required to
 say anything that would appear to be his own speech. (He could be required
 to post a sign saying that the state requires all customers to be served,
 without respect to race etc., but that would identify the message as coming
 from the state.)

 Nor is Ollie required to be involved personally in the intimate lives of
 his customers, the way a wedding photographer (or wedding planner)
 ordinarily is with the couple. That raises separate free exercise issues in
 the wedding photography case for a photographer who believes it is wrong
 (as a matter of conventional religion or its equivalent per the Seeger
 case) to facilitate a same-sex marriage. And perhaps it creates a hybrid
 rights situation per Smith.

 Of course it's also easier for the state to tell whether Ollie burns the
 food or includes noxious ingredients than it is for the state to determine
 whether a photographer has sufficiently expressed the state's (or the
 clients') views as to beauty and truth. That implicates not only practical
 concerns but also the degree of vagueness of the law and the degree of
 discretion given to officials who would police the photographer's use of
 her First Amendment rights.

 Mark

 Mark S. Scarberry
 Pepperdine University School of Law


 Sent from my iPad

 On Apr 1, 2015, at 6:03 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

 No, I don't think that's OK.  But that's a real compelled speech problem,
 where the student must first utter the Pledge.

 The wedding vendors do not have to say anything approving about the
 marriage, or affirm its validity in the eyes of the state or God.  They do
 have to provide goods and services; in the photographer's case, the
 services include making the wedding look authentic and beautiful, not ugly
 or false.  So the compelled speech concern seems much weaker to me than in
 Barnette.

 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 8:53 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 Apart from the other points with which I disagree:



 Wow, Chip. You really think it’s OK to make the student recite the
 Pledge, as long as the student is permitted at the end to say “I don’t mean
 it”? Can I be required to burn a pinch of incense to the emperor as long as
 I am permitted afterwards to say that the emperor isn’t really a god?



 Mark



 Mark S. Scarberry

 Professor of Law

 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law







 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Ira Lupu
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 5:32 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 If the compelled speech argument is constitutionally sufficient,
 permission to post a disclaiming sign may solve the problem. (It would be
 like letting a student say aloud I don't mean it after forcing her to
 recite the Pledge of Allegiance.)

  [snip]



 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.




-- 
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law, Emeritus
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
Co-author (with Professor Robert Tuttle) of Secular Government, Religious
People ( Wm. B. Eerdmans Pub. Co., 2014))
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-05 Thread Doug Laycock
Chip says: 

 

“(Cf. the doctors who refuse to provide infertility treatments to lesbian 
couples; those are real cases, not scare hypotheticals.)”

 

Well, they’re real cases in the sense that at least one has been litigated. It 
remains the case that the religious objector has never won such a case, even 
when the treatment was offered by a different doc in the same medical practice. 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Sunday, April 05, 2015 10:51 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

 

Mark and I agree on fewer legal premises than he thinks.  Yes, the wedding 
photographer creates art.  And I'm sure that the best wedding caterers, 
planners, florists, and bakers also have artistic elements in their work.  So 
what?  Davey O'Brien created political theater when he burned his draft card; 
his actions could be regulated because they threatened legitimate state 
interests (in an orderly selective service system), independent of their 
communicative content.  

 

I think the concept of hybrid rights is made up hooey.

 

I don't draw lines based on art vs. non-art.  I might draw lines, for free 
speech purposes, based on the communicative character of the business covered 
by public accommodations law.  Regulating the content of newspapers and films 
seems much more troubling than regulating the content of food presentations in 
restaurants.  So I am tempted, but only a little, by Jim Oleske's suggestion on 
this list that certain predominantly communicative trades -- photographer, 
videographer, free lance writer -- be removed from the coverage of public 
accommodations law entirely.  I am not at all convinced that the First A 
doctrines of compelled speech require this, but I can see how First A 
expressive values support this move, if the coverage is narrow. 

 

I strongly disfavor covering these or any other trades with public 
accommodations laws while simultaneously granting exemptions to religious 
objectors, either explicitly or through a RFRA balancing test.  The assurances 
that Tom Berg and Doug Laycock give, that the only successful RFRA defenses to 
discrimination will be in same sex wedding cases, are politically self-serving, 
totally unreliable, and objectionable on their own terms.   If weddings get 
special treatment, then anniversary parties, children's birthdays, etc. may 
follow. (Cf. the doctors who refuse to provide infertility treatments to 
lesbian couples; those are real cases, not scare hypotheticals.)  

 

And who among us knows when other religious exemptions will be sought and 
gained -- re: Muslims, Jews, Hispanics, immigrants from certain places, etc.? 
Today's intense culture war will fade, and tomorrow will bring a new one.  

 

The hardest questions for me, and I don't see a whole lot of discussion on the 
list about these, are the exemptions for religiously affiliated non-profits.  
Are they all ministries, to be left unregulated?  When government funded?  When 
government licensed? These are not merely speculative questions -- see the 
Indiana RFRA fix, and see 

http://www.irfalliance.org/hidden-restriction-on-faith-based-organizations-in-vawa-reauthorization/

​.​

 

On Thu, Apr 2, 2015 at 2:04 PM, Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu 
mailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu  wrote:

Let's see what Chip and I seem to agree on, and then I'll express my strong 
disagreement on one point.

 

We seem to agree that the wedding photographer creates art. It is hard to see 
how visual portrayals of an event can convey a message of beauty and 
authenticity and not be called art. Indeed it would seem to be celebratory art, 
as I've been saying all along, if it deals with beauty and authenticity.

 

We seem to agree that the wedding photographer (if she can be required to 
photograph the same sex ceremony) cannot (as a colleague put it off list) 
sabotage the photography, by intentionally portraying the ceremony as ugly or 
false (in the sense that the two persons are insincere or that the ceremony 
doesn't have whatever legal effect the law provides). I suppose I'd go further 
and say that the photographer has to use the same high-quality equipment that 
she normally would use, has to take photos from the normal angles, and has to 
fix red-eye problems and similar problems before sending the proofs to the 
clients for their selection.

 

I can't agree that the photographer can be required to create visual works that 
portray the ceremony as beautiful (or authentic, if that means posing the 
couple so as to bring out their sincere commitment to each other). The state 
may be able to require her to photograph the ceremony, but it can't require

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-05 Thread Steven Jamar
The benefits of clarity in regulation are that it obviates the need for 
litigation and it allows for compromise among disparate and often competing 
interests as well as allowing for compromise of competing values.  If a law 
specifically exempts a well-defined business or entity, then the very real 
costs of litigation to enforce rights either by the person excluded or by the 
business seeking to exclude  are avoided.  If a law specifically draws a line 
and includes specific examples or a limited exclusive list, then to that extent 
people can understand and predict results without resorting to expensive 
litigation and broad-brush misinterpretation (willful or otherwise).  A law 
exempting from public accommodation laws cake bakers, 
photographers/videographers, and florists would be clear (in many cases at 
least), but would cut too broadly — allowing race discrimination, gender 
discrimination, religious discrimination, and so on.  If the carve-out were 
only for one type of discrimination — sexual orientation — and only for that 
would the public accommodation law not apply, again one might have relative 
clarity and compromise, but, of course, at a social justice cost for some but 
with some accommodation of some who wish to discriminate on that basis.

Enter religious freedom acts (nothing restorative about them, is there, so they 
should be RFAs, not RFRAs).  Now it is all up in the air.  A broad exemption is 
enacted with no clarity, no predictability, and endless opportunity for 
mischief from both sides and endless possibilities for interpretation.  And all 
the comcomitant social costs and litigation costs.  The state RFA approach 
allows the public accommodation to discriminate on the basis of sexual 
orientation and puts the burden on the victim to sue — which is time consuming 
and taxing financially, socially, and emotionally.  And it then puts the 
business owner to having to defend the action on a fact-specific, 
individual-specific basis of convincing a judge and jury that the actions were 
justified by a religious exercise being substantially burdened.  Well, Hobby 
Lobby made this easy — just claim complicity with evil as your burden and 
you’re home.   Then the burden shifts to the victim — and not the state — to 
show the compelling state interest and least restrictive alternative.  So would 
now the state need to be impleded as a necessary party for complete 
adjudication?  Or would it intervene?

The Indiana sort of RFA carve-out is fraught with problems that a specific 
provision is not.  If the desire is to discriminate against someone on the 
basis of their sexual orientation in some businesses, carve out those 
businesses.  Most will not discriminate either because they don’t feel the 
desire to do so or because they see little point in excluding 10% of their 
possible business clients.  It takes religion out of the equation.

But to some, this paints too broadly and so some who migh accept some carve out 
push it back to religiously-based motivations — but that creates all the 
problems noted above.

In the end, this is another manifestation of the fight between liberty as 
license and equality as inclusion.  Equality and liberty can often be mutually 
supportive at least for some — requiring non-discrimination in employment on 
the basis of race is premised on equality — but makes the historically excluded 
group more included and thus able to exercise liberty more — they have more 
options, more choices, more liberty.

But a cost of any such regulation is a reduction in choice and liberty for 
some.  Same is true for zoning ordinances, environmental regulations, OSHA, and 
so much more — they all limit the liberty of the person who must comply with 
them.  

Hence the concept of “ordered liberty.”  Liberty does not equal license.  And 
never has.  The fact that many people dislike the change wrought by the 
Reconstruction Amendments to bring equality into the constitution at some cost 
to liberty to discriminate against historically excluded and marginalized 
groups does not invalidate the dramatic change those amendments brought about.

Including those who are LGBT favors the equality principle and gives them more 
liberty.  But it does cost some liberty to those who would continue to exclude 
them — for any reason, including religious beliefs.

Do you favor equality as inclusion or liberty as license?  Or some compromise, 
uncomfortable as they can be, between the two?

As I argued about 20 years ago, we should recognize the legitimacy of the 
restrictions on religious exercise as well as the legitimacy of claims premised 
on religious exercise and reach principled compromises whenever possible.  And 
when that doesn’t work — sometimes the principles are not sufficient to reach a 
principled compromise, unless the principle itself is compromise between two 
first-order concepts like liberty and equality, then simple pragmatism should 
rule.

But such is not the world we 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-05 Thread James Oleske
When asked about the Indiana RFRA on Meet the Press today, Gov. Jindal said
the following:

Let's remember what this debate was originally all about.  This is about
business owners that don't wanna have to choose between their Christian
faith, their sincerely held religious beliefs, and being able to operate
their businesses. Now, what they don't want is the government to force them
to participate in wedding ceremonies that contradict their beliefs.

http://www.nola.com/politics/index.ssf/2015/04/bobby_jindal_religious_freedom.html

Longtime advocates of RFRAs would understandably object to this
characterization as ignoring all the many less-controversial religious
liberty claims that originally motivated the push for RFRAs, but in terms
of the political impetus for the new state RFRAs, Gov. Jindal is
undoubtedly correct as to what the debate is all about.

Accordingly, it seems appropriate that the coming debate in Louisiana won't
be about a new RFRA or new RFRA amendment (like those considered in Indiana
and Arizona) that would leave the answer to the wedding vendor cases
unclear and subject to future judicial balancing. Rather, the coming debate
in Louisiana will be over proposed legislation (introduced Friday) that
would clearly give businesses the right to refuse marriage-related services
and benefits to same-sex couples.

Bill:
http://www.nola.com/politics/index.ssf/2015/04/louisiana_religious_freedom_bi.html
Story about the Bill (in which Doug is quoted):
http://www.nola.com/politics/index.ssf/2015/04/religious_freedom_fight_headed.html

The Louisiana bill would, in Steve's words below, have the benefits of
clarity, but it would likely cut too broadly even for many who support
carve-outs from antidiscrimination laws in the same-sex marriage context,
as the language of the proposal would allow vendors to refuse service to
interracial couples, interfaith couples, couples involving divorced
individuals, or any other type of couple to which there is a religious
objection.

The legislation closely mirrors the proposed Marriage and Religious Freedom
Act that was introduced in the last Congress and was sponsored by 103
Representatives and 17 Senators. It is also similar to an exemption
proposal first offered by a group of law professors in 2009, although that
group subsequently modified its proposal to limit it to small businesses
and include a hardship exemption that would require services to be provided
when no other business was available to provide them. The group has also
suggested that states could make a race exception to the religious
exemption if they are concerned about the exemption allowing discrimination
against interracial couples. (The Louisiana proposal, like its federal
counterpart, begins with the following finding: Leading legal scholars
concur that conflicts between religious liberty and changing ideas about
the institution of marriage are very real, rapidly increasing, and should
be addressed by legislation.) (note: the federal version explicitly says
same-sex marriage in this finding, rather than changing ideas about the
institution of marriage).

I have argued that exemptions designed to allow businesses to refuse
services and benefits to same-sex couples, such as the exemption proposed
in Louisiana (and previously, in Oklahoma, Oregon, Washington, Minnesota,
Kansas, South Dakota, Tennessee, and the U.S. Congress), would be
vulnerable to challenge under the Equal Protection Clause. Others have
argued that they would be vulnerable to Establishment Clause challenge. I
suspect both arguments, however, would be strongly disputed by proponents
of the exemptions.

- Jim

On Sun, Apr 5, 2015 at 10:45 AM, Steven Jamar stevenja...@gmail.com wrote:

 The benefits of clarity in regulation are that it obviates the need for
 litigation and it allows for compromise among disparate and often competing
 interests as well as allowing for compromise of competing values.  If a law
 specifically exempts a well-defined business or entity, then the very real
 costs of litigation to enforce rights either by the person excluded or by
 the business seeking to exclude  are avoided.  If a law specifically draws
 a line and includes specific examples or a limited exclusive list, then to
 that extent people can understand and predict results without resorting to
 expensive litigation and broad-brush misinterpretation (willful or
 otherwise).  A law exempting from public accommodation laws cake bakers,
 photographers/videographers, and florists would be clear (in many cases at
 least), but would cut too broadly — allowing race discrimination, gender
 discrimination, religious discrimination, and so on.  If the carve-out were
 only for one type of discrimination — sexual orientation — and only for
 that would the public accommodation law not apply, again one might have
 relative clarity and compromise, but, of course, at a social justice cost
 for some but with some accommodation of some who wish to discriminate 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-05 Thread K Chen
And who among us knows when other religious exemptions will be sought and
gained -- re: Muslims, Jews, Hispanics, immigrants from certain places,
etc.? Today's intense culture war will fade, and tomorrow will bring a new
one.

Well yeah. That's a fine argument going the other way too. *Today* RFRA is
a fight between a conservative religiosocial movement  that is
simultaneously powerful and waning, simultaneously honored and roundly
hated versus a band of sympathetic minorities and their comfortably
righteous allies. *Today *the conservative religiosocial movement is in
favor of a vision of religious liberty that serves their momentary
reactionary goals. *Today* limited-use public forums are used by locally
powerful religions to spray religious patina on the state. *Today* the
vagaries and impossibilities in religious liberty law cast a shadow that
favors discrimination. But the law isn't (just) about today any more than
appellate decisions are (just) about the case in front of them. *Tomorrow* that
limited-use public forum will allow a Muslim student to speak the pledge
of allegiance in Arabic and the day after that a dozen more Muslim students
will do the same. (Already nearly happened in upstate new york) *Tomorrow* it
will be the Quaker failing to resist the draft under a RFRA claim and the
day after that it will be that Quaker on national TV making a passionate
case for pacifism in a country convinced that war is the only option.
*Tomorrow* it will be the social issue we're all blinkered on and can't
possibly anticipate, and a lone unpopular voice offending and protecting us
all.

Or maybe it won't, but it's the only shot we've got. Power will always find
a way to take advantage of any system. Power will always make things
unequal. Power will always discard simple pragmatism for maximizing
first-order principles. No conceivable system of laws will rescue a morally
acceptable number of minorities from the tyranny of the majority, because
the morally acceptable number is zero.

