Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread hamilton02
Religious groups and their supporters have been trying to water down 
substantial
for years.   The Alabama rfra doesn't include substantial and neither did the 
failed North Dakota or Colorado
initiatives.  One of the reasons the latter failed is overreaching, though it 
is also attributable to the fact
that the Rutherford Institute and others lobbying for rfras have met their 
match in a number of opposing groups.


The court in the ACA case did little more than apply existing law on the 
interpretation of substantial.  Those arguing
the case was wrongly decided on this issue are arguing for a new standard.  
That is contrary to RFRA's (and RLUIPA's) legislative history, which indicate
substantial burden was to be interpreted according to existing precedents (as 
of 1993 and 2000).  In other words, Lyng, Bowen, and Lee are the
governing interpretations for RFRA.  Subjective views of burden are not part of 
the doctrine.  It would take the Supreme Court to overturn these
decisions to grant a win to the religiously affiliated institutions.


Marci


 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Steven Jamar stevenja...@gmail.com
Cc: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Sun, Sep 30, 2012 10:16 pm
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate



On Sep 30, 2012, at 9:49 PM, Douglas Laycock wrote:

 Steve's second point -- the difference between historic exclusion of 
 Catholics 
as such and contemporary exclusion of those who adhere too strictly to certain 
Catholic teachings -- is just Smith's holding about generally applicable laws. 
The whole point of RFRA was to create statutory protection not restricted to 
that holding.

Agreed.  But that doesn't make the history of status-based exclusion 
controlling 
for what is and is not a substantial burden, or even particularly relevant.  
They are different types of exclusion.  There are reasons to protect 
pure-belief-based actions even in the commercial secular marketplace, but that 
history is not one of them.


 The ACA and the contraceptive mandate also have exceptions that cover rens of 
millions of people, so it is far from clear that this is a neutral and 
generally 
applicable law. The no-burden holding also saves the court from having to 
address that issue.

I am not overly fond of a number of substantial burden results.  But the test 
is 
substantial burden, not merely burden, and the term substantial should mean 
something.  I think it should mean something quite substantial and be something 
that really effectively prohibits the exercise of religion or really makes it 
so 
hard to practice one's beliefs that one has a hard time practicing them.  I 
understand others think it should be subjective and controlled by the adherent 
and that we should take his or her word for the substantiality of the effect.

You may believe that OSHA is the work of the devil.  But that doesn't relieve 
you from compliance if you choose to engage in the sort of commerce that OSHA 
regulates.  No one is making you do that sort of work.  You have alternatives.  

Do we really want to say the subjective burden as felt by the adherent gets 
past 
the first hurdle and then have courts start expanding compelling state 
interest to uphold the myriad regulations on commercial establishments?  That 
seems to me to be a greater mischief.

Perhaps RFRA should be revisited to address the back-end standard to make the 
balancing more like EP intermediate scrutiny.  Or to consider the 
substantiality 
of the burden, the importance of the state's interest, the effect on third 
parties (e.g. employees in an employer setting), and the effect of ruling one 
way or the other on all three -- what options are available for the religious 
adherent employer; what costs are there to society and the government in 
interests of equality, equity, administration of the laws; what options are 
there to the employee.  But that opens quite another can of worms and gives 
huge 
discretionary power to the courts.

Is that really what we want here?

Or do we really want the unit veto for any and all government regulations short 
of human sacrifice and child abuse as compelling interests?

Are we going to revisit the social security cases and now say they don't need 
to 
pay the tax?

I think the judge got it right here and that the alternatives are not 
necessarily good for free exercise in the bigger picture.

Steve

 
 On Sun, 30 Sep 2012 21:32:10 -0400
 Steven Jamar stevenja...@gmail.com wrote:
 I was quite clearly talking about religious employers in secular commerce.   
The religious institutions engaging in secular/religious endeavors like 
religious schools and hospitals are different from someone making and selling 
widgets.
 
 There is also quite a difference 

RE: Laws barring political discrimination by private employers

2012-10-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
Good to know.

 

There are also some statutes like Colorado’s, which (last time I looked) 
prohibits discrimination on the basis of “any lawful off-the-job activity.” I’m 
told that these were passed by the tobacco lobby, but I have never verified 
that. I forgot about those last night, and I don’t know if Eugene included them 
in his count of statutes restricting political discrimination. 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Sunday, September 30, 2012 10:37 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Laws barring political discrimination by private employers

 

Doug Laycock writes:

 

 No law prohibits political discrimination by private employers, except in DC

 and maybe a few other places I don't know about. But I think not very many,.

