Re: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread hamilton02
It is not majoritarian but rather the marketplace. Expressive association is a 
new right with little justification in history and I am beginning to think a 
large step toward government sponsored Balkanization
Does the government have an obligation to make sure dwindling religions remain 
viable. I would say absolutely not. But apparently Mark would disagree?

Marci
Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry

-Original Message-
From: Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu
Date: Wed, 12 May 2010 19:11:04 
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Esenberg, Richard
The right of expressive association is not a demand for government protection 
in the market place of ideas or a demand for government support. It is, rather, 
a shield against government compulsion, i.e., the demand that an organization 
not define itself by adherance to any particular creed or that it engage in 
practices inconsistent with its expressive message or core beliefs. While in 
the public forum context, it might involve access to a government benefit but 
that is a function of the government's decision to establish a forum and the 
(quite reasonble rule) that, if it chooses to do so, it may not discriminate on 
the basis of viewpoint.

This doesn't immunize religious organizations from the market place of ideas 
which, in any event, does not work as she thinks it does. Churches regularly 
impose creedal requirements on clergy, leaders and members. If congregants 
don't like it, they leave much as those who don't like CLS policy could leave 
as well.

The problem with takeovers - whether effected through rules of a public forum 
or antidiscrimination laws - is that they would undermine the capacity of 
minority or, more specifically, unpopular groups to associate for a particular 
expressive purpose because, as soon as they choose to combine, they must be 
prepared, in this context, to permit others to come in and not simply expose 
their creed to the market place of ideas (that happens in all events) but to 
vote it out.


Professor Rick Esenberg
Marquette University Law School
Sensenbrenner Hall 321C
1103 W. Wisconsin Avenue
Milwaukee, WI 53201
(o) 414-288-6908
(m)414-213-3957
(f)  414-288-6975



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of hamilto...@aol.com [hamilto...@aol.com]
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 7:09 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

It is not majoritarian but rather the marketplace. Expressive association is a 
new right with little justification in history and I am beginning to think a 
large step toward government sponsored Balkanization
Does the government have an obligation to make sure dwindling religions remain 
viable. I would say absolutely not. But apparently Mark would disagree?

Marci
Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry

-Original Message-
From: Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu
Date: Wed, 12 May 2010 19:11:04
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Rick Duncan
Marci says: It is not majoritarian but rather the marketplace. Expressive 
association is a new right with little justification in history and I am
 beginning to think a large step toward government sponsored 
Balkanization
Does the government have an obligation to make sure 
dwindling religions remain viable. I would say absolutely not. But 
apparently Mark would disagree?


Expressive association lies at the heart of freedom of speech and freedom of 
belief.

It is not designed to protect dwindling religions from extinction. 
Christianity thrives in the catacombs. The CLS will survive attempts by 
Hastings to drive it off campus.

The purpose of expressive association is to prevent govt from watering down or 
distorting the expressive beliefs of groups organized for the purpose of 
expressing those beliefs.

Quite frankly, these attacks on the CLS on campus are driven by a kind of 
fundamentalism that has captured much, but not all, of academia. There is an 
established truth about human sexuality on campus, and any group that rejects 
that established dogma must be driven out of the on-campus marketplace of ideas.

What is it about that established truth that leads people who normally praise 
open-mindedness to be so close-minded as to want to eradicate ideas that 
challenge it in the marketplace of ideas.

I say let CLS and Outlaw meet on campus and let the marketplace of ideas decide 
which version of the truth is the true truth.

Rick Duncan 
Welpton Professor of Law 
University of Nebraska College of Law 
Lincoln, NE 68583-0902


And against the constitution I have never raised a storm,It's the scoundrels 
who've corrupted it that I want to reform --Dick Gaughan (from the song, 
Thomas Muir of Huntershill)





  ___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Esenberg, Richard
And since we are all going back and reading Elena Kagan's ruminations on the 
role of motive in assessing speech restrictions, we might ask what Hastings 
seeks to accomplish by prohibiting CLS from insisting upon its distinctive 
creed as a condition of leadership or voting membership. What work does its 
policy do in promoting the full participation of students in the life of the 
law school?

The answer, it seems, is almost none. CLS events are open to nonadherents. 
Nonadherents can form groups of their own with equal access to whatever 
benefits are on offer. Hastings never believed - until now - that organization 
around a particular set of ideas diminishes the campus citizenship or 
opportunities of those who did not share them. (In fact, it apparently allowed 
La Raza to operate with a racial requirement for voting membership and 
leadership.)

It seems clear that what Hastings want to do is to completely disassociate 
itself with CLS and to place it at a disadvantage vis-a-vis other groups. It 
wants to send a message to CLS that, to borrow Justice O'Connor's phrase, it is 
a disfavored member of the community. Hastings goal is not to create new 
opportunities for minorities but to step on a message that it does not like.

Rick Esenberg
Marquette

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of Scarberry, Mark [mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu]
Sent: Wednesday, May 12, 2010 9:11 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

So I presume Marci would have no problem with a bunch of Christians who join a 
campus Chabad group and turn it into a Christian evangelization organization. 
Or a bunch of students who favor prayer in public schools taking over a campus 
ACLU or Americans United chapter. Or a bunch of Federalists taking over a 
campus ACS chapter. After all, the Jewish students or the ACLU or AU or ACS 
students could just form other groups. But that approach is deeply unfaithful 
to the core concept of expressive associational freedom. It is sad that Marci, 
and the educational establishment (united as it seems to be against CLS in CLS 
v. Martinez), would embrace such a crude majoritarian approach.

Mark Scarberry
Pepperdine


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu on behalf of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Wed 5/12/2010 6:51 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

Here is my question-- why would anyone care about a takeover?  Wouldn't that 
just mean that a majority of the members voted in a different slate of leaders? 
 It's not like a dissenter could come in and singlehandedly takeover a group, 
is it?  They have to be chosen by a majority.  Then if the group takes a turn 
some don't like, the minority starts their own new group, right??  Isn't that 
what happens everyday with groups of people?  And in particular religious 
groups?  There is even a term for it -- schism.  But you don't even need a 
full-out schism to see this happen in religious groups, where a congregation 
will love a pastor but then some start disliking his/her sermons or priorities, 
and switch over to another congregation, or start a new congregation, or 
agitate for a new pastor.  Isn't that the American way of a marketplace in 
ideas and religion?

So why does CLS or any other group need protection from the possibility that 
outsiders will take them over?  If the CLS leaders are so weak that those 
with different views can take over, they can form a whole new group.  So just 
how does the all-comers rule disadvantage CLS?  I think this need for 
protection against takeovers is just a pretense for the intent to discriminate 
on the basis of sexual orientation.


Marci



In a message dated 5/12/2010 9:21:14 P.M. Eastern Daylight Time, 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu writes:
In any event, I think those who argue that an all comers rule is OK because 
takeovers are unlikely would in effect be relying on a pattern or practice of 
groups choosing leaders based on their views. Usually a pattern or practice is 
somewhat equivalent to a rule, where antidiscrimination principles are at 
stake. Thus in a sense CLS is being denied benefits in part because of its 
honesty in admitting what its members will do, and the all comers rule is 
supported because groups will in fact engage in discrimination, though perhaps 
not by way of formal rules.

Mark Scarberry
Pepperdine


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Steven Jamar
But is it a constitutional violation?  I would tend to agree that the  
government ought to accommodate religious associations and give them  
equal access to government facilities and should grant religious  
associations exemptions from certain non-discrimination rules that  
apply to secular organizations.


But, should this be a constitutional rule?  Isn't the all comers  
rule a quintessential neutral rule of general applicability so  
religious organizations are bound by it?  So no free exercise violation.


Isn't a rule that says only those who abid by our non-discrimination  
policy are entitled to government benefits (like funding,  
certification, contracts) constitutional under every theory?


And no one is stopping CLS or any other organization from freedom of  
association or freedom of speech.  And Rosenberger shows how far  
freedom of speech can push the government to support religion.  (If we  
apply Rosenberger we get the result that there is no establishment if  
the university exempts CLS, right?)


So, those wanting to further constitutionalize church and state  
relations fail on the religion clause and equal protection, fail on  
freedom of association and freedom of speech grounds.


So we come to a new version of constitutionalizing church and state  
relations -- government sponsorship of religious groups that  
discriminate on banned bases under an expressive association  
theory.  (For you originalists, where is that in the constitution?)


No.  This battle belongs in the political processes, not in the  
Constitution.  If the CLS case is so strong on the merits of fairness  
and equality and expression and association, why isn't it implemented  
through the political process?  Because people are evil and out to get  
CLS?  Nah.  It is because people want to reduce discrimination on the  
basis of sexual orientation.


But, like so many things, we tend to make such matters constitutional  
issues and so this is as well, no doubt.


As a policy matter, I would exempt religious organizations from this  
particular non-discrimination, equal treatment requirement -- it  
really is not the same as race.  But, I'm not at all sure I would  
reach the same result as a constitutional question.


Religion is different and requires different treatment.  Not all  
speech and association rules apply to trump that difference.


Steve Jamar

On May 13, 2010, at 8:32 AM, Esenberg, Richard wrote:

The right of expressive association is not a demand for government  
protection in the market place of ideas or a demand for government  
support. It is, rather, a shield against government compulsion,  
i.e., the demand that an organization not define itself by adherance  
to any particular creed or that it engage in practices inconsistent  
with its expressive message or core beliefs. While in the public  
forum context, it might involve access to a government benefit but  
that is a function of the government's decision to establish a forum  
and the (quite reasonble rule) that, if it chooses to do so, it may  
not discriminate on the basis of viewpoint.


This doesn't immunize religious organizations from the market place  
of ideas which, in any event, does not work as she thinks it does.  
Churches regularly impose creedal requirements on clergy, leaders  
and members. If congregants don't like it, they leave much as those  
who don't like CLS policy could leave as well.


The problem with takeovers - whether effected through rules of a  
public forum or antidiscrimination laws - is that they would  
undermine the capacity of minority or, more specifically, unpopular  
groups to associate for a particular expressive purpose because, as  
soon as they choose to combine, they must be prepared, in this  
context, to permit others to come in and not simply expose their  
creed to the market place of ideas (that happens in all events) but  
to vote it out.



Professor Rick Esenberg
Marquette University Law School
Sensenbrenner Hall 321C
1103 W. Wisconsin Avenue
Milwaukee, WI 53201
(o) 414-288-6908
(m)414-213-3957
(f)  414-288-6975



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
] on behalf of hamilto...@aol.com [hamilto...@aol.com]

Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 7:09 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

It is not majoritarian but rather the marketplace. Expressive  
association is a new right with little justification in history and  
I am beginning to think a large step toward government sponsored  
Balkanization
Does the government have an obligation to make sure dwindling  
religions remain viable. I would say absolutely not. But apparently  
Mark would disagree?


Marci
Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry

-Original Message-
From: Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu
Date: Wed, 12 May 2010 19:11:04
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real

Re: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread hamilton02
Of course the marketplace works as I described it especially in the US. Groups 
thrive and shrivel and respond to and interact with the culture and if they 
cannot adapt to broadbased moral and social changes by changing their beliefs 
and practices, they become marginalized. Groups spin off of other groups.
The many religions that supported slavery and the subjection of women and 
children to state-sponsored patriarchal control have had to adjust or choose 
the sidelines.  Hasn't CLS conceded that the school can enforce race 
discrimination laws?  

Marci

Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry

-Original Message-
From: Esenberg, Richard richard.esenb...@marquette.edu
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 12:32:59 
To: hamilto...@aol.comhamilto...@aol.com; Law  Religion issues for 
LawAcademicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

The right of expressive association is not a demand for government protection 
in the market place of ideas or a demand for government support. It is, rather, 
a shield against government compulsion, i.e., the demand that an organization 
not define itself by adherance to any particular creed or that it engage in 
practices inconsistent with its expressive message or core beliefs. While in 
the public forum context, it might involve access to a government benefit but 
that is a function of the government's decision to establish a forum and the 
(quite reasonble rule) that, if it chooses to do so, it may not discriminate on 
the basis of viewpoint.

This doesn't immunize religious organizations from the market place of ideas 
which, in any event, does not work as she thinks it does. Churches regularly 
impose creedal requirements on clergy, leaders and members. If congregants 
don't like it, they leave much as those who don't like CLS policy could leave 
as well.

The problem with takeovers - whether effected through rules of a public forum 
or antidiscrimination laws - is that they would undermine the capacity of 
minority or, more specifically, unpopular groups to associate for a particular 
expressive purpose because, as soon as they choose to combine, they must be 
prepared, in this context, to permit others to come in and not simply expose 
their creed to the market place of ideas (that happens in all events) but to 
vote it out.


Professor Rick Esenberg
Marquette University Law School
Sensenbrenner Hall 321C
1103 W. Wisconsin Avenue
Milwaukee, WI 53201
(o) 414-288-6908
(m)414-213-3957
(f)  414-288-6975



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of hamilto...@aol.com [hamilto...@aol.com]
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 7:09 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

It is not majoritarian but rather the marketplace. Expressive association is a 
new right with little justification in history and I am beginning to think a 
large step toward government sponsored Balkanization
Does the government have an obligation to make sure dwindling religions remain 
viable. I would say absolutely not. But apparently Mark would disagree?