History has proved that RFRA was a ticking time bomb, but history is also
rife with repeated examples of other ticking time bomb enactments with no
clarity, no predictability, and endless opportunity for mischief from both
sides and endless possibilities for interpretation being the only thing
that held things together. Say, The Bill of Rights for example. The
Fourteenth Amendment. The ICC. Probably how most of us have to keep the
peace at the dinner table. On some level, we're just going to have to
accept this too shall pass and leave tools so someone, somewhere will be
able to make things better. And that's a fight as much about tea-reading as
it is noble first-order principles.

Kevin Chen

On Sun, Apr 5, 2015 at 1:45 PM, Steven Jamar stevenja...@gmail.com wrote:

 The benefits of clarity in regulation are that it obviates the need for
 litigation and it allows for compromise among disparate and often competing
 interests as well as allowing for compromise of competing values.  If a law
 specifically exempts a well-defined business or entity, then the very real
 costs of litigation to enforce rights either by the person excluded or by
 the business seeking to exclude  are avoided.  If a law specifically draws
 a line and includes specific examples or a limited exclusive list, then to
 that extent people can understand and predict results without resorting to
 expensive litigation and broad-brush misinterpretation (willful or
 otherwise).  A law exempting from public accommodation laws cake bakers,
 photographers/videographers, and florists would be clear (in many cases at
 least), but would cut too broadly — allowing race discrimination, gender
 discrimination, religious discrimination, and so on.  If the carve-out were
 only for one type of discrimination — sexual orientation — and only for
 that would the public accommodation law not apply, again one might have
 relative clarity and compromise, but, of course, at a social justice cost
 for some but with some accommodation of some who wish to discriminate on
 that basis.

 Enter religious freedom acts (nothing restorative about them, is there, so
 they should be RFAs, not RFRAs).  Now it is all up in the air.  A broad
 exemption is enacted with no clarity, no predictability, and endless
 opportunity for mischief from both sides and endless possibilities for
 interpretation.  And all the comcomitant social costs and litigation
 costs.  The state RFA approach allows the public accommodation to
 discriminate on the basis of sexual orientation and puts the burden on the
 victim to sue — which is time consuming and taxing financially, socially,
 and emotionally.  And it then puts the business owner to having to defend
 the action on a fact-specific, individual-specific basis of convincing a
 judge and jury that the actions were justified by a religious exercise
 being substantially burdened.  Well, Hobby Lobby made this easy — just
 claim complicity with evil as your burden and 

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-05 Thread Scarberry, Mark
I am astonished and dismayed that Chip says the First Amendment allows the 
State to require a person to create art that depicts beauty. The authoritarian 
spirit arises: So what he says. Principles that get in the way of a preferred 
outcome must be discarded. Perhaps that is too harsh; he says that he is not 
*convinced* that the First Amendment does not provide protection against such 
compelled speech

Chip's accusation that Doug's and Tom's arguments are politically 
self-serving does not deserve a response, and I hope will be rejected by 
fair-minded members of this list.

Of course Chip's invocation of O'Brien would receive a very poor grade on a 
student's paper. Does *Chip* have a political agenda here, or is he perhaps 
just not thinking straight? I hope the latter is the case.

Here the photographer is required by the State to express a message; that was 
not the case in O'Brien. Here the photographer does not refuse to obey the law 
in order to communicate a message; she refuses to engage in an affirmative act 
of communicating a State-mandated message because it violates her religious 
conscience to do so. If an important state interest is sufficient to justify 
the state in compelling speech, then we are in very deeply authoritarian 
trouble. The need for commitment to the security of a nation is certainly an 
important state interest.

Perhaps, then, film-makers can be required to create films celebrating the 
State, portraying the nation as just and good, and portraying its enemies as 
evil; Oceania and Eurasia. Should I be comforted that Chip finds regulation of 
the content of films and newspapers to be much more troubling than regulation 
of food presentations? Perhaps authoritarians who regulate media content in the 
future (fairness doctrine?) will be troubled when they do so, but freedom of 
expression must not stand in the way of accomplishing the State's goals.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine University School of Law


Sent from my iPad

On Apr 5, 2015, at 9:38 AM, Doug Laycock 
dlayc...@virginia.edumailto:dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:

Chip says:

“(Cf. the doctors who refuse to provide infertility treatments to lesbian 
couples; those are real cases, not scare hypotheticals.)”

Well, they’re real cases in the sense that at least one has been litigated. It 
remains the case that the religious objector has never won such a case, even 
when the treatment was offered by a different doc in the same medical practice.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Sunday, April 05, 2015 10:51 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

Mark and I agree on fewer legal premises than he thinks.  Yes, the wedding 
photographer creates art.  And I'm sure that the best wedding caterers, 
planners, florists, and bakers also have artistic elements in their work.  So 
what?  Davey O'Brien created political theater when he burned his draft card; 
his actions could be regulated because they threatened legitimate state 
interests (in an orderly selective service system), independent of their 
communicative content.

I think the concept of hybrid rights is made up hooey.

I don't draw lines based on art vs. non-art.  I might draw lines, for free 
speech purposes, based on the communicative character of the business covered 
by public accommodations law.  Regulating the content of newspapers and films 
seems much more troubling than regulating the content of food presentations in 
restaurants.  So I am tempted, but only a little, by Jim Oleske's suggestion on 
this list that certain predominantly communicative trades -- photographer, 
videographer, free lance writer -- be removed from the coverage of public 
accommodations law entirely.  I am not at all convinced that the First A 
doctrines of compelled speech require this, but I can see how First A 
expressive values support this move, if the coverage is narrow.

I strongly disfavor covering these or any other trades with public 
accommodations laws while simultaneously granting exemptions to religious 
objectors, either explicitly or through a RFRA balancing test.  The assurances 
that Tom Berg and Doug Laycock give, that the only successful RFRA defenses to 
discrimination will be in same sex wedding cases, are politically self-serving, 
totally unreliable, and objectionable on their own terms.   If weddings get 
special treatment, then anniversary parties, children's birthdays, etc. may 
follow. (Cf. the doctors who refuse to provide infertility treatments to 
lesbian couples; those are real cases, not scare hypotheticals.)

And who among us knows when other religious exemptions will be sought and 
gained -- re

Signing off for a while -- RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-03 Thread Scarberry, Mark
I have a lot to do, what with the holidays and my day job, so I’ll be signing 
off for a while. I’ll keep one eye on any further posts in case Chip responds 
to mine (see below), though of course no one has any obligation to respond to 
anyone else’s post.

May the holidays be meaningful, for those of you who are celebrating Passover 
or Easter (or both); of course, for many Christians tonight is not so joyous. 
It is particularly somber in light of the murder of almost 150 Christian 
students in Kenya by Al-Shabaab – murdered specifically because they were 
Christians. Sometimes I think we strain at gnats, and don’t much notice the 
camel in much of the rest of the world (Syria, Iraq, and many other places), 
where there is wholesale violent persecution of Christians and some people of 
other faiths, like the Yazidi and Bahai, because of their beliefs.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law


From: Scarberry, Mark
Sent: Thursday, April 02, 2015 11:04 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

Let's see what Chip and I seem to agree on, and then I'll express my strong 
disagreement on one point.

We seem to agree that the wedding photographer creates art. It is hard to see 
how visual portrayals of an event can convey a message of beauty and 
authenticity and not be called art. Indeed it would seem to be celebratory art, 
as I've been saying all along, if it deals with beauty and authenticity.

We seem to agree that the wedding photographer (if she can be required to 
photograph the same sex ceremony) cannot (as a colleague put it off list) 
sabotage the photography, by intentionally portraying the ceremony as ugly or 
false (in the sense that the two persons are insincere or that the ceremony 
doesn't have whatever legal effect the law provides). I suppose I'd go further 
and say that the photographer has to use the same high-quality equipment that 
she normally would use, has to take photos from the normal angles, and has to 
fix red-eye problems and similar problems before sending the proofs to the 
clients for their selection.

I can't agree that the photographer can be required to create visual works that 
portray the ceremony as beautiful (or authentic, if that means posing the 
couple so as to bring out their sincere commitment to each other). The state 
may be able to require her to photograph the ceremony, but it can't require her 
to express the view that the ceremony is beautiful. The state has no business 
deciding what is beautiful or requiring people to create expressive works that 
carry a message of beauty, any more than it can require people to express the 
view that the state is good and the laws just. The state may not prescribe 
orthodoxy as to the beautiful, the true, or the good; any other view takes us a 
step on the road to tyranny (or, in the extreme, to totalitarianism) which Chip 
obviously would not endorse).

With regard to Ollie's Barbecue, we may disagree about the ways in which Ollie 
may express his political and social views, but surely he can't intentionally 
spoil the food, just as the photographer can't intentionally spoil the photos.

A key difference for other purposes is that Ollie is not in the business of 
creating expressive works; the requirement that he sell food of the same 
quality to all comers doesn't raise compelled speech issues. He has much less 
need to express his political and social views in the restaurant to avoid 
becoming the state's mouthpiece, because he isn't being required to say 
anything that would appear to be his own speech. (He could be required to post 
a sign saying that the state requires all customers to be served, without 
respect to race etc., but that would identify the message as coming from the 
state.)

Nor is Ollie required to be involved personally in the intimate lives of his 
customers, the way a wedding photographer (or wedding planner) ordinarily is 
with the couple. That raises separate free exercise issues in the wedding 
photography case for a photographer who believes it is wrong (as a matter of 
conventional religion or its equivalent per the Seeger case) to facilitate a 
same-sex marriage. And perhaps it creates a hybrid rights situation per Smith.

Of course it's also easier for the state to tell whether Ollie burns the food 
or includes noxious ingredients than it is for the state to determine whether a 
photographer has sufficiently expressed the state's (or the clients') views as 
to beauty and truth. That implicates not only practical concerns but also the 
degree of vagueness of the law and the degree of discretion given to officials 
who would police the photographer's use of her First Amendment rights.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine University School of Law


Sent from my iPad

On Apr 1, 2015, at 6:03 PM, Ira Lupu 
icl...@law.gwu.edumailto:icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
No, I don't think that's OK

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-02 Thread Rick Garnett
 with
 other citizens’ religious observance deserves respect. Standing alone, it
 would often be dispositive.  Where we disagree, I think, is that in
 religious exemption cases I see two principles here that deserve our
 respect. The one I just quoted above and the principle that the majority
 and government should not prohibit or burden another citizen's religious
 observance. I think, you can tell me if I'm wrong, that you would agree
 that this principle standing alone also deserves respect. If there is no
 harm to third parties, you would support religious exemptions.

  Then the question becomes what do we do when these two principles are in
 conflict with each other. I don't think either trumps the other all of the
 time. I think as the harm to third parties increases, the principle that
 citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with the other
 citizen's religious observance outweighs the religious liberty principle. I
 understand you to be saying that the religious liberty principle is always
 trumped in these cases without regard to the magnitude of the costs
 involved.

  There are a lot of religious accommodations that result in third parties
 incurring some cost.  A RLUIPA land use accommodation might result in some
 neighboring homeowner, business or farmer incurring some diminution of
 value in their property. A public university accommodation shifting move-in
 day so that it doesn't fall on the Jewish High Holy days may require a
 shift in the academic calendar that inconveniences the travel plans of
 specific faculty, students and their families. A court accommodating the
 religious obligations of a religious attorney or witness may delay or
 otherwise increase the cost of litigation. A law banning male circumcision
 exempts Jewish families from its requirements. Does the existence of harm
 to third parties in these situations and others require the invalidation of
 all of these accommodations without regard to the magnitude of the harm
 borne by third parties?

  Alan


  --
 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu on behalf of Nelson Tebbe 
 nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 1, 2015 1:38 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



  Alan, I can’t speak for others who have been defending a principle
 against burden-shifting to third parties, but I do not believe it prohibits
 religion accommodations that result in costs to the government or to the
 public. Rather, the principle prohibits government accommodations that
 shift meaningful costs from religious citizens to other identifiable
 private citizens. And the reason for this is easy to articulate and deeply
 rooted — private citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with
 other citizens’ religious observance.

  On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:07 PM, Alan E Brownstein aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu
 wrote:

  The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him
 correctly, is that it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be
 accepted if it causes any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim
 includes the general public or the public fisc in third party.) I think
 many liberals believe (or at least they used to believe) that rights are
 expensive political goods. We protect them even if we have to incur some
 cost or harm to third parties or the public in order to do so. Of course,
 that leaves open the difficult question of determining when the price for
 protecting a right is too high. (And when we are talking about the right to
 discriminate in employment or public accommodations, leaving religious
 institutions aside, the price is almost always too high.) But I see no
 historical consensus that we only protect freedom of speech or religious
 liberty when the cost of doing so is zero. That certainly wasn't the
 understanding of freedom of speech that Justice Brandeis defended in his
 famous dissents on which contemporary free speech doctrine is based.

  Indeed, the argument that we should only accept zero cost religious
 accommodations is not only inconsistent with the way we generally
 understand rights, it seems inconsistent with the way we evaluate
 government regulations generally. It is one thing to argue that we should
 reject a religious exemption when the harm or cost of granting it is too
 high. That position is consistent with the general cost benefit analysis we
 use to discuss any government decision. But why should we only accept zero
 cost religious accommodations? We routinely allow government to enact laws
 that result in some costs, burdens, and harms to third parties or the
 general public that serve a variety of purposes.

  Alan



  ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-02 Thread Micah Schwartzman
 of Hobby Lobby 
 continue to be harmed right now. And as a matter of theory, finally, 
 prominent scholars continue to deny that the principle exists and has legal 
 status, under either free exercise or nonestablishment, despite the fact that 
 the case law in both areas is lopsided in favor of the principle. But again 
 my basic answer is yes, I am open to that approach.
 
 On Apr 1, 2015, at 5:46 PM, Alan E Brownstein aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu 
 wrote:
 
 I appreciate your point, Nelson. And I think the principle that private 
 citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with other citizens’ 
 religious observance deserves respect. Standing alone, it would often be 
 dispositive.  Where we disagree, I think, is that in religious exemption 
 cases I see two principles here that deserve our respect. The one I just 
 quoted above and the principle that the majority and government should not 
 prohibit or burden another citizen's religious observance. I think, you can 
 tell me if I'm wrong, that you would agree that this principle standing 
 alone also deserves respect. If there is no harm to third parties, you would 
 support religious exemptions.
 
 Then the question becomes what do we do when these two principles are in 
 conflict with each other. I don't think either trumps the other all of the 
 time. I think as the harm to third parties increases, the principle that 
 citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with the other 
 citizen's religious observance outweighs the religious liberty principle. I 
 understand you to be saying that the religious liberty principle is always 
 trumped in these cases without regard to the magnitude of the costs involved.
 
 There are a lot of religious accommodations that result in third parties 
 incurring some cost.  A RLUIPA land use accommodation might result in some 
 neighboring homeowner, business or farmer incurring some diminution of value 
 in their property. A public university accommodation shifting move-in day so 
 that it doesn't fall on the Jewish High Holy days may require a shift in the 
 academic calendar that inconveniences the travel plans of specific faculty, 
 students and their families. A court accommodating the religious obligations 
 of a religious attorney or witness may delay or otherwise increase the cost 
 of litigation. A law banning male circumcision exempts Jewish families from 
 its requirements. Does the existence of harm to third parties in these 
 situations and others require the invalidation of all of these 
 accommodations without regard to the magnitude of the harm borne by third 
 parties?
 
 Alan
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu on behalf of Nelson Tebbe 
 nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu
 Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 1:38 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights
  
 
 
 Alan, I can’t speak for others who have been defending a principle against 
 burden-shifting to third parties, but I do not believe it prohibits religion 
 accommodations that result in costs to the government or to the public. 
 Rather, the principle prohibits government accommodations that shift 
 meaningful costs from religious citizens to other identifiable private 
 citizens. And the reason for this is easy to articulate and deeply rooted — 
 private citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with other 
 citizens’ religious observance. 
 