 

It turns out that bans on some forms of political 
discrimination by private employers are present in states that account for 
about half the population, though some such bans are quite narrow (e.g., 
covering only discrimination based on signing initiative petitions or making 
political contributions) and others are considerably broader, covering a wide 
range of political activity or even speech more broadly.  I quote and 
categorize these laws in Private Employees' Speech and Political Activity: 
Statutory Protection Against Employer Retaliation, 16 Texas Review of Law  
Politics 295 (2012), http://www.trolp.org/main_pgs/issues/v16n2/Volokh.pdf.  
The jurisdictions include California (broad), New York (medium), Illinois 
(narrow), and many more.

 

Eugene

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Laws barring political discrimination by private employers

2012-10-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I did indeed; the Colorado statute has been read – quite 
reasonably, given its text – to apply to speech as well as other off-the-job 
activity.  Colorado also has another, much older, statute that protects 
employees’ political activity.  (Many states besides the one I listed also bar 
discrimination based on how a person has voted, but I didn’t focus on those 
because people nowadays rarely know how their employees voted.)

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 6:59 AM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: Laws barring political discrimination by private employers

Good to know.

There are also some statutes like Colorado’s, which (last time I looked) 
prohibits discrimination on the basis of “any lawful off-the-job activity.” I’m 
told that these were passed by the tobacco lobby, but I have never verified 
that. I forgot about those last night, and I don’t know if Eugene included them 
in his count of statutes restricting political discrimination.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Volokh, Eugene
Sent: Sunday, September 30, 2012 10:37 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Laws barring political discrimination by private employers


Doug Laycock writes:



 No law prohibits political discrimination by private employers, except in DC

 and maybe a few other places I don't know about. But I think not very many,.



It turns out that bans on some forms of political 
discrimination by private employers are present in states that account for 
about half the population, though some such bans are quite narrow (e.g., 
covering only discrimination based on signing initiative petitions or making 
political contributions) and others are considerably broader, covering a wide 
range of political activity or even speech more broadly.  I quote and 
categorize these laws in Private Employees' Speech and Political Activity: 
Statutory Protection Against Employer Retaliation, 16 Texas Review of Law  
Politics 295 (2012), http://www.trolp.org/main_pgs/issues/v16n2/Volokh.pdf.  
The jurisdictions include California (broad), New York (medium), Illinois 
(narrow), and many more.



Eugene
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

FW: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
Lyng and Bowen involved no regulation of religious behavior. Lee expressly 
found a burden on free exercise (455 U.S. at 257); the case was decided on 
compelling interest grounds. None of these cases have any relevance to the 
burden issue in the ACA cases.

 

And by the way, I think that all three were rightly decided.

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 8:34 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Religious groups and their supporters have been trying to water down 
substantial 

for years.   The Alabama rfra doesn't include substantial and neither did the 
failed North Dakota or Colorado

initiatives.  One of the reasons the latter failed is overreaching, though it 
is also attributable to the fact

that the Rutherford Institute and others lobbying for rfras have met their 
match in a number of opposing groups.

 

The court in the ACA case did little more than apply existing law on the 
interpretation of substantial.  Those arguing

the case was wrongly decided on this issue are arguing for a new standard.  
That is contrary to RFRA's (and RLUIPA's) legislative history, which indicate

substantial burden was to be interpreted according to existing precedents (as 
of 1993 and 2000).  In other words, Lyng, Bowen, and Lee are the

governing interpretations for RFRA.  Subjective views of burden are not part of 
the doctrine.  It would take the Supreme Court to overturn these

decisions to grant a win to the religiously affiliated institutions.

 

Marci

 

 

Marci A. Hamilton

Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law

Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law

Yeshiva University

55 Fifth Avenue

New York, NY 10003

(212) 790-0215

hamilto...@aol.com

 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
Oops. Writing too fast.

 

What I meant to say is that neither Lyng, nor Bowen, nor Lee supports a 
no-burden holding in the ACA cases.  Lyng and Bowen do indeed appear 
irrelevant. But Lee is not irrelevant; it supports a holding of substantial 
burden. The Court accepted the Amish claim that payment of social security 
taxes was forbidden by their faith, and concluded that requiring this payment 
“interferes with their free exercise rights.” But “not all burdens are 
unconstitutional. That state may justify a limitation on religious liberty . . 
.” And it went on to find a compelling interest in collecting taxes, including 
social security taxes.