Marci
Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry

-Original Message-
From: Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu
Date: Wed, 12 May 2010 19:11:04
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Steven Jamar
Hastings is not stopping the message.  It is stopping an action.  It  
is not preventing CLS from saying anything it wants to say.  It is  
preventing it from discriminating on a basis the university considers  
improper.


Christian students are allowed full participation in the life of the  
law school.  They can have a Christian student organization that  
doesn't exclude gays.


Yes.  Hasting wants to associate itself with a policy that an group  
advances -- but it is not prohibiting that group from disagreeing with  
it.  It is just prohibiting that group from being a certified student  
organization because it discriminates unlawfully.


If CLS allowed gays in, it could still publish such messages as it  
wants.


Steve Jamar

On May 13, 2010, at 9:01 AM, Esenberg, Richard wrote:

And since we are all going back and reading Elena Kagan's  
ruminations on the role of motive in assessing speech restrictions,  
we might ask what Hastings seeks to accomplish by prohibiting CLS  
from insisting upon its distinctive creed as a condition of  
leadership or voting membership. What work does its policy do in  
promoting the full participation of students in the life of the law  
school?


The answer, it seems, is almost none. CLS events are open to  
nonadherents. Nonadherents can form groups of their own with equal  
access to whatever benefits are on offer. Hastings never believed -  
until now - that organization around a particular set of ideas  
diminishes the campus citizenship or opportunities of those who did  
not share them. (In fact, it apparently allowed La Raza to operate  
with a racial requirement for voting membership and leadership.)


It seems clear that what Hastings want to do is to completely  
disassociate itself with CLS and to place it at a disadvantage vis-a- 
vis other groups. It wants to send a message to CLS that, to borrow  
Justice O'Connor's phrase, it is a disfavored member of the  
community. Hastings goal is not to create new opportunities for  
minorities but to step on a message that it does not like.


Rick Esenberg
Marquette

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
] on behalf of Scarberry, Mark [mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu]

Sent: Wednesday, May 12, 2010 9:11 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

So I presume Marci would have no problem with a bunch of Christians  
who join a campus Chabad group and turn it into a Christian  
evangelization organization. Or a bunch of students who favor prayer  
in public schools taking over a campus ACLU or Americans United  
chapter. Or a bunch of Federalists taking over a campus ACS chapter.  
After all, the Jewish students or the ACLU or AU or ACS students  
could just form other groups. But that approach is deeply unfaithful  
to the core concept of expressive associational freedom. It is sad  
that Marci, and the educational establishment (united as it seems to  
be against CLS in CLS v. Martinez), would embrace such a crude  
majoritarian approach.


Mark Scarberry
Pepperdine


From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu on behalf of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Wed 5/12/2010 6:51 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

Here is my question-- why would anyone care about a takeover?   
Wouldn't that just mean that a majority of the members voted in a  
different slate of leaders?  It's not like a dissenter could come in  
and singlehandedly takeover a group, is it?  They have to be chosen  
by a majority.  Then if the group takes a turn some don't like, the  
minority starts their own new group, right??  Isn't that what  
happens everyday with groups of people?  And in particular religious  
groups?  There is even a term for it -- schism.  But you don't even  
need a full-out schism to see this happen in religious groups, where  
a congregation will love a pastor but then some start disliking his/ 
her sermons or priorities, and switch over to another congregation,  
or start a new congregation, or agitate for a new pastor.  Isn't  
that the American way of a marketplace in ideas and religion?


So why does CLS or any other group need protection from the  
possibility that outsiders will take them over?  If the CLS  
leaders are so weak that those with different views can take over,  
they can form a whole new group.  So just how does the all-comers  
rule disadvantage CLS?  I think this need for protection against  
takeovers is just a pretense for the intent to discriminate on the  
basis of sexual orientation.



Marci



In a message dated 5/12/2010 9:21:14 P.M. Eastern Daylight Time, mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu 
 writes:
In any event, I think those who argue that an all comers rule is OK  
because takeovers are unlikely would in effect be relying on a  
pattern or practice of groups choosing leaders based on their views.  
Usually a pattern or practice

Re: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Rick Duncan
 Marci says: Groups thrive and shrivel and respond to and interact with the 
culture 
and if they cannot adapt to broadbased moral and social changes by 
changing their beliefs and practices, they become marginalized.


I have no further questions of this witness.

Marci's admission--that groups like the CLS must adapt to broadbased moral and 
social changes by 
changing their beliefs--demonstrates the important purpose of freedom of 
expressive association.

That core purpose is that Government should not use its coercive power 
(including its power over public fora) to coerce expressive groups into 
changing their beliefs. Government has no business telling expressive groups 
which beliefs are acceptable and which are unacceptable. 

Hastings can create a public forum and allow the marketplace to decide which 
ideas are marginal and which are not. Or it can close the forum and allow only 
school-sponsored groups to meet. But it cannot engage the fiction of 
maintaining a marketplace of ideas, while at the same time using its power to 
suppress ideas and beliefs that reject established versions of the truth.

Rick Duncan 
Welpton Professor of Law 
University of Nebraska College of Law 
Lincoln, NE 68583-0902


And against the constitution I have never raised a storm,It's the scoundrels 
who've corrupted it that I want to reform --Dick Gaughan (from the song, 
Thomas Muir of Huntershill)



  ___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Marc Stern
Nothing CLS has said challenges Hastings' duty to enforce rules against
its own discrimination on the basis of inter alia sexual orientation or
religion. As Gilmore v. City of Montgomery holds, however, a city's duty
not to engage itself in (there racial) discrimination ) does not
authorize it to deny non-exclusive access to public spaces to groups
that engage in such discrimination. The Court held there that to enforce
non-discrimination rules against such private groups (schools!) would
deny the segregation academies freedom of association. Why isn't Gilmore
controlling here?
Marc Stern 

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of
hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 9:19 AM
To: Esenberg, Richard; Law  Religion issues for LawAcademics
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

Of course the marketplace works as I described it especially in the US.
Groups thrive and shrivel and respond to and interact with the culture
and if they cannot adapt to broadbased moral and social changes by
changing their beliefs and practices, they become marginalized. Groups
spin off of other groups.
The many religions that supported slavery and the subjection of women
and children to state-sponsored patriarchal control have had to adjust
or choose the sidelines.  Hasn't CLS conceded that the school can
enforce race discrimination laws?  

Marci

Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry

-Original Message-
From: Esenberg, Richard richard.esenb...@marquette.edu
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 12:32:59
To: hamilto...@aol.comhamilto...@aol.com; Law  Religion issues for
LawAcademicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

The right of expressive association is not a demand for government
protection in the market place of ideas or a demand for government
support. It is, rather, a shield against government compulsion, i.e.,
the demand that an organization not define itself by adherance to any
particular creed or that it engage in practices inconsistent with its
expressive message or core beliefs. While in the public forum context,
it might involve access to a government benefit but that is a function
of the government's decision to establish a forum and the (quite
reasonble rule) that, if it chooses to do so, it may not discriminate on
the basis of viewpoint.

This doesn't immunize religious organizations from the market place of
ideas which, in any event, does not work as she thinks it does. Churches
regularly impose creedal requirements on clergy, leaders and members. If
congregants don't like it, they leave much as those who don't like CLS
policy could leave as well.

The problem with takeovers - whether effected through rules of a
public forum or antidiscrimination laws - is that they would undermine
the capacity of minority or, more specifically, unpopular groups to
associate for a particular expressive purpose because, as soon as they
choose to combine, they must be prepared, in this context, to permit
others to come in and not simply expose their creed to the market place
of ideas (that happens in all events) but to vote it out.


Professor Rick Esenberg
Marquette University Law School
Sensenbrenner Hall 321C
1103 W. Wisconsin Avenue
Milwaukee, WI 53201
(o) 414-288-6908
(m)414-213-3957
(f)  414-288-6975



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of hamilto...@aol.com
[hamilto...@aol.com]
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 7:09 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

It is not majoritarian but rather the marketplace. Expressive
association is a new right with little justification in history and I am
beginning to think a large step toward government sponsored
Balkanization Does the government have an obligation to make sure
dwindling religions remain viable. I would say absolutely not. But
apparently Mark would disagree?

Marci
Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry

-Original Message-
From: Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu
Date: Wed, 12 May 2010 19:11:04
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe,
unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe,
unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent

Re: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread hamilton02
As I and others have said repeatedly, there is no censorship or suppression.  
No exclusion. Those are not the facts of this case
In any event, I was speaking about the larger picture. I am interested in 
dis-covering the taboo that forbids us from discussing the obvious fact that 
religious groups are a part of the culture.  And that they change.   And that 
change can be good for religious groups. 

Marci   
Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry

-Original Message-
From: Rick Duncan nebraskalawp...@yahoo.com
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 06:34:38 
To: hamilto...@aol.com; Law  Religion issues for Law 
Academicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

 Marci says: Groups thrive and shrivel and respond to and interact with the 
culture 
and if they cannot adapt to broadbased moral and social changes by 
changing their beliefs and practices, they become marginalized.


I have no further questions of this witness.

Marci's admission--that groups like the CLS must adapt to broadbased moral and 
social changes by 
changing their beliefs--demonstrates the important purpose of freedom of 
expressive association.

That core purpose is that Government should not use its coercive power 
(including its power over public fora) to coerce expressive groups into 
changing their beliefs. Government has no business telling expressive groups 
which beliefs are acceptable and which are unacceptable. 

Hastings can create a public forum and allow the marketplace to decide which 
ideas are marginal and which are not. Or it can close the forum and allow only 
school-sponsored groups to meet. But it cannot engage the fiction of 
maintaining a marketplace of ideas, while at the same time using its power to 
suppress ideas and beliefs that reject established versions of the truth.

Rick Duncan 
Welpton Professor of Law 
University of Nebraska College of Law 
Lincoln, NE 68583-0902


And against the constitution I have never raised a storm,It's the scoundrels 
who've corrupted it that I want to reform --Dick Gaughan (from the song, 
Thomas Muir of Huntershill)



  

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Esenberg, Richard
Marci wrote:

Of course the marketplace works as I described it especially in the US. Groups 
thrive and shrivel and respond to and interact with the culture and if they 
cannot adapt to broadbased moral and social changes by changing their beliefs 
and practices, they become marginalized.

That restatement of your description is accurate, but your initial position 
which presumed that churches maintain open doors and are subject to the whims 
of whomever walks througn was not accurate. The market place for religion does 
not - at least not outside of Hastings - operate under government compulsion 
that churches take all comers. And, at least outside of the fading Protestant 
mainline (a phenomenom which may be instructive here), churches don't welcome 
all comers without regard to creed.

It is certainly true that religion organizations are affected by the culture 
outside. That is, in fact, the insight of post-liberal theology. Religion is 
formed in community and is porous.

But whether it is good or bad for religion to be affected by the mainstream 
culture is not, I think, a decision for the state to make - which is why the 
matter will inevitably raise constitutional questions. It seems to me that free 
exercise implies that minority religious groups are perfectly free to barricade 
the garden.

Now, of course, if you believe that it is desireable to drive religious 
organizations into some sphere defined by a set of commonly held views, you'll 
see it differently.

Rick Esenberg
Marquette

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of hamilto...@aol.com [hamilto...@aol.com]
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 8:49 AM
To: Rick Duncan; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

As I and others have said repeatedly, there is no censorship or suppression. No 
exclusion. Those are not the facts of this case
In any event, I was speaking about the larger picture. I am interested in 
dis-covering the taboo that forbids us from discussing the obvious fact that 
religious groups are a part of the culture. And that they change. And that 
change can be good for religious groups.

Marci

Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry


From: Rick Duncan nebraskalawp...@yahoo.com
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 06:34:38 -0700 (PDT)
To: hamilto...@aol.com; Law  Religion issues for Law 
Academicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

Marci says: Groups thrive and shrivel and respond to and interact with the 
culture and if they cannot adapt to broadbased moral and social changes by 
changing their beliefs and practices, they become marginalized.


I have no further questions of this witness.

Marci's admission--that groups like the CLS must adapt to broadbased moral and 
social changes by changing their beliefs--demonstrates the important purpose 
of freedom of expressive association.

That core purpose is that Government should not use its coercive power 
(including its power over public fora) to coerce expressive groups into 
changing their beliefs. Government has no business telling expressive groups 
which beliefs are acceptable and which are unacceptable.

Hastings can create a public forum and allow the marketplace to decide which 
ideas are marginal and which are not. Or it can close the forum and allow only 
school-sponsored groups to meet. But it cannot engage the fiction of 
maintaining a marketplace of ideas, while at the same time using its power to 
suppress ideas and beliefs that reject established versions of the truth.

Rick Duncan
Welpton Professor of Law
University of Nebraska College of Law
Lincoln, NE 68583-0902


And against the constitution I have never raised a storm,It's the scoundrels 
who've corrupted it that I want to reform --Dick Gaughan (from the song, 
Thomas Muir of Huntershill)



___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Judith Baer
Marci Hamilton wrote:

Does the government have an obligation to make sure dwindling religions
remain viable. I would say absolutely not.