 On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:07 PM, Alan E Brownstein aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu 
 wrote:
 
 The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him correctly, is 
 that it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be accepted if it 
 causes any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim includes the general 
 public or the public fisc in third party.) I think many liberals believe 
 (or at least they used to believe) that rights are expensive political 
 goods. We protect them even if we have to incur some cost or harm to third 
 parties or the public in order to do so. Of course, that leaves open the 
 difficult question of determining when the price for protecting a right is 
 too high. (And when we are talking about the right to discriminate in 
 employment or public accommodations, leaving religious institutions aside, 
 the price is almost always too high.) But I see no historical consensus 
 that we only protect freedom of speech or religious liberty when the cost 
 of doing so is zero. That certainly wasn't the understanding of freedom of 
 speech that Justice Brandeis defended in his famous dissents on which 
 contemporary free speech doctrine is based.
 
 Indeed, the argument that we should only accept zero cost religious 
 accommodations is not only inconsistent with the way we generally 
 understand rights, it seems inconsistent with the way we evaluate 
 government regulations generally. It is one thing to argue that we should 
 reject a religious exemption when

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-02 Thread Scarberry, Mark
...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 5:32 PM

To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

If the compelled speech argument is constitutionally sufficient, permission to 
post a disclaiming sign may solve the problem. (It would be like letting a 
student say aloud I don't mean it after forcing her to recite the Pledge of 
Allegiance.)
 [snip]

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-02 Thread Marc DeGirolami
Micah, nobody I know who is resisting the third party Establishment Clause 
theory that you, Nelson, and others have created based on “the general form” of 
a constitutional limit on religious accommodation. RFRA  incorporates the 
general form of such a limit.

Marc


From: Micah Schwartzman mj...@virginia.edumailto:mj...@virginia.edu
Reply-To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Date: Thursday, April 2, 2015 at 1:40 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

Rick,

In Hobby Lobby, the majority says: It is certainly true that in applying RFRA 
“courts must take adequate account of the burdens a requested accommodation may 
impose on nonbeneficiaries.” Cutter v. Wilkinson, 544 U. S. 
709http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/544/709, 720 (2005) 
(applying RLUIPA). That sentence quoted from Cutter relies on Caldor. These are 
both Establishment Clauses cases articulating a limit on permissive 
accommodations.

We can argue about the scope of that limit, but as Nelson said earlier, it is 
surprising to see such resistance to even the general form of it.

Micah

On Apr 2, 2015, at 10:33 AM, Rick Garnett 
rgarn...@nd.edumailto:rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:

Dear Nelson,

I don't see that the Hobby Lobby Court reaffirmed the principle against 
burden-shifting in religion accommodations or that Justice Kennedy made it 
central to his vote if by principle here you mean the argument -- which, of 
course, you and several others have very ably developed and expounded -- that 
the Establishment Clause rules out (all?) legislative accommodations that 
involve or impose third-party costs (on specific, identifiable third parties).  
(I ask about all because my recollection is that you have said that the 
accommodation at issue in Amos was / is permissible.)  Justice Ginsburg notes 
in a footnote that the government’s license to grant religion-based exemptions 
from generally applicable laws is constrained by the Establishment Clause but, 
it seems to me, she did not rely on this point in her dissent, which seemed to 
me to be more about RFRA's particular elements.  Justice Kennedy says, in his 
penultimate paragraph, [y]et neither may that same exercise unduly restrict 
other persons, such as employees, in protecting their own interests, interests 
the law deems compelling[,] but he seems to be doing so in the context of 
applying what he and the Court call RFRA's stringent test and not necessarily 
to be invoking an Establishment Clause constraint.  And, Justice Alito does not 
mention the Establishment Clause at all.

I also continue to think -- although the conversation about the rule you and 
other leading scholars propose is very important -- that it is not quite the 
case that the case law in both areas is lopsided in favor of the principle -- 
again, if the principle is the fairly strong Establishment Clause constraint 
you all have proposed -- but . . . disagreement among colleagues helps make 
life interesting and I guess we just understand Caldor and Cutter differently. 
Marc DeGirolami's discussion (here:  
http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2013/12/exemptions-from-the-mandate-do-not-violate-the-establishment-clause.html)
 and Eugene Volokh's (here: 
http://volokh.com/2013/12/04/3b-granting-exemption-employer-mandate-violate-establishment-clause/)
 were, for me, helpful.

With respect to your (and others') Establishment Clause argument, I do have a 
quick question.  (I am sorry if I am forgetting an answer that you have already 
presented in your scholarship!)  Do you think we should think of the 
no-burden-shifting rule as applying, in a sense, only *after* we have 
identified whatever limits on government regulation the First Amendment might 
require (e.g., the ministerial exception), and as applying only as a constraint 
on discretionary accommodations, or should we think of the rule as kicking in 
earlier, and as helping to fix the point where the First Amendment rights of, 
say, Hosanna-Tabor school end?  Or does it not matter?  Again, please feel free 
just to refer me to something else.

All the best,

Rick


Richard W. Garnett
Professor of Law and Concurrent Professor of Political Science
Director, Program on Church, State  Society
Notre Dame Law School
P.O. Box 780
Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780
574-631-6981 (w)
574-276-2252 (cell)
rgarn...@nd.edumailto:rgarn...@nd.edu



To download my scholarly papers, please visit my SSRN 
pagehttp://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=342235



Blogs:



Prawfsblawghttp://prawfsblawg.blogs.com/
Mirror of Justicehttp://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/



Twitter:  @RickGarnetthttps://twitter.com/RickGarnett

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 7:07 PM, Nelson Tebbe 
nelson.te...@brooklaw.edumailto:nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu wrote:


Thanks, Alan. Speaking again only

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Ira Lupu
I think the compelled speech issues, re: communicative work like
photography, are interesting and sometimes difficult. I address those in an
article I will post later this month.  All I want to say now is that
religious motivation is irrelevant to the compelled speech argument.  (See
W Va Bd of Educ v. Barnette.)

But Mark also say If [harm] depends on the message sent by the refusal,
then we have an interesting viewpoint discrimination issue.  If, in 1965,
Ollie's BBQ had put up a sign in the window that read Federal law says we
must serve all, so we will, but n-s are not sincerely welcome, then he
would have violated the Public Accommodations title of the Civil Rights Act
(he would not have provided full and equal enjoyment of his restaurant
without discrimination on the basis of race.)  Does Mark or anyone on
this list really think that presents a serious First Amendment problem?
Ollie can write letters to Congress, and to the newspapers, and put signs
on his lawn, all railing against the oppressive Civil Rights Act, but he
cannot communicate that directly to customers on his business premises. If
it were otherwise, the Act would be gutted entirely.  I think that no
Justice who has served in the last 50 years would take such a First A claim
seriously.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:53 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 I also think the florist and baker examples are weaker for the religious
 claimant, especially where the flowers and cakes are generic. But what if
 custom floral arrangements involve artistic choices by the florist? What if
 the cake is (as some are) a truly creative work of art? And do only
 high-end bakers get protection from violation of conscience? What if the
 florist or baker is asked to include particular words or other expressive
 content in the arrangement or the cake? (This from someone who argued
 against licensing requirements for sellers of flowers – protectionist
 provisions for florists who fear grocery stores’ selling of flowers – on
 the basis that flower arranging is a kind of art that the government has no
 right to license, other than for health purposes.) What if the custom
 florist decides to include a lot of black roses in the arrangements? Or
 just puts the flowers together without using any creativity (so that they
 look like flowers you would get through 1-800-Flowers)? Can the florist be
 required to enter into the contract to provide flowers and then be required
 to follow some sort of industry standard of artistry in arranging the
 flowers?



 In the photography example, if the photographer must photograph a ceremony
 that he or she believes wrong, may the photographer refuse to use the
 creative skills that would ordinarily be used? (E.g., posing the couple in
 a particular way, using filters to get a romantic look, telling them to
 kiss for the photograph, etc.) I suppose that goes with my view that
 wedding photography is creation of celebratory art, and the First Amendment
 compelled speech cases prohibit the government from requiring the
 photographer to create art.



 On the harm question, of course there is a matter of baseline. Do I harm
 you by not photographing your ceremony? Or do I benefit you by doing it? If
 that depends on the message sent by the refusal, then we have an
 interesting viewpoint discrimination issue.



 Mark



 Mark S. Scarberry

 Professor of Law

 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law









 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Levinson, Sanford V
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 3:18 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 I think Prof. Chen is substantially correct, but I believe, more than
 ever, that it's the kind of problem that can ( and should) be handled
 outside legal constraints. Why would I want to hire a wedding photographer
 who so clearly won't view the day as affirmatively special?  Ditto the
 band?  But I really can't work up much sympathy for the florist or baker.
 They should be treated under the general rubric of public accommodations
 and the Civil Rights Act of 1964. I'm sure there were florists and bakers
 who objected to mixes-race marriages and could cite the purported curse on
 Ham. It really doesn't (and shouldn't) matter.



 Sandy

 Sent from my iPhone


 On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:56 PM, K Chen tzn...@gmail.com wrote:

 As someone putting a wedding together, I can't explain the lack of
 sympathy for the wedding photographer as anything but thinking that their
 work is essentially interchangeable. It is not, unfortunately, and it is
 priced accordingly. Every single photographer of them seems to take their
 business very, very personally. More to the point, it is a personal,
 professional service which is by its nature selective compared to the harm
 done by impersonal corporations excluding goods and services when they
 otherwise

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Ira Lupu
If the compelled speech argument is constitutionally sufficient, permission
to post a disclaiming sign may solve the problem. (It would be like letting
a student say aloud I don't mean it after forcing her to recite the
Pledge of Allegiance.)

If the compelled speech argument is NOT constitutionally sufficient, I
think the photographers have no First A right to put up such a sign, though
of course the NM legislature could permissibly accommodate the religious
objection by permitting a vendor to post such a sign.  Away from the
business site (on line or physical), the photographer of course is free to
express her views on same sex marriage.



On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 7:37 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 I don’t have time right now to respond in a substantial way to Chip’s
 post. Let me just quote this language from the New Mexico Supreme Court’s
 decision in Elane Photography:



 “Businesses that choose to be public accommodations must comply with the
 NMHRA, although such businesses retain their First Amendment rights to
 express their religious or political beliefs. They may, for example, post a
 disclaimer on their website or in their studio advertising that they oppose
 same-sex marriage but that they comply with applicable antidiscrimination
 laws.”



 That’s not quite the same as saying that gay couples aren’t welcome, but
 it’s pretty close. Is the NM court right that the photographers have a 1st
 Am right to do so?



 On the question whether religious liberty claims have anything to do with
 the compelled speech issue, if we believe that the “hybrid rights” part of
 Smith means anything, it might apply in this kind of case so that the
 combination of the claims to constitutional protection might create some
 synergy.



 Mark



 Mark S. Scarberry

 Professor of Law

 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law



















 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Ira Lupu
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 4:22 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 I think the compelled speech issues, re: communicative work like
 photography, are interesting and sometimes difficult. I address those in an
 article I will post later this month.  All I want to say now is that
 religious motivation is irrelevant to the compelled speech argument.  (See
 W Va Bd of Educ v. Barnette.)



 But Mark also say If [harm] depends on the message sent by the refusal,
 then we have an interesting viewpoint discrimination issue.  If, in 1965,
 Ollie's BBQ had put up a sign in the window that read Federal law says we
 must serve all, so we will, but n-s are not sincerely welcome, then he
 would have violated the Public Accommodations title of the Civil Rights Act
 (he would not have provided full and equal enjoyment of his restaurant
 without discrimination on the basis of race.)  Does Mark or anyone on
 this list really think that presents a serious First Amendment problem?
 Ollie can write letters to Congress, and to the newspapers, and put signs
 on his lawn, all railing against the oppressive Civil Rights Act, but he
 cannot communicate that directly to customers on his business premises. If
 it were otherwise, the Act would be gutted entirely.  I think that no
 Justice who has served in the last 50 years would take such a First A claim
 seriously.



 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:53 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 I also think the florist and baker examples are weaker for the religious
 claimant, especially where the flowers and cakes are generic. But what if
 custom floral arrangements involve artistic choices by the florist? What if
 the cake is (as some are) a truly creative work of art? And do only
 high-end bakers get protection from violation of conscience? What if the
 florist or baker is asked to include particular words or other expressive
 content in the arrangement or the cake? (This from someone who argued
 against licensing requirements for sellers of flowers – protectionist
 provisions for florists who fear grocery stores’ selling of flowers – on
 the basis that flower arranging is a kind of art that the government has no
 right to license, other than for health purposes.) What if the custom
 florist decides to include a lot of black roses in the arrangements? Or
 just puts the flowers together without using any creativity (so that they
 look like flowers you would get through 1-800-Flowers)? Can the florist be
 required to enter into the contract to provide flowers and then be required
 to follow some sort of industry standard of artistry in arranging the
 flowers?



 In the photography example, if the photographer must photograph a ceremony
 that he or she believes wrong, may the photographer refuse to use the
 creative skills that would ordinarily be used? (E.g., posing the couple in
 a particular way, using

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Ira Lupu
No, I don't think that's OK.  But that's a real compelled speech problem,
where the student must first utter the Pledge.

The wedding vendors do not have to say anything approving about the
marriage, or affirm its validity in the eyes of the state or God.  They do
have to provide goods and services; in the photographer's case, the
services include making the wedding look authentic and beautiful, not ugly
or false.  So the compelled speech concern seems much weaker to me than in
Barnette.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 8:53 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 Apart from the other points with which I disagree:



 Wow, Chip. You really think it’s OK to make the student recite the Pledge,
 as long as the student is permitted at the end to say “I don’t mean it”?
 Can I be required to burn a pinch of incense to the emperor as long as I am
 permitted afterwards to say that the emperor isn’t really a god?



 Mark



 Mark S. Scarberry

 Professor of Law

 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law







 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Ira Lupu
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 5:32 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 If the compelled speech argument is constitutionally sufficient,
 permission to post a disclaiming sign may solve the problem. (It would be
 like letting a student say aloud I don't mean it after forcing her to
 recite the Pledge of Allegiance.)



 If the compelled speech argument is NOT constitutionally sufficient, I
 think the photographers have no First A right to put up such a sign, though
 of course the NM legislature could permissibly accommodate the religious
 objection by permitting a vendor to post such a sign.  Away from the
 business site (on line or physical), the photographer of course is free to
 express her views on same sex marriage.







 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 7:37 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 I don’t have time right now to respond in a substantial way to Chip’s
 post. Let me just quote this language from the New Mexico Supreme Court’s
 decision in Elane Photography:



 “Businesses that choose to be public accommodations must comply with the
 NMHRA, although such businesses retain their First Amendment rights to
 express their religious or political beliefs. They may, for example, post a
 disclaimer on their website or in their studio advertising that they oppose
 same-sex marriage but that they comply with applicable antidiscrimination
 laws.”



 That’s not quite the same as saying that gay couples aren’t welcome, but
 it’s pretty close. Is the NM court right that the photographers have a 1st
 Am right to do so?



 On the question whether religious liberty claims have anything to do with
 the compelled speech issue, if we believe that the “hybrid rights” part of
 Smith means anything, it might apply in this kind of case so that the
 combination of the claims to constitutional protection might create some
 synergy.



 Mark



 Mark S. Scarberry

 Professor of Law

 Pepperdine Univ. School of Law



















 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Ira Lupu
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 4:22 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 I think the compelled speech issues, re: communicative work like
 photography, are interesting and sometimes difficult. I address those in an
 article I will post later this month.  All I want to say now is that
 religious motivation is irrelevant to the compelled speech argument.  (See
 W Va Bd of Educ v. Barnette.)



