11. Dopp: "Could deliver unreasonable outcomes…."

Unreasonable outcomes are less likely with IRV than with any other single-seat voting method in use today.

Top-two runoff? Approval Voting (used in a number of professional societies)? Borda Count, used in various forms in a few places for governmental elections?

Top-two runoff can produce much the same unreasonable outcomes as IRV, but there is a serious safety mechanism. In most places, write-in votes are allowed in the runoff, so if a truly bad result happens, the voters can fix it. Usually, though -- in every case I'm aware of -- the two candidates remaining include one good enough that the voters don't bother to work as hard as it would take for a write-in to win. With IRV, that flexibility does not exist.

Every single voting method ever proposed can deliver "unreasonable outcomes" in some scenarios, but real-world experience has shown IRV to be one of the best methods.

Because he says so? Is there any academic consensus on that? (FairVote knows that there is not, and certainly voting systems experts, generally, have a low opinion of IRV, and only support it, sometimes, in comparison to Plurality. For some reason, voting systems experts don't much think about Top-Two Runoff, they mostly focus on deterministic methods that always produce a result, always complete an election from a single ballot. Which is one very serious limitation, incompatible with majority rule, actually.

The overwhelming number of election method experts agree that IRV is fairer and more democratic than plurality voting even if some might prefer other theoretical voting methods.

Seriously spun. Sure, better than plurality voting, better than diving into a swimming pool with no water in it. Better than dictatorship. Better than lots of things. But ask those same experts about Top-Two Runoff, which is the real choice, the real alternative in most places. IRV is actually being implemented in places that had top-two runoff, not plurality. Is it better. What, I wonder, does FairVote think Robert's Rules of Order would say?

The American Political Science Association (the national association of political science professors) has incorporated IRV into their own constitution for electing their own national president. Robert’s Rules of Order recommends IRV over plurality voting.

FairVote knows the truth about this, and the statement has been very carefully worded to convey the desired impression without actually lying. The impression conveyed is false, the words used are true. Genuine, class-A political spin. Fortunately, I've been working on these issues for about nine months now, with the Wikipedia article, which was at one time full of FairVote spin, enforced by sock puppets and Rob Richie himself, edit warring using an anonymous unregistered account to keep all genuine criticism out of the article and maintain all his talking points, including the two above.

What's the problem? Go look at the APSA constitution and, sure enough, you will find a provision that if there are three or more candidates for the office of President-Elect, the "standard method of the alternative vote" is to be used. And the method is described, and it is STV, or what we call, loosely, IRV. But what does this *mean.* Richie wants us to think it means that political scientists prefer IRV. Sometimes the APSA factoid is even listed as a "recommendation" of IRV.

However, how does APSA *actually* elect its Presidents? Surely if we are going to look to the political scientists for guidance on election methods, we'd want to see what they actually use, and STV is in the Constitution only as a contingency.

The President, with the advice and consent of the Council, another elected body, appoints a Nominating Committee which names a single nominee. If there is no other nominee, this candidate is elected at the Annual Meeting. However, it is possible to nominate other candidates by petition. The last time there was a petition candidate was almost forty years ago. In order for them to use IRV, there would have to be a second petition candidate. The chances of that can be estimated at once in 1600 years.

Wait, what about the Council? Ah, yes, the Council. Plurality-at-large. There are as many candidates nominated for the Council as there are seats, but there are some petition candidates, often. Voters vote for as many seats as are open, and the candidates with the most votes win. So ... political scientists are actually using Plurality. Period. They are not actually using IRV, and they set it up so that the need for IRV would be extraordinarily rare. Should we do this.

Now, next factoid: to repeat it: "Robert’s Rules of Order recommends IRV over plurality voting."

Well, it doesn't exactly recommend it. It says that "preferential voting" gives a fairer result than plurality voting if it is considered impractical to use repeated balloting, which is what they *actually* recommend, indeed *require* unless bylaws specifically permit otherwise.

It then states that "there are many forms of preferential voting." We've named some above. Borda Count, for example, or what Brams calls Fallback Voting, more widely known as Bucklin Voting. But Robert's Rules then describes the STV method "by way of illustration." And then it proceeds to tell us the problems of this specific described method: it "deprives" voters of the opportunity to base later choices on the results of earlier rounds (which is what is allowed with Top-Two Runoff) and it can fail to find a "compromise winner," and it blames this on candidate elimination.

This latter failure is the "Center Squeeze" phenomenon of IRV: a candidate might be preferred, collectively, over every other candidate, but merely because the candidate does not get enough first preference votes, it is eliminated before all the votes that would show this are counted. Those votes, in fact, are never counted. We'll come back to that.

Attempting to make a virtue out of a vice, FairVote has invented the Core Support Criterion which is a reference to this. Suppose that there are three candidates in an election, and their partisans are about equal in number. Add a fourth candidate who is the first choice of nobody, but who is everyone's second choice. According to the Core Support Criterion, a candidate should not win who is not the first choice of at least one voter, so this obvious compromise candidate, preferred by every voter by a large margin over whoever would win the IRV election, can't win. Preferred by, in the example given, a vote of three to one.

Let's make a more reasonable example, the Core Support Criterion is based on something utterly impossible, I'd say. Suppose there are three candidates running a close race. Any one of them could have the lowest first round total. With IRV, that one would be eliminated. Now, suppose that one of the three candidates is really very broadly trusted, and is the second choice of nearly everyone who does not have him or her as a first choice. I can think of candidates for whom that might be true. So we have

34: A>B>C
33+:C>B>A
33-:B>A>C

There is nothing particularly unreasonable about this profile. B is eliminated in the first round. But B would beat, in a pairwise election, A, the IRV winner, by a vote of 66:34, a landslide. And with just a few more votes, B would win the IRV election as well, *by the same margin*, because one of the other candidates would be eliminated and those votes for B would be revealed. So a very few votes in the first round flips the result from B, a landlide winner, to one of the others. Which one depends on where the votes taken from B went.

This problem is serious enough that Robert's Rules mentions it. FairVote will tell you it is very rare.

Of course it is rare. This problem does not happen in a two-party system! And IRV, remember, helps maintain a two-party system.

Is this problem inevitable? Definitely not! Consider Fallback Voting (a.k.a. Bucklin). The first round does not find a majority, so the second round votes are added in, the election becomes an Approval election. Wonder of wonders, B is elected with a vote of 100%! That is because, when the approval threshold is lowered to include second rank choices, every voter has placed B in second rank or higher.

Any Condorcet method would also, of course, elect B, because B is the pairwise winner. Approval would probably do the same.

Now, FairVote will doubtless point out that Bucklin doesn't satisfy Later-No-Harm. Later-No-Harm, however, is incompatible with the basic principles of majority rule, which requires compromise if decisions are to be made. Robert's Rules is utterly unconcerned with Later-No-Harm. But here is how it would affect the election:

Some voters would think that if they vote for B in second place, this might help B defeat their favorite. So they wouldn't vote for B, they would "truncate." However, real voters don't mostly think like that, even though political activists wish they would. If a voter has a very strong preference for the favorite over all others, then they won't rank others, quite properly. But if they have a weak preference, they will; in the example given, B is widely known and respected. B might not get a two-thirds majority, but it only takes a relatively small number of the other voters ranking B second to bring B the victory.

Continued with:
Dopp: 12.“Not all ballots are treated equally…”
----
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info

Reply via email to