I agree. Think of the Shakers, for example.
Judy Baer
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread hamilton02
Actually, it is not true that the government cannot or does not impose 
all-comer human rights policies on religions expecting government benefits 
outside Hastings.  That is the core of the Bob Jones Univ case.   That is why I 
raised race discrimination earlier

Marci

Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry

-Original Message-
From: Esenberg, Richard richard.esenb...@marquette.edu
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 14:24:57 
To: hamilto...@aol.comhamilto...@aol.com; Law  Religion issues for 
LawAcademicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edu; Rick Duncannebraskalawp...@yahoo.com
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

Marci wrote:

Of course the marketplace works as I described it especially in the US. Groups 
thrive and shrivel and respond to and interact with the culture and if they 
cannot adapt to broadbased moral and social changes by changing their beliefs 
and practices, they become marginalized.

That restatement of your description is accurate, but your initial position 
which presumed that churches maintain open doors and are subject to the whims 
of whomever walks througn was not accurate. The market place for religion does 
not - at least not outside of Hastings - operate under government compulsion 
that churches take all comers. And, at least outside of the fading Protestant 
mainline (a phenomenom which may be instructive here), churches don't welcome 
all comers without regard to creed.

It is certainly true that religion organizations are affected by the culture 
outside. That is, in fact, the insight of post-liberal theology. Religion is 
formed in community and is porous.

But whether it is good or bad for religion to be affected by the mainstream 
culture is not, I think, a decision for the state to make - which is why the 
matter will inevitably raise constitutional questions. It seems to me that free 
exercise implies that minority religious groups are perfectly free to barricade 
the garden.

Now, of course, if you believe that it is desireable to drive religious 
organizations into some sphere defined by a set of commonly held views, you'll 
see it differently.

Rick Esenberg
Marquette

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of hamilto...@aol.com [hamilto...@aol.com]
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 8:49 AM
To: Rick Duncan; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

As I and others have said repeatedly, there is no censorship or suppression. No 
exclusion. Those are not the facts of this case
In any event, I was speaking about the larger picture. I am interested in 
dis-covering the taboo that forbids us from discussing the obvious fact that 
religious groups are a part of the culture. And that they change. And that 
change can be good for religious groups.

Marci

Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry


From: Rick Duncan nebraskalawp...@yahoo.com
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 06:34:38 -0700 (PDT)
To: hamilto...@aol.com; Law  Religion issues for Law 
Academicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

Marci says: Groups thrive and shrivel and respond to and interact with the 
culture and if they cannot adapt to broadbased moral and social changes by 
changing their beliefs and practices, they become marginalized.


I have no further questions of this witness.

Marci's admission--that groups like the CLS must adapt to broadbased moral and 
social changes by changing their beliefs--demonstrates the important purpose 
of freedom of expressive association.

That core purpose is that Government should not use its coercive power 
(including its power over public fora) to coerce expressive groups into 
changing their beliefs. Government has no business telling expressive groups 
which beliefs are acceptable and which are unacceptable.

Hastings can create a public forum and allow the marketplace to decide which 
ideas are marginal and which are not. Or it can close the forum and allow only 
school-sponsored groups to meet. But it cannot engage the fiction of 
maintaining a marketplace of ideas, while at the same time using its power to 
suppress ideas and beliefs that reject established versions of the truth.

Rick Duncan
Welpton Professor of Law
University of Nebraska College of Law
Lincoln, NE 68583-0902


And against the constitution I have never raised a storm,It's the scoundrels 
who've corrupted it that I want to reform --Dick Gaughan (from the song, 
Thomas Muir of Huntershill)


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Esenberg, Richard
Bob Jones tells us nothing about whether CLS associational rights would protect 
it from an all comers policy imposed through, say, the application of 
discrimination laws. Within the public forum context, however, it is not clear 
to me that permitting the government to forbid status discrimination means that 
it may also forbid viewpoint discrimination. CLS is not claiming the right to 
engage in status discrimination and I think we ought to pause before we elide 
the distinction.


From: hamilto...@aol.com [hamilto...@aol.com]
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 10:01 AM
To: Esenberg, Richard; Law  Religion issues for LawAcademics; Rick Duncan
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

Actually, it is not true that the government cannot or does not impose 
all-comer human rights policies on religions expecting government benefits 
outside Hastings.  That is the core of the Bob Jones Univ case.   That is why I 
raised race discrimination earlier

Marci

Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry

-Original Message-
From: Esenberg, Richard richard.esenb...@marquette.edu
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 14:24:57
To: hamilto...@aol.comhamilto...@aol.com; Law  Religion issues for 
LawAcademicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edu; Rick Duncannebraskalawp...@yahoo.com
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

Marci wrote:

Of course the marketplace works as I described it especially in the US. Groups 
thrive and shrivel and respond to and interact with the culture and if they 
cannot adapt to broadbased moral and social changes by changing their beliefs 
and practices, they become marginalized.

That restatement of your description is accurate, but your initial position 
which presumed that churches maintain open doors and are subject to the whims 
of whomever walks througn was not accurate. The market place for religion does 
not - at least not outside of Hastings - operate under government compulsion 
that churches take all comers. And, at least outside of the fading Protestant 
mainline (a phenomenom which may be instructive here), churches don't welcome 
all comers without regard to creed.

It is certainly true that religion organizations are affected by the culture 
outside. That is, in fact, the insight of post-liberal theology. Religion is 
formed in community and is porous.

But whether it is good or bad for religion to be affected by the mainstream 
culture is not, I think, a decision for the state to make - which is why the 
matter will inevitably raise constitutional questions. It seems to me that free 
exercise implies that minority religious groups are perfectly free to barricade 
the garden.

Now, of course, if you believe that it is desireable to drive religious 
organizations into some sphere defined by a set of commonly held views, you'll 
see it differently.

Rick Esenberg
Marquette

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
on behalf of hamilto...@aol.com [hamilto...@aol.com]
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 8:49 AM
To: Rick Duncan; Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

As I and others have said repeatedly, there is no censorship or suppression. No 
exclusion. Those are not the facts of this case
In any event, I was speaking about the larger picture. I am interested in 
dis-covering the taboo that forbids us from discussing the obvious fact that 
religious groups are a part of the culture. And that they change. And that 
change can be good for religious groups.

Marci

Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry


From: Rick Duncan nebraskalawp...@yahoo.com
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 06:34:38 -0700 (PDT)
To: hamilto...@aol.com; Law  Religion issues for Law 
Academicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

Marci says: Groups thrive and shrivel and respond to and interact with the 
culture and if they cannot adapt to broadbased moral and social changes by 
changing their beliefs and practices, they become marginalized.


I have no further questions of this witness.

Marci's admission--that groups like the CLS must adapt to broadbased moral and 
social changes by changing their beliefs--demonstrates the important purpose 
of freedom of expressive association.

That core purpose is that Government should not use its coercive power 
(including its power over public fora) to coerce expressive groups into 
changing their beliefs. Government has no business telling expressive groups 
which beliefs are acceptable and which are unacceptable.

Hastings can create a public forum and allow the marketplace to decide which 
ideas are marginal and which are not. Or it can close the forum and allow only 
school-sponsored groups to meet. But it cannot engage the fiction of 
maintaining a marketplace of ideas, while at the same time using its power to 
suppress ideas and beliefs that reject established versions of the truth

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Ira (Chip) Lupu
Marc Stern is overstating the holding of Gilmore.  Most of the opinion is about 
a state action question -- whether the city is complicit in the segregation of 
certain facilities.  With respect to those private entities or groups with 
which the city is not so complicit, Gilmore has a brief passage at the end of 
the opinion recognizing their freedom of private association, and concluding 
that they cannot be excluded by an injunction from the right to participate in 
recreational activities in a public park.

But Hastings is not running a park where children come to play.  It has created 
a limited public forum, with access to various communications facilities.  Its 
rules have to be non-discriminatory and reasonable in light of the forum's 
purposes.  The all-comers policy is certainly non-discriminatory. We're arguing 
about whether it's reasonable (there might have been an argument about whether 
it was pretextual, but the parties' stipulation seems to eliminate that 
argument completely.)  Some of us on this list think the policy is quite 
reasonable; it is not likely to disturb any group's message, because of the 
incentives of mutual respect and forebearance, but it leaves open the 
possibility of challenge to a group's message.  A law school might reasonably 
see that openness to challenge -- and the imposition of a corresponding duty to 
include all-comers -- as a healthy and necessary quality in a student 
organization. The fact that students are only at the school for three years m!
 ak!
es this even more reasonable; the next cohort of students may want a different 
kind of CLS.  They can show up and challenge, or (more likely, if the local CLS 
views are entrenched) form their own student organization.  CLS wants the right 
to exclude, but it has real trouble demonstrating a tangible harm (rather than 
a harm in principle) from its inability to do so for  purposes of access to 
the forum.

One argument for unreasonableness that seems to me out of bounds is that CLS 
national has an unwaivable statement of faith.  If Hastings CLS can't comply 
with that, that's a problem between the national and the local affiliate, but 
that's not a problem for Hastings LS.  Likewise if the national ACLU, or any 
other national organization, does not like the local Hastings chapter policy on 
some issue.

 
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW 
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg


 Original message 
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 09:35:34 -0400
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu (on behalf of Marc Stern 
mst...@ajcongress.org)
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example  
To: hamilto...@aol.com,Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu,Esenberg, Richard 
richard.esenb...@marquette.edu

Nothing CLS has said challenges Hastings' duty to enforce rules against
its own discrimination on the basis of inter alia sexual orientation or
religion. As Gilmore v. City of Montgomery holds, however, a city's duty
not to engage itself in (there racial) discrimination ) does not
authorize it to deny non-exclusive access to public spaces to groups
that engage in such discrimination. The Court held there that to enforce
non-discrimination rules against such private groups (schools!) would
deny the segregation academies freedom of association. Why isn't Gilmore
controlling here?
Marc Stern 

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of
hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 9:19 AM
To: Esenberg, Richard; Law  Religion issues for LawAcademics
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

Of course the marketplace works as I described it especially in the US.
Groups thrive and shrivel and respond to and interact with the culture
and if they cannot adapt to broadbased moral and social changes by
changing their beliefs and practices, they become marginalized. Groups
spin off of other groups.
The many religions that supported slavery and the subjection of women
and children to state-sponsored patriarchal control have had to adjust
or choose the sidelines.  Hasn't CLS conceded that the school can
enforce race discrimination laws?  

Marci

Sent from my Verizon Wireless BlackBerry

-Original Message-
From: Esenberg, Richard richard.esenb...@marquette.edu
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 12:32:59
To: hamilto...@aol.comhamilto...@aol.com; Law  Religion issues for
LawAcademicsreligionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

The right of expressive association is not a demand for government
protection in the market place of ideas or a demand for government
support. It is, rather, a shield against government compulsion, i.e.,
the demand that an organization not define itself by adherance to any
particular creed or that it engage in practices

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Brownstein, Alan
Just to make sure I understand your argument, Chip. Is it your position that 
reasonableness is the appropriate standard of review in this case with regard 
to the CLS freedom of association claims because CLS associational freedom will 
not be substantially burdened by the Hastings policy? Or is there another 
reason why you believe a reasonableness standard of review is appropriate in 
this case and your analysis of the magnitude of the burden goes to the 
application of the standard. Are you analogizing the review of freedom of 
association claims challenging a broadly applicable policy to the review of 
content discrimination claims in a designated limited public forum?

Alan Brownstein

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira (Chip) Lupu
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 8:11 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; hamilto...@aol.com; Esenberg, 
Richard
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

Marc Stern is overstating the holding of Gilmore.  Most of the opinion is about 
a state action question -- whether the city is complicit in the segregation of 
certain facilities.  With respect to those private entities or groups with 
which the city is not so complicit, Gilmore has a brief passage at the end of 
the opinion recognizing their freedom of private association, and concluding 
that they cannot be excluded by an injunction from the right to participate in 
recreational activities in a public park.

But Hastings is not running a park where children come to play.  It has created 
a limited public forum, with access to various communications facilities.  Its 
rules have to be non-discriminatory and reasonable in light of the forum's 
purposes.  The all-comers policy is certainly non-discriminatory. We're arguing 
about whether it's reasonable (there might have been an argument about whether 
it was pretextual, but the parties' stipulation seems to eliminate that 
argument completely.)  Some of us on this list think the policy is quite 
reasonable; it is not likely to disturb any group's message, because of the 
incentives of mutual respect and forebearance, but it leaves open the 
possibility of challenge to a group's message.  A law school might reasonably 
see that openness to challenge -- and the imposition of a corresponding duty to 
include all-comers -- as a healthy and necessary quality in a student 
organization. The fact that students are only at the school for three years m!
 ak!
es this even more reasonable; the next cohort of students may want a different 
kind of CLS.  They can show up and challenge, or (more likely, if the local CLS 
views are entrenched) form their own student organization.  CLS wants the right 
to exclude, but it has real trouble demonstrating a tangible harm (rather than 
a harm in principle) from its inability to do so for  purposes of access to 
the forum.

One argument for unreasonableness that seems to me out of bounds is that CLS 
national has an unwaivable statement of faith.  If Hastings CLS can't comply 
with that, that's a problem between the national and the local affiliate, but 
that's not a problem for Hastings LS.  Likewise if the national ACLU, or any 
other national organization, does not like the local Hastings chapter policy on 
some issue.