 But Mark also say If [harm] depends on the message sent by the refusal,
 then we have an interesting viewpoint discrimination issue.  If, in 1965,
 Ollie's BBQ had put up a sign in the window that read Federal law says we
 must serve all, so we will, but n-s are not sincerely welcome, then he
 would have violated the Public Accommodations title of the Civil Rights Act
 (he would not have provided full and equal enjoyment of his restaurant
 without discrimination on the basis of race.)  Does Mark or anyone on
 this list really think that presents a serious First Amendment problem?
 Ollie can write letters to Congress, and to the newspapers, and put signs
 on his lawn, all railing against the oppressive Civil Rights Act, but he
 cannot communicate that directly to customers on his business premises. If
 it were otherwise, the Act would be gutted entirely.  I think that no
 Justice who has served in the last 50 years would take such a First A claim
 seriously.



 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:53 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
 mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 I also think the florist and baker examples are weaker for the religious
 claimant, especially where the flowers and cakes

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Nelson Tebbe


Thanks, Alan. Speaking again only for myself, I am open to some balancing, not 
only as to this particular principle (against burden shifting to third parties) 
but also as a general methodology, as you know. But the conversation is not yet 
at that point. Right now, the main debate is over whether the principle even 
exists in constitutional law, and what its most basic applications might be, 
not over its contours. As a matter of doctrine, the Hobby Lobby Court 
reaffirmed the principle against burden-shifting in religion accommodations, 
and Justice Kennedy made it central to his vote, but there is some troubling 
language in the opinion (see, e.g., footnote 37 and the sharp division between 
RFRA and pre-Smith cases). As a matter of application, the Hobby Lobby Court 
did not make its ruling contingent on the absence of harm to third parties. And 
in fact employees of Hobby Lobby continue to be harmed right now. And as a 
matter of theory, finally, prominent scholars continue to deny that the 
principle exists and has legal status, under either free exercise or 
nonestablishment, despite the fact that the case law in both areas is lopsided 
in favor of the principle. But again my basic answer is yes, I am open to that 
approach.

On Apr 1, 2015, at 5:46 PM, Alan E Brownstein 
aebrownst...@ucdavis.edumailto:aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu wrote:


I appreciate your point, Nelson. And I think the principle that private 
citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with other citizens’ 
religious observance deserves respect. Standing alone, it would often be 
dispositive.  Where we disagree, I think, is that in religious exemption cases 
I see two principles here that deserve our respect. The one I just quoted above 
and the principle that the majority and government should not prohibit or 
burden another citizen's religious observance. I think, you can tell me if I'm 
wrong, that you would agree that this principle standing alone also deserves 
respect. If there is no harm to third parties, you would support religious 
exemptions.

Then the question becomes what do we do when these two principles are in 
conflict with each other. I don't think either trumps the other all of the 
time. I think as the harm to third parties increases, the principle that 
citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with the other citizen's 
religious observance outweighs the religious liberty principle. I understand 
you to be saying that the religious liberty principle is always trumped in 
these cases without regard to the magnitude of the costs involved.

There are a lot of religious accommodations that result in third parties 
incurring some cost.  A RLUIPA land use accommodation might result in some 
neighboring homeowner, business or farmer incurring some diminution of value in 
their property. A public university accommodation shifting move-in day so that 
it doesn't fall on the Jewish High Holy days may require a shift in the 
academic calendar that inconveniences the travel plans of specific faculty, 
students and their families. A court accommodating the religious obligations of 
a religious attorney or witness may delay or otherwise increase the cost of 
litigation. A law banning male circumcision exempts Jewish families from its 
requirements. Does the existence of harm to third parties in these situations 
and others require the invalidation of all of these accommodations without 
regard to the magnitude of the harm borne by third parties?

Alan



From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
on behalf of Nelson Tebbe 
nelson.te...@brooklaw.edumailto:nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu
Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 1:38 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



Alan, I can’t speak for others who have been defending a principle against 
burden-shifting to third parties, but I do not believe it prohibits religion 
accommodations that result in costs to the government or to the public. Rather, 
the principle prohibits government accommodations that shift meaningful costs 
from religious citizens to other identifiable private citizens. And the reason 
for this is easy to articulate and deeply rooted — private citizens should not 
have to bear the costs associated with other citizens’ religious observance.

On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:07 PM, Alan E Brownstein 
aebrownst...@ucdavis.edumailto:aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu wrote:

The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him correctly, is that 
it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be accepted if it causes 
any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim includes the general public or 
the public fisc in third party.) I think many liberals believe (or at least 
they used to believe) that rights are expensive political goods. We

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
 state.”   
http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers


From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of James Oleske
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’ 
(sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious 
exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full, but I 
want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of Eugene's 
analysis:
Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions from 
antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the same under 
the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long championed.

http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/

Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial marketplace, 
which is the context generating almost all of the liberal concerns about 
exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's characterization of the law 
in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely the opposite argument at length 
in Part II of the following piece: 
http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/ 
(The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the 
Commercial Realm).

Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee, which 
is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed the issue 
of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court dismissed a 
commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an antidiscrimination law as 
patently frivolous. Instead, Eugene refers to Justice Brennan's pre-Sherbert 
dissenting opinion in Crown. Whatever Justice Brennan's views in 1961, it is 
difficult to understand how they are a better representation of the 
Sherbert-era law than the following explicit statement of the Court in Lee, 
which was joined by Justice Brennan (as was Piggie Park):
When followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as a matter 
of choice, the limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter of 
conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on the statutory schemes which 
are binding on others in that activity. Granting an exemption from social 
security taxes to an employer operates to impose the employer's religious faith 
on the employees.

Accordingly, I don't think the ACLU's current position can be accurately 
described as a retreat from their support of Sherbert-era exemption rights. 
As Eugene notes in his post, the ACLU still opposes Smith and supports 
exemption rights outside the commercial context. As I note in my piece, this is 
also true of Americans United and the Brennan Center. The strong opposition of 
those organizations to extending exemption rights into the for-profit 
commercial realm has sometimes been misread as a reversal of their position on 
exemption rights in general (indeed, I myself have made that mistake in the 
past), but as I detail in the piece cited above, an examination of the full 
record shows that [l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 
1993 — including liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely 
continue to support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the 
extension of such exemptions to commercial businesses.
- Jim


___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo

RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
   Sandy:  I appreciate your point, but should it be relevant that 
Title II of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 actually covered a comparatively 
narrow set of places of public accommodation, and (as best I can tell) didn't 
apply to retail establishments or service providers such as florists or bakers? 
 Many state laws are broader, to be sure, but if the appeal is to the seminal 
nature of the federal Civil Rights Act, I'm not sure how far that appeal would 
take us as to these sorts of businesses.

   Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Levinson, Sanford V
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 3:18 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

I think Prof. Chen is substantially correct, but I believe, more than ever, 
that it's the kind of problem that can ( and should) be handled outside legal 
constraints. Why would I want to hire a wedding photographer who so clearly 
won't view the day as affirmatively special?  Ditto the band?  But I really 
can't work up much sympathy for the florist or baker. They should be treated 
under the general rubric of public accommodations and the Civil Rights Act of 
1964. I'm sure there were florists and bakers who objected to mixes-race 
marriages and could cite the purported curse on Ham. It really doesn't (and 
shouldn't) matter.

Sandy

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
. The harm of being 
denied service by a consumer (or laborer) because of their beliefs has a 
societal harm, if any, nearly indistinguishable to being denied for any other 
reason.

Some services should fall in between. I'm not convinced for the florist and the 
and the baker, but I'm sympathetic to the photographer, the doctor, the lawyer 
(ethical obligations notwithstanding) , the political consultant, the ghost 
writer...

I don't know how far that gets liberals of course, but it is a difference 
beyond mere size and corporate form.

Kevin Chen

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek 
dgaub...@imb.orgmailto:dgaub...@imb.org wrote:
“[l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including 
liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to 
support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of 
such exemptions to commercial businesses.

I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many individuals 
depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do liberals see the 
conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy of protection, but the 
conscience of an individual photographer, florist, baker, or bed and breakfast 
owner less worthy of protection?Justice Kagan, at least back in 1996 when 
she was in the Clinton White House, appeared to recognize that the consciences 
of individuals operating small commercial businesses was worthy of protection 
under a RFRA regime.   Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a 
Evelyn Smith who, for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units 
to a co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was 
“outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold that a 
state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because the 
complainant is free to move to another state.”   
http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers


From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of James Oleske
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’ 
(sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious 
exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full, but I 
want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of Eugene's 
analysis:
Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions from 
antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the same under 
the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long championed.

http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/

Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial marketplace, 
which is the context generating almost all of the liberal concerns about 
exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's characterization of the law 
in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely the opposite argument at length 
in Part II of the following piece: 
http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/ 
(The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the 
Commercial Realm).

Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee, which 
is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed the issue 
of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court dismissed a 
commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an antidiscrimination law as 
patently frivolous. Instead, Eugene refers to Justice Brennan's pre-Sherbert 
dissenting opinion in Crown. Whatever Justice Brennan's views in 1961, it is 
difficult to understand how they are a better representation of the 
Sherbert-era law than the following explicit statement of the Court in Lee, 
which was joined by Justice Brennan (as was Piggie Park):
When followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as a matter 
of choice, the limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter of 
conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on the statutory schemes which 
are binding on others in that activity. Granting an exemption from social 
security taxes to an employer operates to impose the employer's religious faith 
on the employees.

Accordingly, I don't think the ACLU's current position can be accurately 
described as a retreat from their support of Sherbert-era exemption rights. 
As Eugene notes in his post, the ACLU still opposes Smith and supports 
exemption rights outside the commercial context. As I note in my piece, this is 
also true of Americans United and the Brennan Center. The strong

RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Scarberry, Mark
I don’t have time right now to respond in a substantial way to Chip’s post. Let 
me just quote this language from the New Mexico Supreme Court’s decision in 
Elane Photography:

“Businesses that choose to be public accommodations must comply with the NMHRA, 
although such businesses retain their First Amendment rights to express their 
religious or political beliefs. They may, for example, post a disclaimer on 
their website or in their studio advertising that they oppose same-sex marriage 
but that they comply with applicable antidiscrimination laws.”

That’s not quite the same as saying that gay couples aren’t welcome, but it’s 
pretty close. Is the NM court right that the photographers have a 1st Am right 
to do so?

On the question whether religious liberty claims have anything to do with the 
compelled speech issue, if we believe that the “hybrid rights” part of Smith 
means anything, it might apply in this kind of case so that the combination of 
the claims to constitutional protection might create some synergy.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law









From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 4:22 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

I think the compelled speech issues, re: communicative work like photography, 
are interesting and sometimes difficult. I address those in an article I will 
post later this month.  All I want to say now is that religious motivation is 
irrelevant to the compelled speech argument.  (See W Va Bd of Educ v. Barnette.)

But Mark also say If [harm] depends on the message sent by the refusal, then 
we have an interesting viewpoint discrimination issue.  If, in 1965, Ollie's 
BBQ had put up a sign in the window that read Federal law says we must serve 
all, so we will, but n-s are not sincerely welcome, then he would have 
violated the Public Accommodations title of the Civil Rights Act (he would not 
have provided full and equal enjoyment of his restaurant without 
discrimination on the basis of race.)  Does Mark or anyone on this list really 
think that presents a serious First Amendment problem?  Ollie can write letters 
to Congress, and to the newspapers, and put signs on his lawn, all railing 
against the oppressive Civil Rights Act, but he cannot communicate that 
directly to customers on his business premises. If it were otherwise, the Act 
would be gutted entirely.  I think that no Justice who has served in the last 
50 years would take such a First A claim seriously.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:53 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
I also think the florist and baker examples are weaker for the religious 
claimant, especially where the flowers and cakes are generic. But what if 
custom floral arrangements involve artistic choices by the florist? What if the 
cake is (as some are) a truly creative work of art? And do only high-end bakers 
get protection from violation of conscience? What if the florist or baker is 
asked to include particular words or other expressive content in the 
arrangement or the cake? (This from someone who argued against licensing 
requirements for sellers of flowers – protectionist provisions for florists who 
fear grocery stores’ selling of flowers – on the basis that flower arranging is 
a kind of art that the government has no right to license, other than for 
health purposes.) What if the custom florist decides to include a lot of black 
roses in the arrangements? Or just puts the flowers together without using any 
creativity (so that they look like flowers you would get through 
1-800-Flowers)? Can the florist be required to enter into the contract to 
provide flowers and then be required to follow some sort of industry standard 
of artistry in arranging the flowers?

In the photography example, if the photographer must photograph a ceremony that 
he or she believes wrong, may the photographer refuse to use the creative 
skills that would ordinarily be used? (E.g., posing the couple in a particular 
way, using filters to get a romantic look, telling them to kiss for the 
photograph, etc.) I suppose that goes with my view that wedding photography is 
creation of celebratory art, and the First Amendment compelled speech cases 
prohibit the government from requiring the photographer to create art.

On the harm question, of course there is a matter of baseline. Do I harm you by 
not photographing your ceremony? Or do I benefit you by doing it? If that 
depends on the message sent by the refusal, then we have an interesting 
viewpoint discrimination issue.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Will Esser
Chip,
Thanks for the explanation, which is helpful.  But I want to push a little 
farther on this concept of dignitary injury.
You state that the dignitary injury is more serious because it has wounded 
the couple with this disrespect.  But how far can that argument really go?  
Are you saying that public non-discrimination laws not only require the 
provisions of goods and services to all comers, but also require that those 
services be provided in a way that will be viewed as respectful of the 
particular beliefs of the customers?  
If that is the case, does the photographer who has the Piss Christ photograph 
by Andres Serrano hanging on the wall of their shop (i.e. a photograph which 
very clearly singles out Christians for disrespect and dignitary injury) also 
run afoul of public non-discrimination laws even if the photographer is 
otherwise willing to perform photography services for Christians?  Or use the 
same example but substitute in the cover of the Charlie Hebdo magazine 
depicting the Prophet Muhammad?  
Mark pointed it out in several of his later posts, but I'm troubled about how 
this concept of dignitary injury logically plays out and whether your 
argument essentially means that anyone involved in businesses which provide 
public services are required to check their free speech and opinions at the 
door.  There are, after all, many categories of things that a business owner 
could say which would be gravely disrespectful and injure the dignity of 
customers (e.g. My are you fat.  You are so ugly I can't stand to look at 
you etc.).  The marketplace (particularly in this age of social media) would 
quickly penalize such disrespect in an economic manner, but I had never viewed 
it as within the purview of non-discrimination laws to protect citizens from 
speech that they found disrespectful.  
I welcome your thoughts.  
Will

Will Esser 
Charlotte, North Carolina
   From: Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu
 To: Will Esser willes...@yahoo.com; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu 
 Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 6:35 PM
 Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights
   
Thanks for the question, Will. If the kosher butcher gets that exemption, he 
will sell pork to no one.  He never has and never will carry pork in his shop.  
He also does not sell soda, cars, or wedding cakes.  If you want that stuff, 
you must go elsewhere.  Is that a cost to third parties?''  No more than that 
imposed by any (that is, every) other merchant who sells less than everything.
Compare that to a discriminatory refusal to sell.  Baker A does sell wedding 
cakes, but not to same sex couples.  Two injuries -- material and dignitary.  
The material injury is the lost opportunity to buy a cake at the quality and 
price offered by that baker.  Maybe you can do as well or better elsewhere, 
nearby, or maybe not.  The dignitary injury is more serious -- the couple is 
seeking goods to celebrate one of the most important and special days of their 
lives. And the baker says, in effect, I do not respect your marriage as a 
marriage.  In my belief system, it is not a marriage at all, because you are of 
the same sex. (The baker might also think or say that in his view the 
relationship is disordered, or an abomination, and/or against God's plan, but 
let's assume he says nothing like that all.)  The baker has wounded the couple 
with this disrespect, and done so in regard to a day that has significant 
meaning in their lives.
Those are the focused, third party harms in the refusal to sell goods or 
services to some that you sell to others, especially (though not only) for a 
wedding reception.
On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 4:38 PM, Will Esser willes...@yahoo.com wrote:



Chip,
Can you expound on your argument that wedding vendor exemptions from public 
accommodations laws allow material and dignitary injury to potential 
customers and that liberals only oppose exemptions that impinge on the 
welfare of third parties?  It seems that both sides agree that the kosher 
butcher deserves a religious exemption, and yet granting that exemption imposes 
some cost on third parties (i.e. anyone who wishes to purchase pork must go 
elsewhere, which could involve multiple trips to different butchers, or may 
mean spending more time and money to go to a butcher further away).  So it's 
not really that there is no cost to third parties, but perhaps simply a cost 
which society is more ready to accept (i.e. Go buy your pork somewhere else.)
As I understood the third-party harm argument in Hobby Lobby, the argument 
was that without insurance coverage, female Hobby Lobby employees would be 
unable to afford coverage of the particular, objectionable contraceptives and 
therefore the third party harm was equivalent to total lack of access.  