 

So in Lee, the Court said that payment of funds to the government, for a stated 
purpose that is religiously objectionable, is a constitutionally cognizable 
burden on free exercise. 

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 10:55 AM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: FW: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Lyng and Bowen involved no regulation of religious behavior. Lee expressly 
found a burden on free exercise (455 U.S. at 257); the case was decided on 
compelling interest grounds. None of these cases have any relevance to the 
burden issue in the ACA cases.

 

And by the way, I think that all three were rightly decided.

 

Douglas Laycock

Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

University of Virginia Law School

580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA  22903

 434-243-8546

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 8:34 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Religious groups and their supporters have been trying to water down 
substantial 

for years.   The Alabama rfra doesn't include substantial and neither did the 
failed North Dakota or Colorado

initiatives.  One of the reasons the latter failed is overreaching, though it 
is also attributable to the fact

that the Rutherford Institute and others lobbying for rfras have met their 
match in a number of opposing groups.

 

The court in the ACA case did little more than apply existing law on the 
interpretation of substantial.  Those arguing

the case was wrongly decided on this issue are arguing for a new standard.  
That is contrary to RFRA's (and RLUIPA's) legislative history, which indicate

substantial burden was to be interpreted according to existing precedents (as 
of 1993 and 2000).  In other words, Lyng, Bowen, and Lee are the

governing interpretations for RFRA.  Subjective views of burden are not part of 
the doctrine.  It would take the Supreme Court to overturn these

decisions to grant a win to the religiously affiliated institutions.

 

Marci

 

 

Marci A. Hamilton

Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law

Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law

Yeshiva University

55 Fifth Avenue

New York, NY 10003

(212) 790-0215

hamilto...@aol.com

 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Rick Garnett
Dear colleagues,

Rob Vischer (St. Thomas – MN) has a reaction – one that identifies well the 
decision’s many flaws -- to the decision we’re discussing, at the “Mirror of 
Justice” blog:  
http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2012/10/forcing-a-church-to-pay-for-its-employees-abortions-would-not-create-a-substantial-burden-on-religio.html

As Prof. Vischer reads the decision, its reasoning – i.e., no “substantial 
burden” -- would apply to a RFRA challenge brought by a Catholic diocese to an 
exemption-less requirement that the diocese provide insurance coverage for 
elective abortions.  Do those who have been welcoming this decision agree that 
RFRA would not / should not protect the diocese in such a case?

Best, R

Richard W. Garnett
Professor of Law and Associate Dean
Notre Dame Law School
P.O. Box 780
Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780

574-631-6981 (w)
574-276-2252 (cell)

SSRN pagehttp://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=342235

Blogs:

Prawfsblawghttp://prawfsblawg.blogs.com/
Mirror of Justicehttp://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 10:55 AM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: FW: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Lyng and Bowen involved no regulation of religious behavior. Lee expressly 
found a burden on free exercise (455 U.S. at 257); the case was decided on 
compelling interest grounds. None of these cases have any relevance to the 
burden issue in the ACA cases.

And by the way, I think that all three were rightly decided.

Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of 
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 8:34 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Religious groups and their supporters have been trying to water down 
substantial
for years.   The Alabama rfra doesn't include substantial and neither did the 
failed North Dakota or Colorado
initiatives.  One of the reasons the latter failed is overreaching, though it 
is also attributable to the fact
that the Rutherford Institute and others lobbying for rfras have met their 
match in a number of opposing groups.

The court in the ACA case did little more than apply existing law on the 
interpretation of substantial.  Those arguing
the case was wrongly decided on this issue are arguing for a new standard.  
That is contrary to RFRA's (and RLUIPA's) legislative history, which indicate
substantial burden was to be interpreted according to existing precedents (as 
of 1993 and 2000).  In other words, Lyng, Bowen, and Lee are the
governing interpretations for RFRA.  Subjective views of burden are not part of 
the doctrine.  It would take the Supreme Court to overturn these
decisions to grant a win to the religiously affiliated institutions.

Marci


Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Marty Lederman
Rob's thoughts are well worth reading -- he puts his finger on a bunch of
questions that are sure to be central to these cases going forward.