 
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW 
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg


 Original message 
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 09:35:34 -0400
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu (on behalf of Marc Stern 
mst...@ajcongress.org)
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example  
To: hamilto...@aol.com,Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu,Esenberg, Richard 
richard.esenb...@marquette.edu

Nothing CLS has said challenges Hastings' duty to enforce rules against
its own discrimination on the basis of inter alia sexual orientation or
religion. As Gilmore v. City of Montgomery holds, however, a city's duty
not to engage itself in (there racial) discrimination ) does not
authorize it to deny non-exclusive access to public spaces to groups
that engage in such discrimination. The Court held there that to enforce
non-discrimination rules against such private groups (schools!) would
deny the segregation academies freedom of association. Why isn't Gilmore
controlling here?
Marc Stern 

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of
hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 9:19 AM
To: Esenberg, Richard; Law  Religion issues for LawAcademics
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example

Of course the marketplace works as I described it especially in the US.
Groups thrive and shrivel and respond to and interact with the culture
and if they cannot adapt to broadbased

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Marc Stern
The lower courts in Gilmore had enjoined the city from allowing
segregation academies-established to sidestep a public school
integration order-any use of city facilities, including parks and zoos
for field trips. The Court set aside this last part of the order on the
grounds,inter alia,that it trenched on those schools associational
rights,ie their right to associate with whites only. Why am I
exaggerating when I ask whether Gilmore thus controls Hastings?
It is true, as Ira notes, that much of Gilmore deals with a state action
problem, especially with regard to exclusive uses of public property by
private schools. But that was not the only holding of the case.
Marc 

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Brownstein,
Alan
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 12:27 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

Just to make sure I understand your argument, Chip. Is it your position
that reasonableness is the appropriate standard of review in this case
with regard to the CLS freedom of association claims because CLS
associational freedom will not be substantially burdened by the Hastings
policy? Or is there another reason why you believe a reasonableness
standard of review is appropriate in this case and your analysis of the
magnitude of the burden goes to the application of the standard. Are you
analogizing the review of freedom of association claims challenging a
broadly applicable policy to the review of content discrimination claims
in a designated limited public forum?

Alan Brownstein

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira (Chip) Lupu
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 8:11 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; hamilto...@aol.com;
Esenberg, Richard
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

Marc Stern is overstating the holding of Gilmore.  Most of the opinion
is about a state action question -- whether the city is complicit in the
segregation of certain facilities.  With respect to those private
entities or groups with which the city is not so complicit, Gilmore has
a brief passage at the end of the opinion recognizing their freedom of
private association, and concluding that they cannot be excluded by an
injunction from the right to participate in recreational activities in a
public park.

But Hastings is not running a park where children come to play.  It has
created a limited public forum, with access to various communications
facilities.  Its rules have to be non-discriminatory and reasonable in
light of the forum's purposes.  The all-comers policy is certainly
non-discriminatory. We're arguing about whether it's reasonable (there
might have been an argument about whether it was pretextual, but the
parties' stipulation seems to eliminate that argument completely.)  Some
of us on this list think the policy is quite reasonable; it is not
likely to disturb any group's message, because of the incentives of
mutual respect and forebearance, but it leaves open the possibility of
challenge to a group's message.  A law school might reasonably see that
openness to challenge -- and the imposition of a corresponding duty to
include all-comers -- as a healthy and necessary quality in a student
organization. The fact that students are only at the school for three
years m!
 ak!
es this even more reasonable; the next cohort of students may want a
different kind of CLS.  They can show up and challenge, or (more likely,
if the local CLS views are entrenched) form their own student
organization.  CLS wants the right to exclude, but it has real trouble
demonstrating a tangible harm (rather than a harm in principle) from
its inability to do so for  purposes of access to the forum.

One argument for unreasonableness that seems to me out of bounds is that
CLS national has an unwaivable statement of faith.  If Hastings CLS
can't comply with that, that's a problem between the national and the
local affiliate, but that's not a problem for Hastings LS.  Likewise if
the national ACLU, or any other national organization, does not like the
local Hastings chapter policy on some issue.

 
Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law George Washington University
Law School 2000 H St., NW Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg


 Original message 
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 09:35:34 -0400
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu (on behalf of Marc Stern
mst...@ajcongress.org)
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example  
To: hamilto...@aol.com,Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu,Esenberg, Richard
richard.esenb...@marquette.edu

Nothing CLS has said challenges Hastings' duty to enforce rules against
its own discrimination on the basis of inter alia sexual orientation or
religion

Re: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Lisa A. Runquist


On 5/12/2010 6:51 PM, hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
Here is my question-- why would anyone care about a takeover?  
Wouldn't that just mean that a majority of the members voted in a 
different slate of leaders?  It's not like a dissenter could come in 
and singlehandedly takeover a group, is it?  They have to be chosen by 
a majority.  Then if the group takes a turn some don't like, the 
minority starts their own new group, right??  Isn't that what happens 
everyday with groups of people?  And in particular religious groups?  
There is even a term for it -- schism.  But you don't even need a 
full-out schism to see this happen in religious groups, where a 
congregation will love a pastor but then some start disliking his/her 
sermons or priorities, and switch over to another congregation, or 
start a new congregation, or agitate for a new pastor.  Isn't that the 
American way of a marketplace in ideas and religion?


Well, not really.  To begin with, there are congregational churches and 
hierarchical churches, and churches that fall sort of in the middle.  In 
fact, there is no such thing as boilerplate bylaws for churches 
because they all differ.  Anyway, with hierarchical churches, the church 
is controlled by the higher church authority (e.g. see the recent 
Episcopal cases).  With congregational churches, where the members 
control, there is the question of who is a true member and has a right 
to vote.  Normally the people have to be admitted; you do not generally 
become a member just by attending meetings.  Sometimes the members have 
to take classes; generally they need to agree to a statement of faith.  
If someone does not do these things they can still attend the church, 
but they cannot vote at church meetings.  I had one case that went to 
trial over who the members of the church were as of a specific date.


The vast majority of church splits occur, not because someone doesn't 
like a pastor's sermons (as you said, that person will probably just 
find another church where he or she is more comfortable), but over some 
doctrinal issue.  And courts cannot decide matters of church doctrine; 
they must decide cases on the basis of neutral principles of law.  The 
case I mentioned re the members had to do with whether the church was 
going to remain a Christian Church/Church of Christ, or whether it was 
going to become a Pentecostal Church (and yes, new people came in and 
claimed (unsuccessfully) that they were members, in order to try to 
wrest the property away from the original church).
So why does CLS or any other group need protection from the 
possibility that outsiders will take them over?  If the CLS leaders 
are so weak that those with different views can take over, they can 
form a whole new group.  So just how does the all-comers rule 
disadvantage CLS?  I think this need for protection against takeovers 
is just a pretense for the intent to discriminate on the basis of 
sexual orientation.
As set forth above, churches (and other religious groups) all have their 
own doctrines and beliefs, and generally require members to adhere to 
those beliefs.  A statement of faith of a Christian church is going to 
be totally different from a new age type church.  And there is no 
uniformity of beliefs between the various Christian churches.  Doctrinal 
disputes have been going on, probably as long as there have been people 
to believe (if you get 5 rabbis together, you will probably end up with 
6 opinions).  The issue of sexual orientation is really a very recent 
dispute that has arisen in some religious organizations, and is only one 
item on a long list of beliefs, any one of which would disqualify 
someone from membership/leadership in the particular organization.  
Truly, most Christian groups do NOT spend most of their time on the 
issue of sexual orientation.


Lisa
In a message dated 5/12/2010 9:21:14 P.M. Eastern Daylight Time, 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu writes:


In any event, I think those who argue that an all comers rule is
OK because takeovers are unlikely would in effect be relying on a
pattern or practice of groups choosing leaders based on their
views. Usually a pattern or practice is somewhat equivalent to a
rule, where antidiscrimination principles are at stake. Thus in a
sense CLS is being denied benefits in part because of its honesty
in admitting what its members will do, and the all comers rule is
supported because groups will in fact engage in discrimination,
though perhaps not by way of formal rules.

Mark Scarberry
Pepperdine


   


--
Lisa A. Runquist
Runquist  Associates
Attorneys at Law
17554 Community Street
Northridge, CA 91325
(818)609-7761
(818)609-7794 (fax)
l...@runquist.com
http://www.runquist.com



___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Rick Duncan
Chip, the problem with the all comers policy, even if applied across the board, 
is that it entirely destroys the ability of student expressive groups to 
organize around a set of beliefs and viewpoints. It is not viewpoint 
discriminatory (if applied to all), but it destroys all attempts to organize on 
the basis of viewpoint and belief.

It is like a rule that says no one can engage in speech on public sidewalks. 
Such a rule completely eliminates free speech in a public forum, even though it 
doesn't discriminate on the basis of viewpoint.

If CLS and all other student expressive groups have a right of expressive 
association concerning their membership policies, Hastings violates that First 
Amendment right by demanding that it be waived as a condition of access to a 
limited public forum. Such an unconstitutional condition is also an 
unreasonable restriction in light of the purpose of the forum (which is to 
create a marketplace of ideas for student group expression).

Rick

Rick Duncan 
Welpton Professor of Law 
University of Nebraska College of Law 
Lincoln, NE 68583-0902


And against the constitution I have never raised a storm,It's the scoundrels 
who've corrupted it that I want to reform --Dick Gaughan (from the song, 
Thomas Muir of Huntershill)





  ___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Eric Rassbach
Chip -

Does the situation where the Mormon student shut down the Washburn chapter of 
CLS represent the sort of dynamism, openness and challenge you are talking 
about?  (That's the real-life on-campus example you asked for earlier and was 
cited in Petitioner's brief at page 33.)

That scenario seems to create the opposite of dynamism, by allowing one student 
to enlist the government in shutting down the dialogue altogether.  Remember, 
we aren't talking about the ability to create dialogue--CLS meetings are open 
to all students--we are talking about the ability of one group of students to 
get the government to withdraw permission from another group of students to use 
email, bulletin boards, etc. to communicate with the rest of the student body. 
Conditioning permission to speak to the entire student body on relinquishing 
any ability to affirm a specific set of beliefs burdens freedom of association 
under Healy.

The sort of open-source associational dynamic you describe sounds nice if you 
don't get too specific about how it actually works in practice, but in reality 
even open-source systems always need exclusionary rules for there to be a 
coherent dialogue.  Even Wikipedia has rules against vandals.

Eric




From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
On Behalf Of Ira (Chip) Lupu [icl...@law.gwu.edu]
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 1:30 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

Alan asks a good question about the standard of review.  This is a designated 
public forum.  The reasonableness standard (that is, reasonable in light of 
the purposes of the forum) ordinarily applies to exclusion of speech content 
(by subject matter, or by viewpoint, but the latter will be never be 
reasonable).  But the Hastings LS all-comers policy is not an exclusion of 
speech content -- it's a policy regarding  associational freedom.  It only 
indirectly and occasionally (perhaps rarely, perhaps never) operates to exclude 
any speech content at all.  Because the challenged policy covers association 
and not content, I think the requirements of reasonableness (in light of the 
purposes of the forum) might be even weaker than would be the case for a policy 
of subject matter exclusion.  And, because the challenged all-comers policy 
rarely if ever will compromise the group's message (and hasn't been shown to do 
so here), there is no substantial burden on associational freedom.
And -- to your question, Rick -- the forum can have more than one purpose.  It 
can be designed to have diverse groups (e.g., by allowing a very small number 
to form a group), and it can simultaneously be designed to permit dynamism, 
openness, and challenge within a group if a student wants to do that (hence 
all-comers). If these policies are reasonable, it is not an unconstitutional 
condition to make compliance with them a condition of access to the forum.  
(The most orthodox CLS students can still meet outside the forum, and may 
exclude anyone they choose to exclude in that separate associational context.)

Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg


 Original message 
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 09:26:48 -0700
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu (on behalf of Brownstein, Alan 
aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu)
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

Just to make sure I understand your argument, Chip. Is it your position that 
reasonableness is the appropriate standard of review in this case with regard 
to the CLS freedom of association claims because CLS associational freedom 
will not be substantially burdened by the Hastings policy? Or is there another 
reason why you believe a reasonableness standard of review is appropriate in 
this case and your analysis of the magnitude of the burden goes to the 
application of the standard. Are you analogizing the review of freedom of 
association claims challenging a broadly applicable policy to the review of 
content discrimination claims in a designated limited public forum?

Alan Brownstein

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Ira (Chip) Lupu
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 8:11 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics; hamilto...@aol.com; Esenberg, 
Richard
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

Marc Stern is overstating the holding of Gilmore.  Most of the opinion is 
about a state action question -- whether the city is complicit in the 
segregation of certain facilities.  With respect to those private entities or 
groups with which the city is not so complicit, Gilmore has a brief passage at 
the end

Re: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread hamilton02

Rick-- This strikes me as your desired interpretation of the law, not the law 
as it stands.  


 and it does not reflect the case.  Yours and CLS's reasoning leads to an 
absolutely absurd result.