Given modern changes in societal perspectives, I have not heard the same 
argument about a total lack of access when it comes to wedding vendors for 
same-sex

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Marty Lederman
Sandy:  the florist who refuses to sell a bouquet for use at a same-sex
marriage, who is necessarily condoning the presumptively sinful conduct?

I assume you meant to say that the florist would necessarily condone the
presumptively sinful conduct if she *did* sell the bouquet to the same-sex
couple.  If so -- really?!  I would think that such a sale would *not*
reasonably
be viewed as condoning the same-sex marriage even in the absence of an
antidiscrimination law requirement . . . and certainly not if it were done
solely in order to comply with such a law.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 5:17 PM, Levinson, Sanford V 
slevin...@law.utexas.edu wrote:

  Non-Jews are under no obligation not to eat pork (or adhere to almost
 all of the other 612 mitzvot). So there is no stigma attached to any
 non-Jew who wants to buy a ham at a kosher butchery. That can't be said
 with regard to the florist who refuses to sell a bouquet for use at a
 same-sex marriage, who is necessarily condoning the presumptively sinful
 conduct. Ironically or not, the only person a Jewish butcher might be upset
 with is another Jew. This underscores the fact that very few Jewish laws
 are universal.  This is not true of most purported Christian precepts
 (beginning with the widely shared view among many a Evangelicals that I'm
 damned for failure to accept the teaching of John 3:16 (which I know by
 heart having memorized it some 65 years ago in order to earn a Bible
 certificate from the state of North Carolina).

  Sandy

 Sent from my iPhone

 On Apr 1, 2015, at 3:44 PM, Will Esser willes...@yahoo.com wrote:

   Chip,

  Can you expound on your argument that wedding vendor exemptions from
 public accommodations laws allow material and dignitary injury to
 potential customers and that liberals only oppose exemptions that impinge
 on the welfare of third parties?  It seems that both sides agree that the
 kosher butcher deserves a religious exemption, and yet granting that
 exemption imposes *some* cost on third parties (i.e. anyone who wishes to
 purchase pork must go elsewhere, which could involve multiple trips to
 different butchers, or may mean spending more time and money to go to a
 butcher further away).  So it's not really that there is * no* cost to
 third parties, but perhaps simply a cost which society is more ready to
 accept (i.e. Go buy your pork somewhere else.)

  As I understood the third-party harm argument in Hobby Lobby, the
 argument was that without insurance coverage, female Hobby Lobby employees
 would be unable to afford coverage of the particular, objectionable
 contraceptives and therefore the third party harm was equivalent to total
 lack of access.

  Given modern changes in societal perspectives, I have not heard the same
 argument about a total lack of access when it comes to wedding vendors for
 same-sex wedding ceremonies.  Under the assumption the goods and services
 are otherwise generally available in the marketplace (i.e. there are plenty
 of wedding photographers, bakers, etc. who would be happy for the business
 of same-sex weddings), what is the distinguishing factor which causes
 material and dignitary injury in the wedding vendor exemptions scenario
 but not in the kosher butcher example?  In both, the customers want a
 service which they can get in the marketplace (although perhaps not from
 the exact person or place they want it).  And in both, the reason for not
 providing the service is the same (i.e. violation of a sincerely held
 religious belief).

  Thanks in advance for clarification.

  Will

  Will Esser
 Charlotte, North Carolina


   --
 *From:* James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 1, 2015 3:22 PM
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

   The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the
 Court might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but
 rather, a strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm
 that can be overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the
 presumption (a third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead
 simply discarded the Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further
 than the pre-Smith law.

  - Jim




  On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

  I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se --
 imagine a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with
 religious dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.
 Liberals oppose exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties --
 Hobby Lobby (those female employees still do not have contraceptive
 coverage) or wedding vendor exemptions from public accommodations laws
 (those exemptions allow material and dignitary injury to potential
 customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other family members of Amish

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
 one 
of her units to a co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning 
was “outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold 
that a state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because the 
complainant is free to move to another state.”
  http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers


From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of James Oleske
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’ 
(sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious 
exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full, but 
I want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of Eugene's 
analysis:
Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions from 
antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the same 
under the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long championed.

http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/

Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial marketplace, 
which is the context generating almost all of the liberal concerns about 
exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's characterization of the law 
in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely the opposite argument at length 
in Part II of the following piece: 
http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/ 
(The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the 
Commercial Realm).

Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee, which 
is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed the 
issue of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court dismissed a 
commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an antidiscrimination law 
as patently frivolous. Instead, Eugene refers to Justice Brennan's 
pre-Sherbert dissenting opinion in Crown. Whatever Justice Brennan's views in 
1961, it is difficult to understand how they are a better representation of 
the Sherbert-era law than the following explicit statement of the Court in 
Lee, which was joined by Justice Brennan (as was Piggie Park):
When followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as a 
matter of choice, the limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter of 
conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on the statutory schemes which 
are binding on others in that activity. Granting an exemption from social 
security taxes to an employer operates to impose the employer's religious 
faith on the employees.

Accordingly, I don't think the ACLU's current position can be accurately 
described as a retreat from their support of Sherbert-era exemption rights. 
As Eugene notes in his post, the ACLU still opposes Smith and supports 
exemption rights outside the commercial context. As I note in my piece, this 
is also true of Americans United and the Brennan Center. The strong opposition 
of those organizations to extending exemption rights into the for-profit 
commercial realm has sometimes been misread as a reversal of their position on 
exemption rights in general (indeed, I myself have made that mistake in the 
past), but as I detail in the piece cited above, an examination of the full 
record shows that [l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 
1993 — including liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely 
continue to support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the 
extension of such exemptions to commercial businesses.
- Jim


___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private. 
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people 
can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward 
the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private. 
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people 
can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Richard Friedman
 distinction.   Do not many
 individuals depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do
 liberals see the conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy
 of protection, but the conscience of an individual photographer, florist,
 baker, or bed and breakfast owner less worthy of protection?Justice
 Kagan, at least back in 1996 when she was in the Clinton White House,
 appeared to recognize that the consciences of individuals operating small
 commercial businesses was worthy of protection under a RFRA regime.
 Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a Evelyn Smith who,
 for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units to a
 co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was
 “outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to
 hold that a state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion
 because the complainant is free to move to another state.”
 http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers





 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *James Oleske
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’
 (sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious
 exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full,
 but I want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of
 Eugene's analysis:

 Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions
 from antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the
 same under the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long
 championed.




 http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/


 Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial
 marketplace, which is the context generating almost all of the liberal
 concerns about exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's
 characterization of the law in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely
 the opposite argument at length in Part II of the following piece:
 http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/
 (The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the
 Commercial Realm).

 Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v.
 Lee, which is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly
 addressed the issue of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the
 Court dismissed a commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an
 antidiscrimination law as patently frivolous. Instead, Eugene refers to
 Justice Brennan's pre-Sherbert dissenting opinion in Crown. Whatever
 Justice Brennan's views in 1961, it is difficult to understand how they are
 a better representation of the Sherbert-era law than the following explicit
 statement of the Court in Lee, which was joined by Justice Brennan (as was
 Piggie Park):

 When followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as
 a matter of choice, the limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter
 of conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on the statutory schemes
 which are binding on others in that activity. Granting an exemption from
 social security taxes to an employer operates to impose the employer's
 religious faith on the employees.



 Accordingly, I don't think the ACLU's current position can be
 accurately described as a retreat from their support of Sherbert-era
 exemption rights. As Eugene notes in his post, the ACLU still opposes Smith
 and supports exemption rights outside the commercial context. As I note in
 my piece, this is also true of Americans United and the Brennan Center. The
 strong opposition of those organizations to extending exemption rights into
 the for-profit commercial realm has sometimes been misread as a reversal of
 their position on exemption rights in general (indeed, I myself have made
 that mistake in the past), but as I detail in the piece cited above, an
 examination of the full record shows that [l]iberals who opposed
 *Smith* in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including liberal
 organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to support
 religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of such
 exemptions to commercial businesses.

 - Jim



 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can

RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Scarberry, Mark
Apart from the other points with which I disagree:

Wow, Chip. You really think it’s OK to make the student recite the Pledge, as 
long as the student is permitted at the end to say “I don’t mean it”? Can I be 
required to burn a pinch of incense to the emperor as long as I am permitted 
afterwards to say that the emperor isn’t really a god?

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 5:32 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

If the compelled speech argument is constitutionally sufficient, permission to 
post a disclaiming sign may solve the problem. (It would be like letting a 
student say aloud I don't mean it after forcing her to recite the Pledge of 
Allegiance.)

If the compelled speech argument is NOT constitutionally sufficient, I think 
the photographers have no First A right to put up such a sign, though of course 
the NM legislature could permissibly accommodate the religious objection by 
permitting a vendor to post such a sign.  Away from the business site (on line 
or physical), the photographer of course is free to express her views on same 
sex marriage.



On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 7:37 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
I don’t have time right now to respond in a substantial way to Chip’s post. Let 
me just quote this language from the New Mexico Supreme Court’s decision in 
Elane Photography:

“Businesses that choose to be public accommodations must comply with the NMHRA, 
although such businesses retain their First Amendment rights to express their 
religious or political beliefs. They may, for example, post a disclaimer on 
their website or in their studio advertising that they oppose same-sex marriage 
but that they comply with applicable antidiscrimination laws.”

That’s not quite the same as saying that gay couples aren’t welcome, but it’s 
pretty close. Is the NM court right that the photographers have a 1st Am right 
to do so?

On the question whether religious liberty claims have anything to do with the 
compelled speech issue, if we believe that the “hybrid rights” part of Smith 
means anything, it might apply in this kind of case so that the combination of 
the claims to constitutional protection might create some synergy.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law









From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of Ira Lupu
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 4:22 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

I think the compelled speech issues, re: communicative work like photography, 
are interesting and sometimes difficult. I address those in an article I will 
post later this month.  All I want to say now is that religious motivation is 
irrelevant to the compelled speech argument.  (See W Va Bd of Educ v. Barnette.)

But Mark also say If [harm] depends on the message sent by the refusal, then 
we have an interesting viewpoint discrimination issue.  If, in 1965, Ollie's 
BBQ had put up a sign in the window that read Federal law says we must serve 
all, so we will, but n-s are not sincerely welcome, then he would have 
violated the Public Accommodations title of the Civil Rights Act (he would not 
have provided full and equal enjoyment of his restaurant without 
discrimination on the basis of race.)  Does Mark or anyone on this list really 
think that presents a serious First Amendment problem?  Ollie can write letters 
to Congress, and to the newspapers, and put signs on his lawn, all railing 
against the oppressive Civil Rights Act, but he cannot communicate that 
directly to customers on his business premises. If it were otherwise, the Act 
would be gutted entirely.  I think that no Justice who has served in the last 
50 years would take such a First A claim seriously.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 6:53 PM, Scarberry, Mark 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edumailto:mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:
I also think the florist and baker examples are weaker for the religious 
claimant, especially where the flowers and cakes are generic. But what if 
custom floral arrangements involve artistic choices by the florist? What if the 
cake is (as some are) a truly creative work of art? And do only high-end bakers 
get protection from violation of conscience? What if the florist or baker is 
asked to include particular words or other expressive content in the 
arrangement or the cake? (This from someone who argued against licensing 
requirements for sellers of flowers – protectionist provisions for florists who 
fear grocery stores’ selling of flowers

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Richard Friedman
, but the conscience of an individual photographer, florist,
 baker, or bed and breakfast owner less worthy of protection?Justice
 Kagan, at least back in 1996 when she was in the Clinton White House,
 appeared to recognize that the consciences of individuals operating small
 commercial businesses was worthy of protection under a RFRA regime.
 Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a Evelyn Smith who,
 for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units to a
 co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was
 “outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to
 hold that a state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion
 because the complainant is free to move to another state.”
 http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers





 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *James Oleske
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’
 (sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious
 exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full,
 but I want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of
 Eugene's analysis:

 Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions
 from antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the
 same under the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long
 championed.




 http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/


 Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial
 marketplace, which is the context generating almost all of the liberal
 concerns about exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's
 characterization of the law in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely
 the opposite argument at length in Part II of the following piece:
 http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/
 (The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the
 Commercial Realm).

 Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee,
 which is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed
 the issue of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court
 dismissed a commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an
 antidiscrimination law as patently frivolous. Instead, Eugene refers to
 Justice Brennan's pre-Sherbert dissenting opinion in Crown. Whatever
 Justice Brennan's views in 1961, it is difficult to understand how they are
 a better representation of the Sherbert-era law than the following explicit
 statement of the Court in Lee, which was joined by Justice Brennan (as was
 Piggie Park):

 When followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as a
 matter of choice, the limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter
 of conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on the statutory schemes
 which are binding on others in that activity. Granting an exemption from
 social security taxes to an employer operates to impose the employer's
 religious faith on the employees.



 Accordingly, I don't think the ACLU's current position can be accurately
 described as a retreat from their support of Sherbert-era exemption
 rights. As Eugene notes in his post, the ACLU still opposes Smith and
 supports exemption rights outside the commercial context. As I note in my
 piece, this is also true of Americans United and the Brennan Center. The
 strong opposition of those organizations to extending exemption rights into
 the for-profit commercial realm has sometimes been misread as a reversal of
 their position on exemption rights in general (indeed, I myself have made
 that mistake in the past), but as I detail in the piece cited above, an
 examination of the full record shows that [l]iberals who opposed
 *Smith* in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including liberal
 organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to support
 religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of such
 exemptions to commercial businesses.

 - Jim



 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.


   ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Richard Friedman
 *Subject:* Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’
 (sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious
 exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full,
 but I want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of
 Eugene's analysis:

 Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions
 from antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the
 same under the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long
 championed.




 http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/


 Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial
 marketplace, which is the context generating almost all of the liberal
 concerns about exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's
 characterization of the law in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely
 the opposite argument at length in Part II of the following piece:
 http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/
 (The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the
 Commercial Realm).

 Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee,
 which is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed
 the issue of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court
 dismissed a commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an
 antidiscrimination law as patently frivolous. Instead, Eugene refers to
 Justice Brennan's pre-Sherbert dissenting opinion in Crown. Whatever
 Justice Brennan's views in 1961, it is difficult to understand how they are
 a better representation of the Sherbert-era law than the following explicit
 statement of the Court in Lee, which was joined by Justice Brennan (as was
 Piggie Park):

 When followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as a
 matter of choice, the limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter
 of conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on the statutory schemes
 which are binding on others in that activity. Granting an exemption from
 social security taxes to an employer operates to impose the employer's
 religious faith on the employees.