  When we have a court telling a university or law school that it cannot 
require all school-supported groups to include all students (if any student 
desires), as part of a mission to create open dialogue, then we might as well 
hand in our tenure and the academic freedom attached to it.  As I said at the 
start, CLS's position is deeply anti-intellectual and requires one to buy into 
a Balkanized view of the universe.
Years ago, I taught a seminar in Budapest with students from the Balkans.  They 
described the disintegration of a shared culture this way.  It used to be that 
when you got on the subway or the train, everyone was a fellow citizen, not a 
Jew or a Christian or a Muslim.  Everyone shared some common ground and people 
were polite to each other regardless.  Then, the disintegration started and 
people became very conscious of the religious identity of the person across the 
aisle and seated next to them.  Once that crept into the mindset, you became 
very uncomfortable seated next to someone of a different religion, you 
distrusted other believers automatically, as part of the culture.  I will 
never forget their sense of loss or their sincerity.  I think CLS's position 
(as well as Wide Awake's position in Rosenberger) as being a step in that 
direction.  In this era, we need far more effort to find common ground and ways 
for different believers to speak to each other.  Exclusion in the academic 
context, where there is supposed to be wide-ranging, challenging discourse, 
seems precisely the wrong move.

Marci


-Original Message-
From: Rick Duncan nebraskalawp...@yahoo.com
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Thu, May 13, 2010 12:51 pm
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example




Chip, the problem with the all comers policy, even if applied across the board, 
is that it entirely destroys the ability of student expressive groups to 
organize around a set of beliefs and viewpoints. It is not viewpoint 
discriminatory (if applied to all), but it destroys all attempts to organize on 
the basis of viewpoint and belief.

It is like a rule that says no one can engage in speech on public sidewalks. 
Such a rule completely eliminates free speech in a public forum, even though it 
doesn't discriminate on the basis of viewpoint.

If CLS and all other student expressive groups have a right of expressive 
association concerning their membership policies, Hastings violates that First 
Amendment right by demanding that it be waived as a condition of access to a 
limited public forum. Such an unconstitutional condition is also an 
unreasonable restriction in light of the purpose of the forum (which is to 
create a marketplace of ideas for student group expression).

Rick


Rick Duncan 
Welpton Professor of Law 
University of Nebraska College of Law 
Lincoln, NE 68583-0902



And against the constitution I have never raised a storm,It's the scoundrels 
who've corrupted it that I want to reform --Dick Gaughan (from the song, 
Thomas Muir of Huntershill)








___
o post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
o subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
ttp://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
nyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
ead the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
essages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-13 Thread Ira (Chip) Lupu
Eric:

I would need a thick and objective description of what happened at Washburn in 
order to evaluate its significance in this larger argument.   For example, what 
was the Mormon student saying (or planning to say) about the Bible that caused 
such consternation and conflict?  Was there a back story of conflict between 
Mormons (or this particular student) and CLS members that preceded this 
incident?   That would all be quite useful to know, but I have to say that it's 
still only one story, and I would guess that CLS lawyers (who have been 
litigating these cases for years) would have been on the lookout for such 
incidents.  So one story and one story only would not change my basic intuition 
that an all-comers policy in a school-created forum presents a cooperation 
game, where everyone understands that aggressive challenges and takeovers will 
invite reciprocal action, and that such tit-for-tat responses will quickly 
destroy the forum.

Chip

Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW 
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg


 Original message 
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 13:59:20 -0400
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu (on behalf of Eric Rassbach 
erassb...@becketfund.org)
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example  
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

Chip -

Does the situation where the Mormon student shut down the Washburn chapter of 
CLS represent the sort of dynamism, openness and challenge you are talking 
about?  (That's the real-life on-campus example you asked for earlier and was 
cited in Petitioner's brief at page 33.)

That scenario seems to create the opposite of dynamism, by allowing one 
student to enlist the government in shutting down the dialogue altogether.  
Remember, we aren't talking about the ability to create dialogue--CLS meetings 
are open to all students--we are talking about the ability of one group of 
students to get the government to withdraw permission from another group of 
students to use email, bulletin boards, etc. to communicate with the rest of 
the student body. Conditioning permission to speak to the entire student body 
on relinquishing any ability to affirm a specific set of beliefs burdens 
freedom of association under Healy.

The sort of open-source associational dynamic you describe sounds nice if you 
don't get too specific about how it actually works in practice, but in reality 
even open-source systems always need exclusionary rules for there to be a 
coherent dialogue.  Even Wikipedia has rules against vandals.

Eric




From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] 
On Behalf Of Ira (Chip) Lupu [icl...@law.gwu.edu]
Sent: Thursday, May 13, 2010 1:30 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

Alan asks a good question about the standard of review.  This is a designated 
public forum.  The reasonableness standard (that is, reasonable in light of 
the purposes of the forum) ordinarily applies to exclusion of speech content 
(by subject matter, or by viewpoint, but the latter will be never be 
reasonable).  But the Hastings LS all-comers policy is not an exclusion of 
speech content -- it's a policy regarding  associational freedom.  It only 
indirectly and occasionally (perhaps rarely, perhaps never) operates to 
exclude any speech content at all.  Because the challenged policy covers 
association and not content, I think the requirements of reasonableness (in 
light of the purposes of the forum) might be even weaker than would be the 
case for a policy of subject matter exclusion.  And, because the challenged 
all-comers policy rarely if ever will compromise the group's message (and 
hasn't been shown to do so here), there is no substantial burden on 
associational freedom.
And -- to your question, Rick -- the forum can have more than one purpose.  It 
can be designed to have diverse groups (e.g., by allowing a very small number 
to form a group), and it can simultaneously be designed to permit dynamism, 
openness, and challenge within a group if a student wants to do that (hence 
all-comers). If these policies are reasonable, it is not an unconstitutional 
condition to make compliance with them a condition of access to the forum.  
(The most orthodox CLS students can still meet outside the forum, and may 
exclude anyone they choose to exclude in that separate associational context.)

Ira C. Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law
George Washington University Law School
2000 H St., NW
Washington, DC 20052
(202)994-7053
My SSRN papers are here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=181272#reg


 Original message 
Date: Thu, 13 May 2010 09:26:48 -0700
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu (on behalf

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-12 Thread Brownstein, Alan
I'm sorry to be late joining this thread, but I thought that the argument in 
the CLS brief that Hastings engaged in viewpoint discrimination by prohibiting 
groups from discriminating against individuals on religious grounds, while 
permitting discrimination on political grounds, made no sense to me. This is, 
after all, a pretty common distinction that is drawn in many civil rights 
statutes. I appreciate the need for religious accommodations in many of these 
statutes, but I never thought that if Title VII did not have the exemption for 
religious organizations that currently exists that the law would be 
unconstitutional because it is viewpoint discriminatory.

Moreover, the implications of this argument are problematic to say the least. 
CLS seemed to arguing that it was legitimate, even praiseworthy, for 
nonreligious clubs to be prohibited from discriminating on the basis of 
religion, even though no clubs were prohibited from discriminating on political 
grounds. If distinguishing between religious and political discrimination is 
viewpoint discrimination prohibited by the free speech clause, wouldn't it also 
be viewpoint discrimination if the Hastings policy allowed the CLS to 
discriminate against liberals, while prohibiting the Marxist Club from 
discriminating against Christians. Indeed, would it not be unconstitutional 
viewpoint discrimination to ever protect individuals against discrimination 
based on religious beliefs without also prohibiting discrimination based on 
political belief? Why couldn't a nonreligious individual who has strong 
political convictions argue that a law providing individuals who hold (and 
express) religious beliefs more protection than he receives against 
discrimination based on his political beliefs is unconstitutional viewpoint 
discrimination.

Is this really a road we want to go down?

Alan Brownstein

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Scarberry, Mark
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 10:21 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

Hastings' initial policy prevented CLS from discriminating on religious 
grounds but did not prevent political groups from discriminating on political 
grounds. (As Michael McConnell's brief pointed out, with quotes from, if I 
remember correctly, Larry Tribe, Justice Brennan, and Justice O'Connor, the 
ability to choose those who determine an expressive association's message is 
integral to the freedom of expressive association and constitutive of the 
expressive associational group; considering it to be discrimination in the way 
we ordinarily use that term is a category error.) Probably because it realized 
that such a policy was indefensible, Hastings tried to switch to an all-comers 
policy that supposedly would apply to all groups. That all comers policy is the 
one Doug is referencing as being egregiously unconst as to both political and 
religious groups. The record seems to support the view that Hastings continued 
to apply its original policy against CLS, along with the all-comers policy, 
though one could argue that the latter encompasses the former. The record also 
shows no enforcement of the all comers policy against groups, including 
Hastings Outlaw, that had provisions in their constitutions requiring officers 
to support the group's mission.

Mark Scarberry
Pepperdine

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Sanford Levinson
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 10:06 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

Doug may very well be right, but I must say that plowing through the oral 
argument didn't highlight the difference between CLS and, say, the Young 
Democrats.  If Hastings is indeed selecting out religious groups for special 
all comers non-discrimination with regard to eligibility for leadership 
positions, then I agree it's a no brainer.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 12:01 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

CLS does not claim that it should be treated differently from political groups. 
 Hastings' written rule treated religious groups differently, because it 
prohibited religious discrimination but did not prohibit political 
discrimination. The only groups that could not organize around a viewpoint were 
religious group.  It's all comers rule is egregiously unconstitutional as to 
political groups as well as to religious groups.

Quoting Sanford Levinson slevin...@law.utexas.edu:

 I can't figure out exactly why religious groups deserve to be treated
 differently from, say, the young Democrats or Republicans or the
 Sierra Club.  The Constitution says not that we have to treat
 religion differently, but, rather, that we have to keep engaging

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-12 Thread Brownstein, Alan
I'm sorry to be late joining this thread, but I thought that the argument in 
the CLS brief that Hastings engaged in viewpoint discrimination by prohibiting 
groups from discriminating against individuals on religious grounds, while 
permitting discrimination on political grounds, made no sense to me. This is, 
after all, a pretty common distinction that is drawn in many civil rights 
statutes. I appreciate the need for religious accommodations in many of these 
statutes, but I never thought that if Title VII did not have the exemption for 
religious organizations that currently exists that the law would be 
unconstitutional because it is viewpoint discriminatory.

Moreover, the implications of this argument are problematic to say the least. 
CLS seemed to arguing that it was legitimate, even praiseworthy, for 
nonreligious clubs to be prohibited from discriminating on the basis of 
religion, even though no clubs were prohibited from discriminating on political 
grounds. If distinguishing between religious and political discrimination is 
viewpoint discrimination prohibited by the free speech clause, wouldn't it also 
be viewpoint discrimination if the Hastings policy allowed the CLS to 
discriminate against liberals, while prohibiting the Marxist Club from 
discriminating against Christians. Indeed, would it not be unconstitutional 
viewpoint discrimination to ever protect individuals against discrimination 
based on religious beliefs without also prohibiting discrimination based on 
political belief? Why couldn't a nonreligious individual who has strong 
political convictions argue that a law providing individuals who hold (and 
express) religious beliefs more protection than he receives against 
discrimination based on his political beliefs is unconstitutional viewpoint 
discrimination.

Is this really a road we want to go down?

Alan Brownstein



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Scarberry, Mark
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 10:21 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

Hastings' initial policy prevented CLS from discriminating on religious 
grounds but did not prevent political groups from discriminating on political 
grounds. (As Michael McConnell's brief pointed out, with quotes from, if I 
remember correctly, Larry Tribe, Justice Brennan, and Justice O'Connor, the 
ability to choose those who determine an expressive association's message is 
integral to the freedom of expressive association and constitutive of the 
expressive associational group; considering it to be discrimination in the way 
we ordinarily use that term is a category error.) Probably because it realized 
that such a policy was indefensible, Hastings tried to switch to an all-comers 
policy that supposedly would apply to all groups. That all comers policy is the 
one Doug is referencing as being egregiously unconst as to both political and 
religious groups. The record seems to support the view that Hastings continued 
to apply its original policy against CLS, along with the all-comers policy, 
though one could argue that the latter encompasses the former. The record also 
shows no enforcement of the all comers policy against groups, including 
Hastings Outlaw, that had provisions in their constitutions requiring officers 
to support the group's mission.

Mark Scarberry
Pepperdine

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Sanford Levinson
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 10:06 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

Doug may very well be right, but I must say that plowing through the oral 
argument didn't highlight the difference between CLS and, say, the Young 
Democrats.  If Hastings is indeed selecting out religious groups for special 
all comers non-discrimination with regard to eligibility for leadership 
positions, then I agree it's a no brainer.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 12:01 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

CLS does not claim that it should be treated differently from political groups. 
 Hastings' written rule treated religious groups differently, because it 
prohibited religious discrimination but did not prohibit political 
discrimination. The only groups that could not organize around a viewpoint were 
religious group.  It's all comers rule is egregiously unconstitutional as to 
political groups as well as to religious groups.


___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-12 Thread Douglas Laycock
Alan, you are assuming that any individual could make this claim, and I agree 
that that sounds problematic.

But at the level of groups organized around a viewpoint, the distinction is 
fundamental. The Hastings written policy was that groups could enforce their 
ability to organize around political viewpoints but could not enforce their 
ability to organize around religious viewpoints. That is viewpoint 
discrimination.