 Accordingly, I don't think the ACLU's current position can be accurately
 described as a retreat from their support of Sherbert-era exemption
 rights. As Eugene notes in his post, the ACLU still opposes Smith and
 supports exemption rights outside the commercial context. As I note in my
 piece, this is also true of Americans United and the Brennan Center. The
 strong opposition of those organizations to extending exemption rights into
 the for-profit commercial realm has sometimes been misread as a reversal of
 their position on exemption rights in general (indeed, I myself have made
 that mistake in the past), but as I detail in the piece cited above, an
 examination of the full record shows that [l]iberals who opposed *Smith*
 in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including liberal organizations,
 professors, and politicians — largely continue to support religious
 exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of such exemptions
 to commercial businesses.

 - Jim



 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.


   ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.


 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get

Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread James Oleske
Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’
(sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious
exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full,
but I want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of
Eugene's analysis:

Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions from
antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the same
under the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long
championed.


http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/

Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial
marketplace, which is the context generating almost all of the liberal
concerns about exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's
characterization of the law in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely
the opposite argument at length in Part II of the following piece:
http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/
(The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the
Commercial Realm).

Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee,
which is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed
the issue of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court
dismissed a commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an
antidiscrimination law as patently frivolous. Instead, Eugene refers to
Justice Brennan's pre-Sherbert dissenting opinion in Crown. Whatever
Justice Brennan's views in 1961, it is difficult to understand how they are
a better representation of the Sherbert-era law than the following explicit
statement of the Court in Lee, which was joined by Justice Brennan (as was
Piggie Park):

When followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as a
matter of choice, the limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter
of conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on the statutory schemes
which are binding on others in that activity. Granting an exemption from
social security taxes to an employer operates to impose the employer's
religious faith on the employees.

Accordingly, I don't think the ACLU's current position can be accurately
described as a retreat from their support of Sherbert-era exemption
rights. As Eugene notes in his post, the ACLU still opposes Smith and
supports exemption rights outside the commercial context. As I note in my
piece, this is also true of Americans United and the Brennan Center. The
strong opposition of those organizations to extending exemption rights into
the for-profit commercial realm has sometimes been misread as a reversal of
their position on exemption rights in general (indeed, I myself have made
that mistake in the past), but as I detail in the piece cited above, an
examination of the full record shows that [l]iberals who opposed *Smith*
in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including liberal organizations,
professors, and politicians — largely continue to support religious
exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of such exemptions
to commercial businesses.

- Jim
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Gaubatz, Derek
“[l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including 
liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to 
support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of 
such exemptions to commercial businesses.

I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many individuals 
depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do liberals see the 
conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy of protection, but the 
conscience of an individual photographer, florist, baker, or bed and breakfast 
owner less worthy of protection?Justice Kagan, at least back in 1996 when 
she was in the Clinton White House, appeared to recognize that the consciences 
of individuals operating small commercial businesses was worthy of protection 
under a RFRA regime.   Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a 
Evelyn Smith who, for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units 
to a co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was 
“outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold that a 
state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because the 
complainant is free to move to another state.”   
http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of James Oleske
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’ 
(sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious 
exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full, but I 
want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of Eugene's 
analysis:
Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions from 
antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the same under 
the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long championed.

http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/

Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial marketplace, 
which is the context generating almost all of the liberal concerns about 
exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's characterization of the law 
in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely the opposite argument at length 
in Part II of the following piece: 
http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/ 
(The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the 
Commercial Realm).

Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee, which 
is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed the issue 
of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court dismissed a 
commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an antidiscrimination law as 
patently frivolous. Instead, Eugene refers to Justice Brennan's pre-Sherbert 
dissenting opinion in Crown. Whatever Justice Brennan's views in 1961, it is 
difficult to understand how they are a better representation of the 
Sherbert-era law than the following explicit statement of the Court in Lee, 
which was joined by Justice Brennan (as was Piggie Park):
When followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as a matter 
of choice, the limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter of 
conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on the statutory schemes which 
are binding on others in that activity. Granting an exemption from social 
security taxes to an employer operates to impose the employer's religious faith 
on the employees.

Accordingly, I don't think the ACLU's current position can be accurately 
described as a retreat from their support of Sherbert-era exemption rights. 
As Eugene notes in his post, the ACLU still opposes Smith and supports 
exemption rights outside the commercial context. As I note in my piece, this is 
also true of Americans United and the Brennan Center. The strong opposition of 
those organizations to extending exemption rights into the for-profit 
commercial realm has sometimes been misread as a reversal of their position on 
exemption rights in general (indeed, I myself have made that mistake in the 
past), but as I detail in the piece cited above, an examination of the full 
record shows that [l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 
1993 — including liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely 
continue to support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the 
extension of such exemptions to commercial businesses.
- Jim

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Greg Lipper
Beyond the question of commerce/non-commerce, there is a broader distinction 
between accommodations that harm others and accommodations that do not. This 
distinction was reflected in the Supreme Court’s opinions in United States v. 
Lee (among other pre-Smith cases), Cutter v. Wilkinson (upholding RLUIPA 
against Establishment Clause challenge), and in Justice Ginsburg’s dissent in 
Hobby Lobby and concurrence in Holt v. Hobbs.

Quite apart from Hobby Lobby’s status as a for-profit corporation, we 
(Americans United) opposed the Hobby Lobby exemption because it had the effect 
of stripping otherwise available healthcare coverage from employees’ 
compensation. We would have opposed that exemption even if the company was not 
a for-profit corporation – there were innocent third parties who were losing an 
important part of their employment compensation as a result of the exemption.

There are some accommodations (a prisoner who wants to wear a beard, an 
individual who wants to use peyote (or wine, for that matter) as part of a 
religious ceremony, etc. etc.) that do not harm third parties. There are others 
(withholding healthcare from others, exemptions from antidiscrimination law) 
that harm third parties directly. That distinction was respected in the 
pre-Smith cases and highlighted again in Cutter, but it has come under attack 
in recent rounds of RFRA litigation.



On Apr 1, 2015, at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek 
dgaub...@imb.orgmailto:dgaub...@imb.org wrote:

“[l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including 
liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to 
support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of 
such exemptions to commercial businesses.

I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many individuals 
depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do liberals see the 
conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy of protection, but the 
conscience of an individual photographer, florist, baker, or bed and breakfast 
owner less worthy of protection?Justice Kagan, at least back in 1996 when 
she was in the Clinton White House, appeared to recognize that the consciences 
of individuals operating small commercial businesses was worthy of protection 
under a RFRA regime.   Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a 
Evelyn Smith who, for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units 
to a co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was 
“outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold that a 
state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because the 
complainant is free to move to another state.”  
http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers


From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of James Oleske
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’ 
(sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious 
exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full, but I 
want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of Eugene's 
analysis:
Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions from 
antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the same under 
the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long championed.

http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/

Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial marketplace, 
which is the context generating almost all of the liberal concerns about 
exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's characterization of the law 
in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely the opposite argument at length 
in Part II of the following 
piece:http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/
 (The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the 
Commercial Realm).

Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee, which 
is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed the issue 
of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court dismissed a 
commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an antidiscrimination law as 
patently frivolous. Instead, Eugene refers to Justice Brennan's pre-Sherbert 
dissenting opinion in Crown. Whatever Justice Brennan's views in 1961, it is 
difficult to understand how they are a better representation of the 
Sherbert-era law than the following explicit statement of the Court in Lee, 
which was joined by Justice Brennan

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread James Oleske
I discuss this question -- which is about the merits of the Sherbert-era
distinction between commercial and non-commercial, not the existence of the
distinction -- in another recent piece:

There was very good reason, however, for the earlier consensus that owners
of for-profit businesses must comply with secular laws regardless of their
religious beliefs. In the commercial context, religious exemptions will
almost always impose burdens on third parties, whether employees,
customers, or business competitors. As a result, such exemptions implicate
a rule “with a long history in libertarian thought”— that rights are
limited by the need for “prevention of tangible harm to specifiable others
without their consent.” Even in its pre-*Smith *jurisprudence, which held
that exemptions from generally applicable laws were sometimes required, the
Supreme Court gave force to this limitation, refusing to exempt an employer
from the Social Security system because doing so would “operate[] to impose
the employer’s religious faith on the employees.” In so reasoning, the
Court was acting in accord with the general principle espoused by Justice
Jackson four decades earlier that the “limitations which of necessity bound
religious freedom . . . begin to operate whenever activities begin to
collide with liberties of others or of the public.” Or as Justice Ginsburg
has put it more recently, “with respect to free exercise claims no less
than free speech claims, ‘your right to swing your arms ends just where the
other man’s nose begins.’”


http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2400100 (pp. 39-40)

As I discuss in footnote 149 of the same piece, the Court has long made a
similar commercial/non-commercial distinction in its free association
jurisprudence.

- Jim

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 11:51 AM, Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org wrote:

  “[l]iberals who opposed *Smith* in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 —
 including liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely
 continue to support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing
 the extension of such exemptions to commercial businesses.



 I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many
 individuals depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do
 liberals see the conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy
 of protection, but the conscience of an individual photographer, florist,
 baker, or bed and breakfast owner less worthy of protection?Justice
 Kagan, at least back in 1996 when she was in the Clinton White House,
 appeared to recognize that the consciences of individuals operating small
 commercial businesses was worthy of protection under a RFRA regime.
 Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a Evelyn Smith who,
 for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units to a
 co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was
 “outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold
 that a state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because
 the complainant is free to move to another state.”
 http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers





 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *James Oleske
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’
 (sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious
 exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full,
 but I want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of
 Eugene's analysis:

 Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions
 from antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the
 same under the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long
 championed.




 http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/


 Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial
 marketplace, which is the context generating almost all of the liberal
 concerns about exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's
 characterization of the law in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely
 the opposite argument at length in Part II of the following piece:
 http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/
 (The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the
 Commercial Realm).

 Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee,
 which is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed
 the issue of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court
 dismissed a commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread James Oleske
The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the
Court might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but
rather, a strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm
that can be overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the
presumption (a third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead
simply discarded the Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further
than the pre-Smith law.

- Jim


On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

 I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se --
 imagine a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with
 religious dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.
 Liberals oppose exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties --
 Hobby Lobby (those female employees still do not have contraceptive
 coverage) or wedding vendor exemptions from public accommodations laws
 (those exemptions allow material and dignitary injury to potential
 customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other family members of Amish
 employees, as well as others in the social insurance pool.

 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org wrote:

  “[l]iberals who opposed *Smith* in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 —
 including liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely
 continue to support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing
 the extension of such exemptions to commercial businesses.



 I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many
 individuals depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do
 liberals see the conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy
 of protection, but the conscience of an individual photographer, florist,
 baker, or bed and breakfast owner less worthy of protection?Justice
 Kagan, at least back in 1996 when she was in the Clinton White House,
 appeared to recognize that the consciences of individuals operating small
 commercial businesses was worthy of protection under a RFRA regime.
 Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a Evelyn Smith who,
 for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units to a
 co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was
 “outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold
 that a state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because
 the complainant is free to move to another state.”
 http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers





 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *James Oleske
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’
 (sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious
 exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full,
 but I want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of
 Eugene's analysis:

 Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions
 from antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the
 same under the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long
 championed.




 http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/


 Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial
 marketplace, which is the context generating almost all of the liberal
 concerns about exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's
 characterization of the law in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely
 the opposite argument at length in Part II of the following piece:
 http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/
 (The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the
 Commercial Realm).

 Nowhere in his post does Eugene acknowledge either United States v. Lee,
 which is the only Sherbert-era case in which the Court explicitly addressed
 the issue of commercial exemptions, or Piggie Park, where the Court
 dismissed a commercial businesses' claim for an exemption from an
 antidiscrimination law as patently frivolous. Instead, Eugene refers to
 Justice Brennan's pre-Sherbert dissenting opinion in Crown. Whatever
 Justice Brennan's views in 1961, it is difficult to understand how they are
 a better representation of the Sherbert-era law than the following explicit
 statement of the Court in Lee, which was joined by Justice Brennan (as was
 Piggie Park):

 When followers of a particular sect enter into commercial activity as a
 matter of choice, the limits they accept on their own conduct as a matter
 of conscience and faith are not to be superimposed on the statutory schemes

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Alan E Brownstein
I appreciate your point, Nelson. And I think the principle that private 
citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with other citizens’ 
religious observance deserves respect. Standing alone, it would often be 
dispositive.  Where we disagree, I think, is that in religious exemption cases 
I see two principles here that deserve our respect. The one I just quoted above 
and the principle that the majority and government should not prohibit or 
burden another citizen's religious observance. I think, you can tell me if I'm 
wrong, that you would agree that this principle standing alone also deserves 
respect. If there is no harm to third parties, you would support religious 
exemptions.


Then the question becomes what do we do when these two principles are in 
conflict with each other. I don't think either trumps the other all of the 
time. I think as the harm to third parties increases, the principle that 
citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with the other citizen's 
religious observance outweighs the religious liberty principle. I understand 
you to be saying that the religious liberty principle is always trumped in 
these cases without regard to the magnitude of the costs involved.


There are a lot of religious accommodations that result in third parties 
incurring some cost.  A RLUIPA land use accommodation might result in some 
neighboring homeowner, business or farmer incurring some diminution of value in 
their property. A public university accommodation shifting move-in day so that 
it doesn't fall on the Jewish High Holy days may require a shift in the 
academic calendar that inconveniences the travel plans of specific faculty, 
students and their families. A court accommodating the religious obligations of 
a religious attorney or witness may delay or otherwise increase the cost of 
litigation. A law banning male circumcision exempts Jewish families from its 
requirements. Does the existence of harm to third parties in these situations 
and others require the invalidation of all of these accommodations without 
regard to the magnitude of the harm borne by third parties?


Alan



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
on behalf of Nelson Tebbe nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu
Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 1:38 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



Alan, I can’t speak for others who have been defending a principle against 
burden-shifting to third parties, but I do not believe it prohibits religion 
accommodations that result in costs to the government or to the public. Rather, 
the principle prohibits government accommodations that shift meaningful costs 
from religious citizens to other identifiable private citizens. And the reason 
for this is easy to articulate and deeply rooted — private citizens should not 
have to bear the costs associated with other citizens’ religious observance.

On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:07 PM, Alan E Brownstein 
aebrownst...@ucdavis.edumailto:aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu wrote:

The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him correctly, is that 
it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be accepted if it causes 
any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim includes the general public or 
the public fisc in third party.) I think many liberals believe (or at least 
they used to believe) that rights are expensive political goods. We protect 
them even if we have to incur some cost or harm to third parties or the public 
in order to do so. Of course, that leaves open the difficult question of 
determining when the price for protecting a right is too high. (And when we are 
talking about the right to discriminate in employment or public accommodations, 
leaving religious institutions aside, the price is almost always too high.) But 
I see no historical consensus that we only protect freedom of speech or 
religious liberty when the cost of doing so is zero. That certainly wasn't the 
understanding of freedom of speech that Justice Brandeis defended in his famous 
dissents on which contemporary free speech doctrine is based.

Indeed, the argument that we should only accept zero cost religious 
accommodations is not only inconsistent with the way we generally understand 
rights, it seems inconsistent with the way we evaluate government regulations 
generally. It is one thing to argue that we should reject a religious exemption 
when the harm or cost of granting it is too high. That position is consistent 
with the general cost benefit analysis we use to discuss any government 
decision. But why should we only accept zero cost religious accommodations? We 
routinely allow government to enact laws that result in some costs, burdens, 
and harms to third parties or the general public that serve a variety of 
purposes.

Alan



___
To post, send message

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread K Chen
As someone putting a wedding together, I can't explain the lack of sympathy
for the wedding photographer as anything but thinking that their work is
essentially interchangeable. It is not, unfortunately, and it is priced
accordingly. Every single photographer of them seems to take their business
very, very personally. More to the point, it is a personal, professional
service which is by its nature selective compared to the harm done by
impersonal corporations excluding goods and services when they otherwise
serve the public.