It is also a category mistake.  The civil rights laws prohibited religious 
discrimination with a view to the commerical world.  Congress never meant to 
require Baptist rabbis and atheist church elders.  A ban on religious 
discrimination as applied to a religious organization is as idiotic as a ban on 
political discrimination as applied to a political party.  Hastings has 
borrowed the Congressional list of protected categories and applied it in a 
wholly inappropriate context.

Quoting Brownstein, Alan aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu:

 I'm sorry to be late joining this thread, but I thought that the 
 argument in the CLS brief that Hastings engaged in viewpoint 
 discrimination by prohibiting groups from discriminating against 
 individuals on religious grounds, while permitting discrimination on 
 political grounds, made no sense to me. This is, after all, a pretty 
 common distinction that is drawn in many civil rights statutes. I 
 appreciate the need for religious accommodations in many of these 
 statutes, but I never thought that if Title VII did not have the 
 exemption for religious organizations that currently exists that the 
 law would be unconstitutional because it is viewpoint discriminatory.

 Moreover, the implications of this argument are problematic to say 
 the least. CLS seemed to arguing that it was legitimate, even 
 praiseworthy, for nonreligious clubs to be prohibited from 
 discriminating on the basis of religion, even though no clubs were 
 prohibited from discriminating on political grounds. If 
 distinguishing between religious and political discrimination is 
 viewpoint discrimination prohibited by the free speech clause, 
 wouldn't it also be viewpoint discrimination if the Hastings policy 
 allowed the CLS to discriminate against liberals, while prohibiting 
 the Marxist Club from discriminating against Christians. Indeed, 
 would it not be unconstitutional viewpoint discrimination to ever 
 protect individuals against discrimination based on religious beliefs 
 without also prohibiting discrimination based on political belief? 
 Why couldn't a nonreligious individual who has strong political 
 convictions argue that a law providing individuals who hold (and 
 express) religious beliefs more protection than he receives against 
 discrimination based on his political beliefs is unconstitutional 
 viewpoint discrimination.

 Is this really a road we want to go down?

 Alan Brownstein



 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Scarberry, 
 Mark
 Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 10:21 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

 Hastings' initial policy prevented CLS from discriminating on 
 religious grounds but did not prevent political groups from 
 discriminating on political grounds. (As Michael McConnell's brief 
 pointed out, with quotes from, if I remember correctly, Larry Tribe, 
 Justice Brennan, and Justice O'Connor, the ability to choose those 
 who determine an expressive association's message is integral to the 
 freedom of expressive association and constitutive of the expressive 
 associational group; considering it to be discrimination in the way 
 we ordinarily use that term is a category error.) Probably because it 
 realized that such a policy was indefensible, Hastings tried to 
 switch to an all-comers policy that supposedly would apply to all 
 groups. That all comers policy is the one Doug is referencing as 
 being egregiously unconst as to both political and religious groups. 
 The record seems to support the view that Hastings continued to apply 
 its original policy against CLS, along with the all-comers policy, 
 though one could argue that the latter encompasses the former. The 
 record also shows no enforcement of the all comers policy against 
 groups, including Hastings Outlaw, that had provisions in their 
 constitutions requiring officers to support the group's mission.

 Mark Scarberry
 Pepperdine

 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Sanford 
 Levinson
 Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 10:06 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

 Doug may very well be right, but I must say that plowing through the 
 oral argument didn't highlight the difference between CLS and, say, 
 the Young Democrats.  If Hastings is indeed selecting out religious 
 groups for special all comers non-discrimination with regard to 
 eligibility

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-12 Thread Brownstein, Alan
A quick response, Doug. With regard to my example about individuals, I agree 
that this is the most problematic example, but I'm not sure what the argument 
would be that precludes an individual from challenging an anti-discrimination 
law as viewpoint discriminatory. (A law that protected individuals holding left 
wing political views from discrimination, but failed to provide comparable 
protection to individuals holding right wings views would be viewpoint 
discriminatory, wouldn't it?)

As to categories, if there were only two categories - houses of worship and 
commercial institutions - life would be a lot simpler. But there is a lot 
between these two categories and I think the world of religiously, culturally, 
politically, or socially affiliated non-profits raises a lot of complicated 
problems.

But basically, I think my disagreement with you comes down to this. I certainly 
agree that if Title VII required a synagogue to hire a Baptist as a rabbi, that 
would be unconstitutional (as well as idiotic).  But I would not be arguing 
that it is unconstitutional because it violates the free speech clause 
prohibition against viewpoint discrimination because Title VII doesn't prohibit 
discrimination on political grounds. Would you?

I have considerably sympathy for the CLS freedom of association argument 
(although I worry about how far such an argument might extend.) But I continue 
to believe that extending the religion is a viewpoint of speech protected by 
the free speech clause prohibition against viewpoint discrimination argument 
is fraught with perils.

Alan Brownstein

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Wednesday, May 12, 2010 10:11 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

Alan, you are assuming that any individual could make this claim, and I agree 
that that sounds problematic.

But at the level of groups organized around a viewpoint, the distinction is 
fundamental. The Hastings written policy was that groups could enforce their 
ability to organize around political viewpoints but could not enforce their 
ability to organize around religious viewpoints. That is viewpoint 
discrimination.

It is also a category mistake.  The civil rights laws prohibited religious 
discrimination with a view to the commerical world.  Congress never meant to 
require Baptist rabbis and atheist church elders.  A ban on religious 
discrimination as applied to a religious organization is as idiotic as a ban on 
political discrimination as applied to a political party.  Hastings has 
borrowed the Congressional list of protected categories and applied it in a 
wholly inappropriate context.

Quoting Brownstein, Alan aebrownst...@ucdavis.edu:

 I'm sorry to be late joining this thread, but I thought that the
 argument in the CLS brief that Hastings engaged in viewpoint
 discrimination by prohibiting groups from discriminating against
 individuals on religious grounds, while permitting discrimination on
 political grounds, made no sense to me. This is, after all, a pretty
 common distinction that is drawn in many civil rights statutes. I
 appreciate the need for religious accommodations in many of these
 statutes, but I never thought that if Title VII did not have the
 exemption for religious organizations that currently exists that the
 law would be unconstitutional because it is viewpoint discriminatory.

 Moreover, the implications of this argument are problematic to say
 the least. CLS seemed to arguing that it was legitimate, even
 praiseworthy, for nonreligious clubs to be prohibited from
 discriminating on the basis of religion, even though no clubs were
 prohibited from discriminating on political grounds. If
 distinguishing between religious and political discrimination is
 viewpoint discrimination prohibited by the free speech clause,
 wouldn't it also be viewpoint discrimination if the Hastings policy
 allowed the CLS to discriminate against liberals, while prohibiting
 the Marxist Club from discriminating against Christians. Indeed,
 would it not be unconstitutional viewpoint discrimination to ever
 protect individuals against discrimination based on religious beliefs
 without also prohibiting discrimination based on political belief?
 Why couldn't a nonreligious individual who has strong political
 convictions argue that a law providing individuals who hold (and
 express) religious beliefs more protection than he receives against
 discrimination based on his political beliefs is unconstitutional
 viewpoint discrimination.

 Is this really a road we want to go down?

 Alan Brownstein



 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Scarberry,
 Mark
 Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 10:21 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

 Hastings' initial policy prevented CLS from discriminating

Re: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-12 Thread Steven Jamar
1.  What evidence is there that Outlaw excludes those who don't support its
positions?

2.  Asssuming there is such evidence, once again Rick is refusing to
recognize that associational rights, expressive rights, and religious rights
are not all one thing governed by a single, unified or coherent set of
principles.

If one takes Rick's point seriously, then there is no establishment clause
(other than coercion) or free exercise accommodations allowed because every
accommodation for a religious group would be viewpoint based.

Steve


On Wed, May 12, 2010 at 6:14 PM, Rick Duncan nebraskalawp...@yahoo.comwrote:

 Alan, CLS is not discriminating against protected groups qua groups.

 CLS wishes to organize around a set of beliefs and to exclude from
 membership those who don't subscribe to those beliefs. This is what
 expressive association is designed to protect.

 When Hastings requires CLS to admit members who don't share its beliefs
 about the divinity of Christ or the good of human sexuality, it prevents CLS
 from effectively expressing those viewpoints as a group. At the same time,
 other student groups are allowed to exclude members who don't subscribe to
 the beliefs of these other groups. Thus, Outlaw can exclude those who don't
 support its beliefs about gay sexual equality, but CLS can not exclude those
 who reject its beliefs about the sinfulness of homosexuality.

 How is this not viewpoint discrimination?

 Rick Duncan
 Welpton Professor of Law
 University of Nebraska College of Law
 Lincoln, NE 68583-0902


 And against the constitution I have never raised a storm,It's the
 scoundrels who've corrupted it that I want to reform --Dick Gaughan (from
 the song, Thomas Muir of Huntershill)





 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
 wrongly) forward the messages to others.




-- 
Prof. Steven Jamar
Howard University School of Law
Associate Director, Institute of Intellectual Property and Social Justice
(IIPSJ) Inc.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-12 Thread Scarberry, Mark
Hastings' Outlaw's constitution said officers could be removed for not 
supporting its mission, if I remember correctly. Hastings did not require it to 
amend its constitution.
 
In any event, I think those who argue that an all comers rule is OK because 
takeovers are unlikely would in effect be relying on a pattern or practice of 
groups choosing leaders based on their views. Usually a pattern or practice is 
somewhat equivalent to a rule, where antidiscrimination principles are at 
stake. Thus in a sense CLS is being denied benefits in part because of its 
honesty in admitting what its members will do, and the all comers rule is 
supported because groups will in fact engage in discrimination, though perhaps 
not by way of formal rules.
 
Mark Scarberry
Pepperdine



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu on behalf of Steven Jamar
Sent: Wed 5/12/2010 6:06 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example


1.  What evidence is there that Outlaw excludes those who don't support its 
positions?

2.  Asssuming there is such evidence, once again Rick is refusing to recognize 
that associational rights, expressive rights, and religious rights are not all 
one thing governed by a single, unified or coherent set of principles.

If one takes Rick's point seriously, then there is no establishment clause  
(other than coercion) or free exercise accommodations allowed because every 
accommodation for a religious group would be viewpoint based.

Steve



On Wed, May 12, 2010 at 6:14 PM, Rick Duncan nebraskalawp...@yahoo.com wrote:


Alan, CLS is not discriminating against protected groups qua groups.

CLS wishes to organize around a set of beliefs and to exclude from membership 
those who don't subscribe to those beliefs. This is what expressive association 
is designed to protect.

When Hastings requires CLS to admit members who don't share its beliefs about 
the divinity of Christ or the good of human sexuality, it prevents CLS from 
effectively expressing those viewpoints as a group. At the same time, other 
student groups are allowed to exclude members who don't subscribe to the 
beliefs of these other groups. Thus, Outlaw can exclude those who don't support 
its beliefs about gay sexual equality, but CLS can not exclude those who reject 
its beliefs about the sinfulness of homosexuality.

How is this not viewpoint discrimination?


Rick Duncan 
Welpton Professor of Law 

University of Nebraska College of Law 
Lincoln, NE 68583-0902



And against the constitution I have never raised a storm,It's the scoundrels 
who've corrupted it that I want to reform --Dick Gaughan (from the song, 
Thomas Muir of Huntershill)





___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
forward the messages to others.





-- 
Prof. Steven Jamar
Howard University School of Law
Associate Director, Institute of Intellectual Property and Social Justice 
(IIPSJ) Inc.

winmail.dat___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-12 Thread Scarberry, Mark
So I presume Marci would have no problem with a bunch of Christians who join a 
campus Chabad group and turn it into a Christian evangelization organization. 
Or a bunch of students who favor prayer in public schools taking over a campus 
ACLU or Americans United chapter. Or a bunch of Federalists taking over a 
campus ACS chapter. After all, the Jewish students or the ACLU or AU or ACS 
students could just form other groups. But that approach is deeply unfaithful 
to the core concept of expressive associational freedom. It is sad that Marci, 
and the educational establishment (united as it seems to be against CLS in CLS 
v. Martinez), would embrace such a crude majoritarian approach.
 
Mark Scarberry
Pepperdine



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu on behalf of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Wed 5/12/2010 6:51 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example


Here is my question-- why would anyone care about a takeover?  Wouldn't that 
just mean that a majority of the members voted in a different slate of leaders? 
 It's not like a dissenter could come in and singlehandedly takeover a group, 
is it?  They have to be chosen by a majority.  Then if the group takes a turn 
some don't like, the minority starts their own new group, right??  Isn't that 
what happens everyday with groups of people?  And in particular religious 
groups?  There is even a term for it -- schism.  But you don't even need a 
full-out schism to see this happen in religious groups, where a congregation 
will love a pastor but then some start disliking his/her sermons or priorities, 
and switch over to another congregation, or start a new congregation, or 
agitate for a new pastor.  Isn't that the American way of a marketplace in 
ideas and religion?
 
So why does CLS or any other group need protection from the possibility that 
outsiders will take them over?  If the CLS leaders are so weak that those 
with different views can take over, they can form a whole new group.  So just 
how does the all-comers rule disadvantage CLS?  I think this need for 
protection against takeovers is just a pretense for the intent to discriminate 
on the basis of sexual orientation.  
 
 
Marci
 
 
 
In a message dated 5/12/2010 9:21:14 P.M. Eastern Daylight Time, 
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu writes:

In any event, I think those who argue that an all comers rule is OK 
because takeovers are unlikely would in effect be relying on a pattern or 
practice of groups choosing leaders based on their views. Usually a pattern or 
practice is somewhat equivalent to a rule, where antidiscrimination principles 
are at stake. Thus in a sense CLS is being denied benefits in part because of 
its honesty in admitting what its members will do, and the all comers rule is 
supported because groups will in fact engage in discrimination, though perhaps 
not by way of formal rules.

Mark Scarberry
Pepperdine



 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-11 Thread Lisa A. Runquist


On 5/10/2010 8:21 PM, Steven Jamar wrote:
Religion and religious organizations are different from other 
organizations.  The constitution says we need to treat religion 
differently.  Unless we decide that speech and association and equal 
treatment principles trump the religion clauses, we need to give them 
effect somehow -- both the free exercise and establishment clauses.


And the constitution does not say that religious organizations are to be 
treated worse than all other groups.  The government cannot establish 
religion, but it also cannot prohibit the free exercise of religion.  
Yet that, it seems to me, is exactly what the college is trying to do here.


What would be the result if the university made an exception for 
religious organizations -- then it is not treating the religious 
organization equally. 
As long as all religious organizations are treated the same way, then 
there is no violation.  If, for example, it allowed CLS to meet but 
prohibited a Muslim group from meeting, then this would be not treating 
the religious organizations equally.


Lisa

--
Lisa A. Runquist
Runquist  Associates
Attorneys at Law
17554 Community Street
Northridge, CA 91325
(818)609-7761
(818)609-7794 (fax)
l...@runquist.com
http://www.runquist.com



___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-11 Thread Sanford Levinson
I can't figure out exactly why religious groups deserve to be treated 
differently from, say, the young Democrats or Republicans or the Sierra Club.  
The Constitution says not that we have to treat religion differently, but, 
rather, that we have to keep engaging in an endless conversation about the 
interplay of religion and state.  Sometimes that might require different 
treatment, as in accommodating people who are unwilling to work on Saturday.  
Note, though, that the Court, rightly or wrongly, refused to extend the 
conscientious objector accommodation to a serious Catholic who was opposed 
only to the Vietnam War (on just war grounds).  Nor, of course, was the Court 
generous to Native Americans either in Lyng or Smith, both of which, I have to 
say, seemed more appealing, on their facts, than the CLS case. But none of 
these cases really involved the freedom of association arguments that are 
really at the heart of the argument.  

Am I correct, incidentally, that the principle being advocated for would allow 
any religious society to restrict its leadership to males if it had a religious 
principle that only men were fit for such roles?  Judge (now Professor) 
McConnell seemed to emphasize the belief-status distinction in his argument, 
but I'm not sure I understand it when the justification for status 
discrimination is a sincere (and quite traditional, often) religious belief.  
The argument that we, as a society have decided that race and sex/gender are 
just different from other categories of differentiation certainly can't hold, 
at least for the latter, since I'm confident that McConnell (and, I suspect, 
almost everybody on this list) would not allow a Title VII-like action against 
the Catholic Church or Orthodox Judaism or even strip those religions of their 
tax exemption because of their blatant sexism.   

Having read the oral argument, incidentally, I do wonder if there will be an 
effort simply to dismiss it as improvidently granted, given that most of the 
time seemed to have been spent on trying to figure out what exactly were the 
facts and the relationship between various stipulations and written policies 
of the Law School.  

sandy

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Lisa A. Runquist
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 11:29 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example


On 5/10/2010 8:21 PM, Steven Jamar wrote:
 Religion and religious organizations are different from other 
 organizations.  The constitution says we need to treat religion 
 differently.  Unless we decide that speech and association and equal 
 treatment principles trump the religion clauses, we need to give them 
 effect somehow -- both the free exercise and establishment clauses.

And the constitution does not say that religious organizations are to be 
treated worse than all other groups.  The government cannot establish 
religion, but it also cannot prohibit the free exercise of religion.  
Yet that, it seems to me, is exactly what the college is trying to do here.

 What would be the result if the university made an exception for 
 religious organizations -- then it is not treating the religious 
 organization equally. 
As long as all religious organizations are treated the same way, then 
there is no violation.  If, for example, it allowed CLS to meet but 
prohibited a Muslim group from meeting, then this would be not treating 
the religious organizations equally.

Lisa

-- 
Lisa A. Runquist
Runquist  Associates
Attorneys at Law
17554 Community Street
Northridge, CA 91325
(818)609-7761
(818)609-7794 (fax)
l...@runquist.com
http://www.runquist.com



___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-11 Thread Steven Jamar
Yes.  Free exercise, establishment, free speech, freedom of  
association, and equality are in tension here.


So what is your principled solution to resolving the tension?  Does  
equality trump everything?  If so, then don't you need to eliminate  
all accommodations for religion?


Your response to my concerns strikes me as a bit simplistic.  I don't  
see how they would work out.


Constitutionally I have no problem with accommodating CLS.  But I also  
have little problem with requiring them not to discriminate (isn't  
that equality?) just like other sanctioned groups.


It is not easy.  It is easy to make slogans, to twist the framing of  
the problem (like Rick Duncan has done, and as I have done and others  
too) to bias it one way or another, but it is a real problem with  
important, fundamental principles in competition -- as was the case in  
Rosenberger.  I would have gone the other way, but, unlike some  
decisions, I don't consider Rosenberger particularly harmful or  
problematic -- except insofar as the lack of somewhat more clear lines  
is always problematic.


Steve



On May 11, 2010, at 12:28 PM, Lisa A. Runquist wrote:



On 5/10/2010 8:21 PM, Steven Jamar wrote:
Religion and religious organizations are different from other  
organizations.  The constitution says we need to treat religion  
differently.  Unless we decide that speech and association and  
equal treatment principles trump the religion clauses, we need to  
give them effect somehow -- both the free exercise and  
establishment clauses.


And the constitution does not say that religious organizations are  
to be treated worse than all other groups.  The government cannot  
establish religion, but it also cannot prohibit the free exercise of  
religion.  Yet that, it seems to me, is exactly what the college is  
trying to do here.


What would be the result if the university made an exception for  
religious organizations -- then it is not treating the religious  
organization equally.
As long as all religious organizations are treated the same way,  
then there is no violation.  If, for example, it allowed CLS to meet  
but prohibited a Muslim group from meeting, then this would be not  
treating the religious organizations equally.


Lisa

--
Lisa A. Runquist
Runquist  Associates
Attorneys at Law
17554 Community Street
Northridge, CA 91325
(818)609-7761
(818)609-7794 (fax)
l...@runquist.com
http://www.runquist.com



___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed  
as private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that  
are posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can  
(rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.


--
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Associate Director, Institute of Intellectual Property and Social  
Justice http://iipsj.org

Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8567
http://iipsj.com/SDJ/


The test of a first-rate intelligence is the ability to hold two  
opposed ideas in mind at the same time and still retain the ability to  
function. One should, for example, be able to see that things are  
hopeless and yet be determined to make them otherwise.

-- F. Scott Fitzgerald.






___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-11 Thread Douglas Laycock
CLS does not claim that it should be treated differently from political 
groups.  Hastings' written rule treated religious groups differently, because 
it prohibited religious discrimination but did not prohibit political 
discrimination. The only groups that could not organize around a viewpoint were 
religious group.  It's all comers rule is egregiously unconstitutional as to 
political groups as well as to religious groups.

Quoting Sanford Levinson slevin...@law.utexas.edu:

 I can't figure out exactly why religious groups deserve to be treated 
 differently from, say, the young Democrats or Republicans or the 
 Sierra Club.  The Constitution says not that we have to treat 
 religion differently, but, rather, that we have to keep engaging in 
 an endless conversation about the interplay of religion and state.  
 Sometimes that might require different treatment, as in 
 accommodating people who are unwilling to work on Saturday.  Note, 
 though, that the Court, rightly or wrongly, refused to extend the 
 conscientious objector accommodation to a serious Catholic who was 
 opposed only to the Vietnam War (on just war grounds).  Nor, of 
 course, was the Court generous to Native Americans either in Lyng or 
 Smith, both of which, I have to say, seemed more appealing, on their 
 facts, than the CLS case. But none of these cases really involved the 
 freedom of association arguments that are really at the heart of 
 the argument.

 Am I correct, incidentally, that the principle being advocated for 
 would allow any religious society to restrict its leadership to males 
 if it had a religious principle that only men were fit for such 
 roles?  Judge (now Professor) McConnell seemed to emphasize the 
 belief-status distinction in his argument, but I'm not sure I 
 understand it when the justification for status discrimination is a 
 sincere (and quite traditional, often) religious belief.  The 
 argument that we, as a society have decided that race and 
 sex/gender are just different from other categories of 
 differentiation certainly can't hold, at least for the latter, since 
 I'm confident that McConnell (and, I suspect, almost everybody on 
 this list) would not allow a Title VII-like action against the 
 Catholic Church or Orthodox Judaism or even strip those religions of 
 their tax exemption because of their blatant sexism.

 Having read the oral argument, incidentally, I do wonder if there 
 will be an effort simply to dismiss it as improvidently granted, 
 given that most of the time seemed to have been spent on trying to 
 figure out what exactly were the facts and the relationship between 
 various stipulations and written policies of the Law School.

 sandy

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Lisa A. 
 Runquist
 Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 11:29 AM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example


 On 5/10/2010 8:21 PM, Steven Jamar wrote:
 Religion and religious organizations are different from other
 organizations.  The constitution says we need to treat religion
 differently.  Unless we decide that speech and association and equal
 treatment principles trump the religion clauses, we need to give them
 effect somehow -- both the free exercise and establishment clauses.

 And the constitution does not say that religious organizations are to be
 treated worse than all other groups.  The government cannot establish
 religion, but it also cannot prohibit the free exercise of religion.
 Yet that, it seems to me, is exactly what the college is trying to do here.

 What would be the result if the university made an exception for
 religious organizations -- then it is not treating the religious
 organization equally.
 As long as all religious organizations are treated the same way, then
 there is no violation.  If, for example, it allowed CLS to meet but
 prohibited a Muslim group from meeting, then this would be not treating
 the religious organizations equally.

 Lisa

 --
 Lisa A. Runquist
 Runquist  Associates
 Attorneys at Law
 17554 Community Street
 Northridge, CA 91325
 (818)609-7761
 (818)609-7794 (fax)
 l...@runquist.com
 http://www.runquist.com



 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are 
 posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can 
 (rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-11 Thread Sanford Levinson
Doug may very well be right, but I must say that plowing through the oral 
argument didn't highlight the difference between CLS and, say, the Young 
Democrats.  If Hastings is indeed selecting out religious groups for special 
all comers non-discrimination with regard to eligibility for leadership 
positions, then I agree it's a no brainer.

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 12:01 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

CLS does not claim that it should be treated differently from political groups. 
 Hastings' written rule treated religious groups differently, because it 
prohibited religious discrimination but did not prohibit political 
discrimination. The only groups that could not organize around a viewpoint were 
religious group.  It's all comers rule is egregiously unconstitutional as to 
political groups as well as to religious groups.

Quoting Sanford Levinson slevin...@law.utexas.edu:

 I can't figure out exactly why religious groups deserve to be treated
 differently from, say, the young Democrats or Republicans or the
 Sierra Club.  The Constitution says not that we have to treat
 religion differently, but, rather, that we have to keep engaging in
 an endless conversation about the interplay of religion and state.
 Sometimes that might require different treatment, as in
 accommodating people who are unwilling to work on Saturday.  Note,
 though, that the Court, rightly or wrongly, refused to extend the
 conscientious objector accommodation to a serious Catholic who was
 opposed only to the Vietnam War (on just war grounds).  Nor, of
 course, was the Court generous to Native Americans either in Lyng or
 Smith, both of which, I have to say, seemed more appealing, on their
 facts, than the CLS case. But none of these cases really involved the
 freedom of association arguments that are really at the heart of
 the argument.

 Am I correct, incidentally, that the principle being advocated for
 would allow any religious society to restrict its leadership to males
 if it had a religious principle that only men were fit for such
 roles?  Judge (now Professor) McConnell seemed to emphasize the
 belief-status distinction in his argument, but I'm not sure I
 understand it when the justification for status discrimination is a
 sincere (and quite traditional, often) religious belief.  The
 argument that we, as a society have decided that race and
 sex/gender are just different from other categories of
 differentiation certainly can't hold, at least for the latter, since
 I'm confident that McConnell (and, I suspect, almost everybody on
 this list) would not allow a Title VII-like action against the
 Catholic Church or Orthodox Judaism or even strip those religions of
 their tax exemption because of their blatant sexism.

 Having read the oral argument, incidentally, I do wonder if there
 will be an effort simply to dismiss it as improvidently granted,
 given that most of the time seemed to have been spent on trying to
 figure out what exactly were the facts and the relationship between
 various stipulations and written policies of the Law School.

 sandy

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Lisa A.
 Runquist
 Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 11:29 AM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example


 On 5/10/2010 8:21 PM, Steven Jamar wrote:
 Religion and religious organizations are different from other
 organizations.  The constitution says we need to treat religion
 differently.  Unless we decide that speech and association and equal
 treatment principles trump the religion clauses, we need to give them
 effect somehow -- both the free exercise and establishment clauses.