A principled difference can be drawn between accommodating personal,
inherently selective commercial businesses and businesses that are open to
the public at large. The vast majority of commercial transactions are from
businesses who sell to the public, or their business community, on a
non-discriminatory basis. When such a business denies goods or services to
a class of person, that is an inherently political act. Such a businesses
is not just refusing the do business with an individual or class, they are
making an attempt to exclude them from *the definition of the public
itself. *They are thus doing harm to both individual and society by
imposing their will on what constitutes the political community. This harm
grows geometrically with each exclusionary actor.

Individual consumers on the other hand, are inherently selective. If you
need one loaf of bread this week, you will patronize precisely one baker
this week. If you need a salary, you will work one, maybe two jobs. The
harm of being denied service by a consumer (or laborer) because of their
beliefs has a societal harm, if any, nearly indistinguishable to being
denied for any other reason.

Some services should fall in between. I'm not convinced for the florist and
the and the baker, but I'm sympathetic to the photographer, the doctor, the
lawyer (ethical obligations notwithstanding) , the political consultant,
the ghost writer...

I don't know how far that gets liberals of course, but it *is* a
difference beyond mere size and corporate form.

Kevin Chen

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org wrote:

  “[l]iberals who opposed *Smith* in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 —
 including liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely
 continue to support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing
 the extension of such exemptions to commercial businesses.



 I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many
 individuals depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do
 liberals see the conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy
 of protection, but the conscience of an individual photographer, florist,
 baker, or bed and breakfast owner less worthy of protection?Justice
 Kagan, at least back in 1996 when she was in the Clinton White House,
 appeared to recognize that the consciences of individuals operating small
 commercial businesses was worthy of protection under a RFRA regime.
 Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a Evelyn Smith who,
 for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units to a
 co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was
 “outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold
 that a state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because
 the complainant is free to move to another state.”
 http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers





 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *James Oleske
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



 Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’
 (sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious
 exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full,
 but I want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of
 Eugene's analysis:

 Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions
 from antidiscrimination laws. But religious objectors could have done the
 same under the Sherbert-era Free Exercise Clause that the ACLU had long
 championed.




 http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/volokh-conspiracy/wp/2015/04/01/many-liberals-sensible-retreat-from-the-old-justice-brennanaclu-position-on-religious-exemptions/


 Insofar as we're talking about discrimination in the commercial
 marketplace, which is the context generating almost all of the liberal
 concerns about exemptions today, I have to disagree with Eugene's
 characterization of the law in the Sherbert era. Indeed, I make precisely
 the opposite argument at length in Part II of the following piece:
 http://harvardlawreview.org/2015/01/the-born-again-champion-of-conscience/
 (The Real Issue: The Unprecedented Expansion of Exemption Rights into the
 Commercial Realm

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread K Chen
private citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with other
citizens’ religious observance. 

Except they do. When my co-workers take time off work to observe religious
restrictions, everyone else's work increases. Sometimes noticeably. And
trying to sort between meaningful costs and *de minimis* costs is going
to be tricky. The difference might be drawn between third parties being
forced to subsidize a religious belief (I cannot eat ham, so you all have
to chip in for a steak sandwich) and merely being asked to bear with it.

Kevin Chen

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 4:38 PM, Nelson Tebbe nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu
wrote:



  Alan, I can’t speak for others who have been defending a principle
 against burden-shifting to third parties, but I do not believe it prohibits
 religion accommodations that result in costs to the government or to the
 public. Rather, the principle prohibits government accommodations that
 shift meaningful costs from religious citizens to other identifiable
 private citizens. And the reason for this is easy to articulate and deeply
 rooted — private citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with
 other citizens’ religious observance.

  On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:07 PM, Alan E Brownstein aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu
 wrote:

  The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him
 correctly, is that it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be
 accepted if it causes any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim
 includes the general public or the public fisc in third party.) I think
 many liberals believe (or at least they used to believe) that rights are
 expensive political goods. We protect them even if we have to incur some
 cost or harm to third parties or the public in order to do so. Of course,
 that leaves open the difficult question of determining when the price for
 protecting a right is too high. (And when we are talking about the right to
 discriminate in employment or public accommodations, leaving religious
 institutions aside, the price is almost always too high.) But I see no
 historical consensus that we only protect freedom of speech or religious
 liberty when the cost of doing so is zero. That certainly wasn't the
 understanding of freedom of speech that Justice Brandeis defended in his
 famous dissents on which contemporary free speech doctrine is based.

  Indeed, the argument that we should only accept zero cost religious
 accommodations is not only inconsistent with the way we generally
 understand rights, it seems inconsistent with the way we evaluate
 government regulations generally. It is one thing to argue that we should
 reject a religious exemption when the harm or cost of granting it is too
 high. That position is consistent with the general cost benefit analysis we
 use to discuss any government decision. But why should we only accept zero
 cost religious accommodations? We routinely allow government to enact laws
 that result in some costs, burdens, and harms to third parties or the
 general public that serve a variety of purposes.

  Alan


  --
 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu on behalf of James Oleske 
 jole...@lclark.edu
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 1, 2015 12:22 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

   The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the
 Court might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but
 rather, a strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm
 that can be overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the
 presumption (a third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead
 simply discarded the Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further
 than the pre-Smith law.

  - Jim


   On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

  I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se --
 imagine a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with
 religious dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.
 Liberals oppose exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties --
 Hobby Lobby (those female employees still do not have contraceptive
 coverage) or wedding vendor exemptions from public accommodations laws
 (those exemptions allow material and dignitary injury to potential
 customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other family members of Amish
 employees, as well as others in the social insurance pool.


 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
I think Prof. Chen is substantially correct, but I believe, more than ever, 
that it's the kind of problem that can ( and should) be handled outside legal 
constraints. Why would I want to hire a wedding photographer who so clearly 
won't view the day as affirmatively special?  Ditto the band?  But I really 
can't work up much sympathy for the florist or baker. They should be treated 
under the general rubric of public accommodations and the Civil Rights Act of 
1964. I'm sure there were florists and bakers who objected to mixes-race 
marriages and could cite the purported curse on Ham. It really doesn't (and 
shouldn't) matter.

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:56 PM, K Chen tzn...@gmail.commailto:tzn...@gmail.com 
wrote:

As someone putting a wedding together, I can't explain the lack of sympathy for 
the wedding photographer as anything but thinking that their work is 
essentially interchangeable. It is not, unfortunately, and it is priced 
accordingly. Every single photographer of them seems to take their business 
very, very personally. More to the point, it is a personal, professional 
service which is by its nature selective compared to the harm done by 
impersonal corporations excluding goods and services when they otherwise serve 
the public.

A principled difference can be drawn between accommodating personal, inherently 
selective commercial businesses and businesses that are open to the public at 
large. The vast majority of commercial transactions are from businesses who 
sell to the public, or their business community, on a non-discriminatory basis. 
When such a business denies goods or services to a class of person, that is an 
inherently political act. Such a businesses is not just refusing the do 
business with an individual or class, they are making an attempt to exclude 
them from the definition of the public itself. They are thus doing harm to both 
individual and society by imposing their will on what constitutes the political 
community. This harm grows geometrically with each exclusionary actor.

Individual consumers on the other hand, are inherently selective. If you need 
one loaf of bread this week, you will patronize precisely one baker this week. 
If you need a salary, you will work one, maybe two jobs. The harm of being 
denied service by a consumer (or laborer) because of their beliefs has a 
societal harm, if any, nearly indistinguishable to being denied for any other 
reason.

Some services should fall in between. I'm not convinced for the florist and the 
and the baker, but I'm sympathetic to the photographer, the doctor, the lawyer 
(ethical obligations notwithstanding) , the political consultant, the ghost 
writer...

I don't know how far that gets liberals of course, but it is a difference 
beyond mere size and corporate form.

Kevin Chen

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek 
dgaub...@imb.orgmailto:dgaub...@imb.org wrote:
“[l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including 
liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to 
support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of 
such exemptions to commercial businesses.

I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many individuals 
depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do liberals see the 
conscience of individuals like Sherbert or Thomas worthy of protection, but the 
conscience of an individual photographer, florist, baker, or bed and breakfast 
owner less worthy of protection?Justice Kagan, at least back in 1996 when 
she was in the Clinton White House, appeared to recognize that the consciences 
of individuals operating small commercial businesses was worthy of protection 
under a RFRA regime.   Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a 
Evelyn Smith who, for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units 
to a co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was 
“outrageous.”   She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold that a 
state law does not impose a substantial burden on religion because the 
complainant is free to move to another state.”   
http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers


From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 On Behalf Of James Oleske
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

Eugene has a new post up on Volokh Conspiracy entitled, Many liberals’ 
(sensible) retreat from the old Justice Brennan/ACLU position on religious 
exemptions. The piece is lengthy, and I recommend folks read it in full, but I 
want to take issue with the following assertion at the heart of Eugene's 
analysis:
Yes, religious objectors can use these RFRAs to try to get exemptions from

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Levinson, Sanford V
Non-Jews are under no obligation not to eat pork (or adhere to almost all of 
the other 612 mitzvot). So there is no stigma attached to any non-Jew who wants 
to buy a ham at a kosher butchery. That can't be said with regard to the 
florist who refuses to sell a bouquet for use at a same-sex marriage, who is 
necessarily condoning the presumptively sinful conduct. Ironically or not, the 
only person a Jewish butcher might be upset with is another Jew. This 
underscores the fact that very few Jewish laws are universal.  This is not 
true of most purported Christian precepts (beginning with the widely shared 
view among many a Evangelicals that I'm damned for failure to accept the 
teaching of John 3:16 (which I know by heart having memorized it some 65 years 
ago in order to earn a Bible certificate from the state of North Carolina).

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Apr 1, 2015, at 3:44 PM, Will Esser 
willes...@yahoo.commailto:willes...@yahoo.com wrote:

Chip,

Can you expound on your argument that wedding vendor exemptions from public 
accommodations laws allow material and dignitary injury to potential 
customers and that liberals only oppose exemptions that impinge on the 
welfare of third parties?  It seems that both sides agree that the kosher 
butcher deserves a religious exemption, and yet granting that exemption imposes 
some cost on third parties (i.e. anyone who wishes to purchase pork must go 
elsewhere, which could involve multiple trips to different butchers, or may 
mean spending more time and money to go to a butcher further away).  So it's 
not really that there is no cost to third parties, but perhaps simply a cost 
which society is more ready to accept (i.e. Go buy your pork somewhere else.)

As I understood the third-party harm argument in Hobby Lobby, the argument 
was that without insurance coverage, female Hobby Lobby employees would be 
unable to afford coverage of the particular, objectionable contraceptives and 
therefore the third party harm was equivalent to total lack of access.

Given modern changes in societal perspectives, I have not heard the same 
argument about a total lack of access when it comes to wedding vendors for 
same-sex wedding ceremonies.  Under the assumption the goods and services are 
otherwise generally available in the marketplace (i.e. there are plenty of 
wedding photographers, bakers, etc. who would be happy for the business of 
same-sex weddings), what is the distinguishing factor which causes material 
and dignitary injury in the wedding vendor exemptions scenario but not in the 
kosher butcher example?  In both, the customers want a service which they can 
get in the marketplace (although perhaps not from the exact person or place 
they want it).  And in both, the reason for not providing the service is the 
same (i.e. violation of a sincerely held religious belief).

Thanks in advance for clarification.

Will

Will Esser
Charlotte, North Carolina



From: James Oleske jole...@lclark.edumailto:jole...@lclark.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 3:22 PM
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the Court 
might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but rather, a 
strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm that can be 
overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the presumption (a 
third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead simply discarded the 
Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further than the pre-Smith law.

- Jim




On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu 
icl...@law.gwu.edumailto:icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se -- imagine 
a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with religious 
dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.  Liberals oppose 
exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties -- Hobby Lobby (those 
female employees still do not have contraceptive coverage) or wedding vendor 
exemptions from public accommodations laws (those exemptions allow material and 
dignitary injury to potential customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other 
family members of Amish employees, as well as others in the social insurance 
pool.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek 
dgaub...@imb.orgmailto:dgaub...@imb.org wrote:
“[l]iberals who opposed Smith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including 
liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to 
support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of 
such exemptions to commercial businesses.

I’m not sure I’m seeing the principled distinction.   Do not many individuals 
depend for their livelihood on commercial businesses?   Why do liberals see

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Alan E Brownstein
The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him correctly, is that 
it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be accepted if it causes 
any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim includes the general public or 
the public fisc in third party.) I think many liberals believe (or at least 
they used to believe) that rights are expensive political goods. We protect 
them even if we have to incur some cost or harm to third parties or the public 
in order to do so. Of course, that leaves open the difficult question of 
determining when the price for protecting a right is too high. (And when we are 
talking about the right to discriminate in employment or public accommodations, 
leaving religious institutions aside, the price is almost always too high.) But 
I see no historical consensus that we only protect freedom of speech or 
religious liberty when the cost of doing so is zero. That certainly wasn't the 
understanding of freedom of speech that Justice Brandeis defended in his famous 
dissents on which contemporary free speech doctrine is based.


Indeed, the argument that we should only accept zero cost religious 
accommodations is not only inconsistent with the way we generally understand 
rights, it seems inconsistent with the way we evaluate government regulations 
generally. It is one thing to argue that we should reject a religious exemption 
when the harm or cost of granting it is too high. That position is consistent 
with the general cost benefit analysis we use to discuss any government 
decision. But why should we only accept zero cost religious accommodations? We 
routinely allow government to enact laws that result in some costs, burdens, 
and harms to third parties or the general public that serve a variety of 
purposes.


Alan



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
on behalf of James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu
Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 12:22 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the Court 
might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but rather, a 
strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm that can be 
overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the presumption (a 
third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead simply discarded the 
Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further than the pre-Smith law.

- Jim


On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu 
icl...@law.gwu.edumailto:icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se -- imagine 
a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with religious 
dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.  Liberals oppose 
exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties -- Hobby Lobby (those 
female employees still do not have contraceptive coverage) or wedding vendor 
exemptions from public accommodations laws (those exemptions allow material and 
dignitary injury to potential customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other 
family members of Amish employees, as well as others in the social insurance 
pool.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Nelson Tebbe


Alan, I can’t speak for others who have been defending a principle against 
burden-shifting to third parties, but I do not believe it prohibits religion 
accommodations that result in costs to the government or to the public. Rather, 
the principle prohibits government accommodations that shift meaningful costs 
from religious citizens to other identifiable private citizens. And the reason 
for this is easy to articulate and deeply rooted — private citizens should not 
have to bear the costs associated with other citizens’ religious observance.

On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:07 PM, Alan E Brownstein 
aebrownst...@ucdavis.edumailto:aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu wrote:

The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him correctly, is that 
it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be accepted if it causes 
any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim includes the general public or 
the public fisc in third party.) I think many liberals believe (or at least 
they used to believe) that rights are expensive political goods. We protect 
them even if we have to incur some cost or harm to third parties or the public 
in order to do so. Of course, that leaves open the difficult question of 
determining when the price for protecting a right is too high. (And when we are 
talking about the right to discriminate in employment or public accommodations, 
leaving religious institutions aside, the price is almost always too high.) But 
I see no historical consensus that we only protect freedom of speech or 
religious liberty when the cost of doing so is zero. That certainly wasn't the 
understanding of freedom of speech that Justice Brandeis defended in his famous 
dissents on which contemporary free speech doctrine is based.

Indeed, the argument that we should only accept zero cost religious 
accommodations is not only inconsistent with the way we generally understand 
rights, it seems inconsistent with the way we evaluate government regulations 
generally. It is one thing to argue that we should reject a religious exemption 
when the harm or cost of granting it is too high. That position is consistent 
with the general cost benefit analysis we use to discuss any government 
decision. But why should we only accept zero cost religious accommodations? We 
routinely allow government to enact laws that result in some costs, burdens, 
and harms to third parties or the general public that serve a variety of 
purposes.