 And the constitution does not say that religious organizations are to be
 treated worse than all other groups.  The government cannot establish
 religion, but it also cannot prohibit the free exercise of religion.
 Yet that, it seems to me, is exactly what the college is trying to do here.

 What would be the result if the university made an exception for
 religious organizations -- then it is not treating the religious
 organization equally.
 As long as all religious organizations are treated the same way, then
 there is no violation.  If, for example, it allowed CLS to meet but
 prohibited a Muslim group from meeting, then this would be not treating
 the religious organizations equally.

 Lisa

 --
 Lisa A. Runquist
 Runquist  Associates
 Attorneys at Law
 17554 Community Street
 Northridge, CA 91325
 (818)609-7761
 (818)609-7794 (fax)
 l...@runquist.com
 http://www.runquist.com



 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-11 Thread Marc Stern
It is common for a dismissal as improvidently granted to occur soon
after oral argument.  I think too much time has passed to make such a
disposition likely.
Marc

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Sanford
Levinson
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 12:50 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

I can't figure out exactly why religious groups deserve to be treated
differently from, say, the young Democrats or Republicans or the Sierra
Club.  The Constitution says not that we have to treat religion
differently, but, rather, that we have to keep engaging in an endless
conversation about the interplay of religion and state.  Sometimes that
might require different treatment, as in accommodating people who are
unwilling to work on Saturday.  Note, though, that the Court, rightly or
wrongly, refused to extend the conscientious objector accommodation to
a serious Catholic who was opposed only to the Vietnam War (on just
war grounds).  Nor, of course, was the Court generous to Native
Americans either in Lyng or Smith, both of which, I have to say, seemed
more appealing, on their facts, than the CLS case. But none of these
cases really involved the freedom of association arguments that are
really at the heart of the argument.  

Am I correct, incidentally, that the principle being advocated for would
allow any religious society to restrict its leadership to males if it
had a religious principle that only men were fit for such roles?  Judge
(now Professor) McConnell seemed to emphasize the belief-status
distinction in his argument, but I'm not sure I understand it when the
justification for status discrimination is a sincere (and quite
traditional, often) religious belief.  The argument that we, as a
society have decided that race and sex/gender are just different from
other categories of differentiation certainly can't hold, at least for
the latter, since I'm confident that McConnell (and, I suspect, almost
everybody on this list) would not allow a Title VII-like action against
the Catholic Church or Orthodox Judaism or even strip those religions of
their tax exemption because of their blatant sexism.   

Having read the oral argument, incidentally, I do wonder if there will
be an effort simply to dismiss it as improvidently granted, given that
most of the time seemed to have been spent on trying to figure out what
exactly were the facts and the relationship between various stipulations
and written policies of the Law School.  

sandy

-Original Message-
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Lisa A.
Runquist
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 11:29 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: A real-life on-campus example


On 5/10/2010 8:21 PM, Steven Jamar wrote:
 Religion and religious organizations are different from other 
 organizations.  The constitution says we need to treat religion 
 differently.  Unless we decide that speech and association and equal 
 treatment principles trump the religion clauses, we need to give them 
 effect somehow -- both the free exercise and establishment clauses.

And the constitution does not say that religious organizations are to be
treated worse than all other groups.  The government cannot establish
religion, but it also cannot prohibit the free exercise of religion.  
Yet that, it seems to me, is exactly what the college is trying to do
here.

 What would be the result if the university made an exception for 
 religious organizations -- then it is not treating the religious 
 organization equally.
As long as all religious organizations are treated the same way, then
there is no violation.  If, for example, it allowed CLS to meet but
prohibited a Muslim group from meeting, then this would be not treating
the religious organizations equally.

Lisa

--
Lisa A. Runquist
Runquist  Associates
Attorneys at Law
17554 Community Street
Northridge, CA 91325
(818)609-7761
(818)609-7794 (fax)
l...@runquist.com
http://www.runquist.com



___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-11 Thread Scarberry, Mark
Hastings' initial policy prevented CLS from discriminating on
religious grounds but did not prevent political groups from
discriminating on political grounds. (As Michael McConnell's brief
pointed out, with quotes from, if I remember correctly, Larry Tribe,
Justice Brennan, and Justice O'Connor, the ability to choose those who
determine an expressive association's message is integral to the freedom
of expressive association and constitutive of the expressive
associational group; considering it to be discrimination in the way we
ordinarily use that term is a category error.) Probably because it
realized that such a policy was indefensible, Hastings tried to switch
to an all-comers policy that supposedly would apply to all groups. That
all comers policy is the one Doug is referencing as being egregiously
unconst as to both political and religious groups. The record seems to
support the view that Hastings continued to apply its original policy
against CLS, along with the all-comers policy, though one could argue
that the latter encompasses the former. The record also shows no
enforcement of the all comers policy against groups, including Hastings
Outlaw, that had provisions in their constitutions requiring officers to
support the group's mission.

 

Mark Scarberry

Pepperdine

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Sanford
Levinson
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 10:06 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

 

Doug may very well be right, but I must say that plowing through the
oral argument didn't highlight the difference between CLS and, say, the
Young Democrats.  If Hastings is indeed selecting out religious groups
for special all comers non-discrimination with regard to eligibility
for leadership positions, then I agree it's a no brainer.  

 

sandy

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 12:01 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

 

CLS does not claim that it should be treated differently from political
groups.  Hastings' written rule treated religious groups differently,
because it prohibited religious discrimination but did not prohibit
political discrimination. The only groups that could not organize around
a viewpoint were religious group.  It's all comers rule is egregiously
unconstitutional as to political groups as well as to religious groups.

Quoting Sanford Levinson slevin...@law.utexas.edu:

 I can't figure out exactly why religious groups deserve to be treated 
 differently from, say, the young Democrats or Republicans or the 
 Sierra Club.  The Constitution says not that we have to treat 
 religion differently, but, rather, that we have to keep engaging in 
 an endless conversation about the interplay of religion and state.  
 Sometimes that might require different treatment, as in 
 accommodating people who are unwilling to work on Saturday.  Note, 
 though, that the Court, rightly or wrongly, refused to extend the 
 conscientious objector accommodation to a serious Catholic who was 
 opposed only to the Vietnam War (on just war grounds).  Nor, of 
 course, was the Court generous to Native Americans either in Lyng or 
 Smith, both of which, I have to say, seemed more appealing, on their 
 facts, than the CLS case. But none of these cases really involved the 
 freedom of association arguments that are really at the heart of 
 the argument.

 Am I correct, incidentally, that the principle being advocated for 
 would allow any religious society to restrict its leadership to males 
 if it had a religious principle that only men were fit for such 
 roles?  Judge (now Professor) McConnell seemed to emphasize the 
 belief-status distinction in his argument, but I'm not sure I 
 understand it when the justification for status discrimination is a 
 sincere (and quite traditional, often) religious belief.  The 
 argument that we, as a society have decided that race and 
 sex/gender are just different from other categories of 
 differentiation certainly can't hold, at least for the latter, since 
 I'm confident that McConnell (and, I suspect, almost everybody on 
 this list) would not allow a Title VII-like action against the 
 Catholic Church or Orthodox Judaism or even strip those religions of 
 their tax exemption because of their blatant sexism.

 Having read the oral argument, incidentally, I do wonder if there 
 will be an effort simply to dismiss it as improvidently granted, 
 given that most of the time seemed to have been spent on trying to 
 figure out what exactly were the facts and the relationship between 
 various stipulations and written policies of the Law School.

 sandy

 -Original Message-
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Lisa A. 
 Runquist
 Sent

RE: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-11 Thread Marc Stern
What is the relevance of Gilmore v. City of Montgomery,417 US 556 which
held that cities need not,indeed could not, exclude racially segregated
schools from non-exclusive use of public parks so long as there was no
lingering state action. .The Court seems to have held held that to do so
would violate the associational  rights of segregation academies.Some of
the examples cited by the court of impermissible exclusions from public
spaces,trenching on freedom of association,we would call public fora of
various kinds.
Marc



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Scarberry, Mark
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 1:21 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example



Hastings' initial policy prevented CLS from discriminating on
religious grounds but did not prevent political groups from
discriminating on political grounds. (As Michael McConnell's brief
pointed out, with quotes from, if I remember correctly, Larry Tribe,
Justice Brennan, and Justice O'Connor, the ability to choose those who
determine an expressive association's message is integral to the freedom
of expressive association and constitutive of the expressive
associational group; considering it to be discrimination in the way we
ordinarily use that term is a category error.) Probably because it
realized that such a policy was indefensible, Hastings tried to switch
to an all-comers policy that supposedly would apply to all groups. That
all comers policy is the one Doug is referencing as being egregiously
unconst as to both political and religious groups. The record seems to
support the view that Hastings continued to apply its original policy
against CLS, along with the all-comers policy, though one could argue
that the latter encompasses the former. The record also shows no
enforcement of the all comers policy against groups, including Hastings
Outlaw, that had provisions in their constitutions requiring officers to
support the group's mission.

 

Mark Scarberry

Pepperdine

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Sanford
Levinson
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 10:06 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

 

Doug may very well be right, but I must say that plowing through the
oral argument didn't highlight the difference between CLS and, say, the
Young Democrats.  If Hastings is indeed selecting out religious groups
for special all comers non-discrimination with regard to eligibility
for leadership positions, then I agree it's a no brainer.  

 

sandy

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Tuesday, May 11, 2010 12:01 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: A real-life on-campus example

 

CLS does not claim that it should be treated differently from political
groups.  Hastings' written rule treated religious groups differently,
because it prohibited religious discrimination but did not prohibit
political discrimination. The only groups that could not organize around
a viewpoint were religious group.  It's all comers rule is egregiously
unconstitutional as to political groups as well as to religious groups.

Quoting Sanford Levinson slevin...@law.utexas.edu:

 I can't figure out exactly why religious groups deserve to be treated 
 differently from, say, the young Democrats or Republicans or the 
 Sierra Club.  The Constitution says not that we have to treat 
 religion differently, but, rather, that we have to keep engaging in 
 an endless conversation about the interplay of religion and state.  
 Sometimes that might require different treatment, as in 
 accommodating people who are unwilling to work on Saturday.  Note, 
 though, that the Court, rightly or wrongly, refused to extend the 
 conscientious objector accommodation to a serious Catholic who was 
 opposed only to the Vietnam War (on just war grounds).  Nor, of 
 course, was the Court generous to Native Americans either in Lyng or 
 Smith, both of which, I have to say, seemed more appealing, on their 
 facts, than the CLS case. But none of these cases really involved the 
 freedom of association arguments that are really at the heart of 
 the argument.

 Am I correct, incidentally, that the principle being advocated for 
 would allow any religious society to restrict its leadership to males 
 if it had a religious principle that only men were fit for such 
 roles?  Judge (now Professor) McConnell seemed to emphasize the 
 belief-status distinction in his argument, but I'm not sure I 
 understand it when the justification for status discrimination is a 
 sincere (and quite traditional, often) religious belief.  The 
 argument that we, as a society have decided that race and 
 sex/gender are just different from other categories of 
 differentiation certainly can't hold

Re: A real-life on-campus example

2010-05-10 Thread Steven Jamar
CLS is not being stopped from association and restricting membership, etc.
CLS can belief-test leaders.  That is not the issue.  The government is not
stopping CLS from meeting, from associating, from adverstising, from doing
anything at all except using government property when CLS fails to comply
with a neutral, secular law/rule of general applicability.

I disagree with the Rosenberger reasoning and result, but it would seem that
that equality principle -- treating CLS just like all the other
organizations (must comply with the neutral, generally applicable rule)
could have some traction here.

Religion and religious organizations are different from other
organizations.  The constitution says we need to treat religion
differently.  Unless we decide that speech and association and equal
treatment principles trump the religion clauses, we need to give them effect
somehow -- both the free exercise and establishment clauses.

Will there be difficult cases?  Surely.

What would be the result if the university made an exception for religious
organizations -- then it is not treating the religious organization
equally.  It is getting special treatment.  And that seems ok.  But what is
being sought here is not a policy based accommodation, but a
constitution-based one.

Steve

On Mon, May 10, 2010 at 10:52 PM, Eric Rassbach erassb...@becketfund.orgwrote:

 Chip -

 One real-life, on-campus example is cited at page 33 n.5 of Petitioner's
 brief -- a Mormon student was not allowed to lead Bible study at the
 Washburn University CLS chapter.  His reaction was to petition
 (successfully) to get the CLS chapter derecognized. It appears from PACER
 that CLS got re-recognized only after filing suit and settling the case.

 In a religiously diverse, politically polarized world (witness this list),
 only Polyanna believes that these situations will just work themselves out
 absent the shadow of the law. Maybe folks think that an outcome allowing CLS
 to belief-test leaders and voting members is immoral or otherwise wrong, but
 they shouldn't pretend the conflict doesn't actually exist.

 Eric


 --
Prof. Steven Jamar
Howard University School of Law
Associate Director, Institute of Intellectual Property and Social Justice
(IIPSJ) Inc.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.