Alan



From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
on behalf of James Oleske jole...@lclark.edumailto:jole...@lclark.edu
Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 12:22 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the Court 
might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but rather, a 
strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm that can be 
overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the presumption (a 
third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead simply discarded the 
Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further than the pre-Smith law.

- Jim


On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu 
icl...@law.gwu.edumailto:icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:
I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se -- imagine 
a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with religious 
dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.  Liberals oppose 
exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties -- Hobby Lobby (those 
female employees still do not have contraceptive coverage) or wedding vendor 
exemptions from public accommodations laws (those exemptions allow material and 
dignitary injury to potential customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other 
family members of Amish employees, as well as others in the social insurance 
pool.


___
To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Will Esser
Chip,
Can you expound on your argument that wedding vendor exemptions from public 
accommodations laws allow material and dignitary injury to potential 
customers and that liberals only oppose exemptions that impinge on the 
welfare of third parties?  It seems that both sides agree that the kosher 
butcher deserves a religious exemption, and yet granting that exemption imposes 
some cost on third parties (i.e. anyone who wishes to purchase pork must go 
elsewhere, which could involve multiple trips to different butchers, or may 
mean spending more time and money to go to a butcher further away).  So it's 
not really that there is no cost to third parties, but perhaps simply a cost 
which society is more ready to accept (i.e. Go buy your pork somewhere else.)
As I understood the third-party harm argument in Hobby Lobby, the argument 
was that without insurance coverage, female Hobby Lobby employees would be 
unable to afford coverage of the particular, objectionable contraceptives and 
therefore the third party harm was equivalent to total lack of access.  

Given modern changes in societal perspectives, I have not heard the same 
argument about a total lack of access when it comes to wedding vendors for 
same-sex wedding ceremonies.  Under the assumption the goods and services are 
otherwise generally available in the marketplace (i.e. there are plenty of 
wedding photographers, bakers, etc. who would be happy for the business of 
same-sex weddings), what is the distinguishing factor which causes material 
and dignitary injury in the wedding vendor exemptions scenario but not in the 
kosher butcher example?  In both, the customers want a service which they can 
get in the marketplace (although perhaps not from the exact person or place 
they want it).  And in both, the reason for not providing the service is the 
same (i.e. violation of a sincerely held religious belief).  

Thanks in advance for clarification.  

Will
 Will Esser 
Charlotte, North Carolina

  From: James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu 
 Sent: Wednesday, April 1, 2015 3:22 PM
 Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights
   
The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the Court 
might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but rather, a 
strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm that can be 
overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the presumption (a 
third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead simply discarded the 
Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further than the pre-Smith law.

- Jim




On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se -- imagine 
a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with religious 
dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.  Liberals oppose 
exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties -- Hobby Lobby (those 
female employees still do not have contraceptive coverage) or wedding vendor 
exemptions from public accommodations laws (those exemptions allow material and 
dignitary injury to potential customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other 
family members of Amish employees, as well as others in the social insurance 
pool.
On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:51 PM, Gaubatz, Derek dgaub...@imb.org wrote:

“[l]iberals who opposedSmith in 1990 and supported RFRA in 1993 — including 
liberal organizations, professors, and politicians — largely continue to 
support religious exemptions for individuals, while opposing the extension of 
such exemptions to commercial businesses. I’m not sure I’m seeing the 
principled distinction.   Do not many individuals depend for their livelihood 
on commercial businesses?   Why do liberals see the conscience of individuals 
like Sherbert or Thomas worthy of protection, but the conscience of an 
individual photographer, florist, baker, or bed and breakfast owner less worthy 
of protection?    Justice Kagan, at least back in 1996 when she was in the 
Clinton White House, appeared to recognize that the consciences of individuals 
operating small commercial businesses was worthy of protection under a RFRA 
regime.   Commenting on the short shrift given to the claim of a Evelyn Smith 
who, for religious reasons, did not want to rent one of her units to a 
co-habitating couple, Kagan noted that the court’s reasoning was “outrageous.”  
 She wrote that it was “almost as if a court were to hold that a state law does 
not impose a substantial burden on religion because the complainant is free to 
move to another state.”  
http://www.brookings.edu/research/papers/2010/06/23-kagan-rogers  From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]On Behalf Of James Oleske
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 2:25 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread James Oleske
Following up on Alan and Nelson's discussion of third-party burdens, I
think it might be helpful to identify two separate legal issues that are
impacted by such burdens:

1. The issue of whether a party has a right to a religious exemption in a
given case.
2. The issue of whether a discretionary legislative decision to grant an
exemption in a given situation violates the Establishment Clause.

I only meant to be addressing Issue #1, and I think the Sherbert-era
decisions are best read as not requiring exemptions as a matter of right
when such exemptions would burden identifiable third parties. And I think
the Lee language is best explained as a recognition that exemptions for
commercial businesses will almost always impose burdens on third parties,
whether employees, customers, or business competitors. I don't think,
however, that burdens shouldered by the government or the public at large
qualified as a third-party burdens under the Sherbert-era decisions, as
evidenced by the exemption required in Sherbert itself.

As for Issue #2, my view of the Establishment Clause limitations on
exemptions is not as robust as Nelson's, and I think legislatures can
likely require burdens on third parties that go beyond the burdens that the
Sherbert-era Court would have imposed in granting exemptions as a matter of
right.

- Jim


On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 2:46 PM, Alan E Brownstein aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu
wrote:

   I appreciate your point, Nelson. And I think the principle
 that private citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with
 other citizens’ religious observance deserves respect. Standing alone, it
 would often be dispositive.  Where we disagree, I think, is that in
 religious exemption cases I see two principles here that deserve our
 respect. The one I just quoted above and the principle that the majority
 and government should not prohibit or burden another citizen's religious
 observance. I think, you can tell me if I'm wrong, that you would agree
 that this principle standing alone also deserves respect. If there is no
 harm to third parties, you would support religious exemptions.


  Then the question becomes what do we do when these two principles are in
 conflict with each other. I don't think either trumps the other all of the
 time. I think as the harm to third parties increases, the principle that
 citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with the other
 citizen's religious observance outweighs the religious liberty principle. I
 understand you to be saying that the religious liberty principle is always
 trumped in these cases without regard to the magnitude of the costs
 involved.


  There are a lot of religious accommodations that result in third parties
 incurring some cost.  A RLUIPA land use accommodation might result in some
 neighboring homeowner, business or farmer incurring some diminution of
 value in their property. A public university accommodation shifting move-in
 day so that it doesn't fall on the Jewish High Holy days may require a
 shift in the academic calendar that inconveniences the travel plans of
 specific faculty, students and their families. A court accommodating the
 religious obligations of a religious attorney or witness may delay or
 otherwise increase the cost of litigation. A law banning male circumcision
 exempts Jewish families from its requirements. Does the existence of harm
 to third parties in these situations and others require the invalidation of
 all of these accommodations without regard to the magnitude of the harm
 borne by third parties?


  Alan


  --
 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu on behalf of Nelson Tebbe 
 nelson.te...@brooklaw.edu
 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 1, 2015 1:38 PM
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights



  Alan, I can’t speak for others who have been defending a principle
 against burden-shifting to third parties, but I do not believe it prohibits
 religion accommodations that result in costs to the government or to the
 public. Rather, the principle prohibits government accommodations that
 shift meaningful costs from religious citizens to other identifiable
 private citizens. And the reason for this is easy to articulate and deeply
 rooted — private citizens should not have to bear the costs associated with
 other citizens’ religious observance.

  On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:07 PM, Alan E Brownstein aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu
 wrote:

  The problem I have with Jim's argument, if I understand him
 correctly, is that it seems to suggest that no religious exemption can be
 accepted if it causes any harm to a third party. (I'm not sure if Jim
 includes the general public or the public fisc in third party.) I think
 many liberals believe (or at least they used to believe) that rights are
 expensive political goods. We protect them even if we have to incur some
 cost or harm

Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Ira Lupu
Thanks for the question, Will. If the kosher butcher gets that exemption,
he will sell pork to no one.  He never has and never will carry pork in his
shop.  He also does not sell soda, cars, or wedding cakes.  If you want
that stuff, you must go elsewhere.  Is that a cost to third parties?''  No
more than that imposed by any (that is, every) other merchant who sells
less than everything.

Compare that to a discriminatory refusal to sell.  Baker A does sell
wedding cakes, but not to same sex couples.  Two injuries -- material and
dignitary.  The material injury is the lost opportunity to buy a cake at
the quality and price offered by that baker.  Maybe you can do as well or
better elsewhere, nearby, or maybe not.  The dignitary injury is more
serious -- the couple is seeking goods to celebrate one of the most
important and special days of their lives. And the baker says, in effect,
I do not respect your marriage as a marriage.  In my belief system, it is
not a marriage at all, because you are of the same sex. (The baker might
also think or say that in his view the relationship is disordered, or an
abomination, and/or against God's plan, but let's assume he says nothing
like that all.)  The baker has wounded the couple with this disrespect, and
done so in regard to a day that has significant meaning in their lives.

Those are the focused, third party harms in the refusal to sell goods or
services to some that you sell to others, especially (though not only) for
a wedding reception.

On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 4:38 PM, Will Esser willes...@yahoo.com wrote:

 Chip,

 Can you expound on your argument that wedding vendor exemptions from
 public accommodations laws allow material and dignitary injury to
 potential customers and that liberals only oppose exemptions that impinge
 on the welfare of third parties?  It seems that both sides agree that the
 kosher butcher deserves a religious exemption, and yet granting that
 exemption imposes *some* cost on third parties (i.e. anyone who wishes to
 purchase pork must go elsewhere, which could involve multiple trips to
 different butchers, or may mean spending more time and money to go to a
 butcher further away).  So it's not really that there is *no* cost to
 third parties, but perhaps simply a cost which society is more ready to
 accept (i.e. Go buy your pork somewhere else.)

 As I understood the third-party harm argument in Hobby Lobby, the
 argument was that without insurance coverage, female Hobby Lobby employees
 would be unable to afford coverage of the particular, objectionable
 contraceptives and therefore the third party harm was equivalent to total
 lack of access.

 Given modern changes in societal perspectives, I have not heard the same
 argument about a total lack of access when it comes to wedding vendors for
 same-sex wedding ceremonies.  Under the assumption the goods and services
 are otherwise generally available in the marketplace (i.e. there are plenty
 of wedding photographers, bakers, etc. who would be happy for the business
 of same-sex weddings), what is the distinguishing factor which causes
 material and dignitary injury in the wedding vendor exemptions scenario
 but not in the kosher butcher example?  In both, the customers want a
 service which they can get in the marketplace (although perhaps not from
 the exact person or place they want it).  And in both, the reason for not
 providing the service is the same (i.e. violation of a sincerely held
 religious belief).

 Thanks in advance for clarification.

 Will

 Will Esser
 Charlotte, North Carolina


   --
  *From:* James Oleske jole...@lclark.edu
 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

 *Sent:* Wednesday, April 1, 2015 3:22 PM
 *Subject:* Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

 The butcher example Chip gives is why I suggested last spring that the
 Court might want to read the Lee language not as an absolute rule, but
 rather, a strong presumption against exemptions in the commercial realm
 that can be overcome in the very rare case where the basis for the
 presumption (a third-party harm) does not exist. Alas, the Court instead
 simply discarded the Lee language wholesale by saying RFRA went further
 than the pre-Smith law.

 - Jim




 On Wed, Apr 1, 2015 at 12:09 PM, Ira Lupu icl...@law.gwu.edu wrote:

 I do not think most liberals oppose exemptions for businesses per se --
 imagine a law that compelled a butcher to carry products in conflict with
 religious dietary laws to which the butcher and his customers subscribe.
 Liberals oppose exemptions that impinge on the welfare of third parties --
 Hobby Lobby (those female employees still do not have contraceptive
 coverage) or wedding vendor exemptions from public accommodations laws
 (those exemptions allow material and dignitary injury to potential
 customers). U.S. v. Lee involved injury to other family members of Amish
 employees, as well as others

RE: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

2015-04-01 Thread Scarberry, Mark
I also think the florist and baker examples are weaker for the religious 
claimant, especially where the flowers and cakes are generic. But what if 
custom floral arrangements involve artistic choices by the florist? What if the 
cake is (as some are) a truly creative work of art? And do only high-end bakers 
get protection from violation of conscience? What if the florist or baker is 
asked to include particular words or other expressive content in the 
arrangement or the cake? (This from someone who argued against licensing 
requirements for sellers of flowers - protectionist provisions for florists who 
fear grocery stores' selling of flowers - on the basis that flower arranging is 
a kind of art that the government has no right to license, other than for 
health purposes.) What if the custom florist decides to include a lot of black 
roses in the arrangements? Or just puts the flowers together without using any 
creativity (so that they look like flowers you would get through 
1-800-Flowers)? Can the florist be required to enter into the contract to 
provide flowers and then be required to follow some sort of industry standard 
of artistry in arranging the flowers?

In the photography example, if the photographer must photograph a ceremony that 
he or she believes wrong, may the photographer refuse to use the creative 
skills that would ordinarily be used? (E.g., posing the couple in a particular 
way, using filters to get a romantic look, telling them to kiss for the 
photograph, etc.) I suppose that goes with my view that wedding photography is 
creation of celebratory art, and the First Amendment compelled speech cases 
prohibit the government from requiring the photographer to create art.

On the harm question, of course there is a matter of baseline. Do I harm you by 
not photographing your ceremony? Or do I benefit you by doing it? If that 
depends on the message sent by the refusal, then we have an interesting 
viewpoint discrimination issue.

Mark

Mark S. Scarberry
Professor of Law
Pepperdine Univ. School of Law




From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Levinson, Sanford V
Sent: Wednesday, April 01, 2015 3:18 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Eugene's Blog Post on Liberals and Exemption Rights

I think Prof. Chen is substantially correct, but I believe, more than ever, 
that it's the kind of problem that can ( and should) be handled outside legal 
constraints. Why would I want to hire a wedding photographer who so clearly 
won't view the day as affirmatively special?  Ditto the band?  But I really 
can't work up much sympathy for the florist or baker. They should be treated 
under the general rubric of public accommodations and the Civil Rights Act of 
1964. I'm sure there were florists and bakers who objected to mixes-race 
marriages and could cite the purported curse on Ham. It really doesn't (and 
shouldn't) matter.

Sandy

Sent from my iPhone

On Apr 1, 2015, at 4:56 PM, K Chen tzn...@gmail.commailto:tzn...@gmail.com 
wrote:
As someone putting a wedding together, I can't explain the lack of sympathy for 
the wedding photographer as anything but thinking that their work is 
essentially interchangeable. It is not, unfortunately, and it is priced 
accordingly. Every single photographer of them seems to take their business 
very, very personally. More to the point, it is a personal, professional 
service which is by its nature selective compared to the harm done by 
impersonal corporations excluding goods and services when they otherwise serve 
the public.

A principled difference can be drawn between accommodating personal, inherently 
selective commercial businesses and businesses that are open to the public at 
large. The vast majority of commercial transactions are from businesses who 
sell to the public, or their business community, on a non-discriminatory basis. 
When such a business denies goods or services to a class of person, that is an 
inherently political act. Such a businesses is not just refusing the do 
business with an individual or class, they are making an attempt to exclude 
them from the definition of the public itself. They are thus doing harm to both 
individual and society by imposing their will on what constitutes the political 
community. This harm grows geometrically with each exclusionary actor.

Individual consumers on the other hand, are inherently selective. If you need 
one loaf of bread this week, you will patronize precisely one baker this week. 
If you need a salary, you will work one, maybe two jobs. The harm of being 
denied service by a consumer (or laborer) because of their beliefs has a 
societal harm, if any, nearly indistinguishable to being denied for any other 
reason.

Some services should fall in between. I'm not convinced for the florist and the 
and the baker, but I'm sympathetic to the photographer, the doctor, the lawyer 
(ethical obligations notwithstanding