One caveat on the equivalence point raised by Rob and Rick:

To the extent the court is rejecting a proximate cooperation with evil
theory of substantial burden here, then yes, that same theory would
presumably be subject to the same objections if the case involved a diocese
and elective abortion coverage.  But the diocese would have a much stronger
substantial burden argument on a different theory -- one of the
institutional autonomy theories that Rick referred to earlier.  In
particular, assuming the diocese exercises its title VII exemption, and
prefers coreligionists in employment, then I'd assume one of its principal
functions -- unlike that of the ceramics-processing O'Brien Industrial
Company -- is to create and nurture a particular kind of religious
community, one in which its employees are expected to advance its Catholic
mission, and to adhere to Catholic tenets in their own conduct.  The HHS
rule would arguably have a significant impact on the ability of the diocese
to so shape its community and to ensure that its employees act in
accordance with Catholic precepts.  In that respect, the diocese is very
differently situated for RFRA purposes from the O'Brien Industrial Company,
which hires many non-Catholics and that does not endeavor to require its
employees to conform their conduct to Catholic precepts.

On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 11:57 AM, Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:

 Dear colleagues,

 ** **

 Rob Vischer (St. Thomas – MN) has a reaction – one that identifies well
 the decision’s many flaws -- to the decision we’re discussing, at the
 “Mirror of Justice” blog:
 http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2012/10/forcing-a-church-to-pay-for-its-employees-abortions-would-not-create-a-substantial-burden-on-religio.html
 

 ** **

 As Prof. Vischer reads the decision, its reasoning – i.e., no “substantial
 burden” -- would apply to a RFRA challenge brought by a Catholic diocese to
 an exemption-less requirement that the diocese provide insurance coverage
 for elective abortions.  Do those who have been welcoming this decision
 agree that RFRA would not / should not protect the diocese in such a case?
   

 ** **

 Best, R

 ** **

 Richard W. Garnett

 Professor of Law and Associate Dean

 Notre Dame Law School

 P.O. Box 780

 Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780

 ** **

 574-631-6981 (w)

 574-276-2252 (cell)

 ** **

 SSRN page http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=342235
 

 ** **

 Blogs:

 ** **

 Prawfsblawg http://prawfsblawg.blogs.com/

 Mirror of Justice http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/ 

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Douglas Laycock

 *Sent:* Monday, October 01, 2012 10:55 AM
 *To:* 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 *Subject:* FW: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 Lyng and Bowen involved no regulation of religious behavior. Lee expressly
 found a burden on free exercise (455 U.S. at 257); the case was decided on
 compelling interest grounds. None of these cases have any relevance to the
 burden issue in the ACA cases.

 ** **

 And by the way, I think that all three were rightly decided.

 ** **

 Douglas Laycock

 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law

 University of Virginia Law School

 580 Massie Road

 Charlottesville, VA  22903

  434-243-8546

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [
 mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edureligionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 *On Behalf Of *hamilto...@aol.com
 *Sent:* Monday, October 01, 2012 8:34 AM
 *To:* religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 Religious groups and their supporters have been trying to water down
 substantial 

 for years.   The Alabama rfra doesn't include substantial and neither
 did the failed North Dakota or Colorado

 initiatives.  One of the reasons the latter failed is overreaching, though
 it is also attributable to the fact

 that the Rutherford Institute and others lobbying for rfras have met their
 match in a number of opposing groups.

 ** **

 The court in the ACA case did little more than apply existing law on the
 interpretation of substantial.  Those arguing

 the case was wrongly decided on this issue are arguing for a new standard.
  That is contrary to RFRA's (and RLUIPA's) legislative history, which
 indicate

 substantial burden was to be interpreted according to existing
 precedents (as of 1993 and 2000).  In other words, Lyng, Bowen, and Lee
 are the

 governing interpretations for RFRA.  Subjective views of burden are 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Marty Lederman
Rick, Alan:  Allow me to ask the flip-side question of the one Alan
raises:  For those of us -- myself included, and you, and most of the
members of this list -- who have long argued that the state is
*not*responsible for the genuinely free and independent choices of
individuals
to use state $$ at a school of their choice, and that the state can surely
ameliorate any risk of misperceived endorsement by simply issuing a clear
disclaimer of neutrality and nonendorsement (see Pinette), is it really
fair to attribute to the employer here the employee's decision to use
contraception when (i) the coverage in the insurance plan is compelled by
law; (ii) the plan can be used for literally hundreds of different types of
medical goods and services, of which contraception is but one; (iii) the
decisions whether or not to use the plan for contraception are the result
of genuinely free and independent private choice and could not reasonably
be attributed to the employer; and (iv) the employer is free to issue as
many disclaimers as it wishes, explaining in no uncertain terms that it
thinks contraception is sinful, that it deplores the law in question, that
it would strongly urge its employees not to use contraception, etc.?

If we're going to argue -- as many of us have -- that the state's
involvement in the student's choice of a religious school is far too
attenuated to implicate in any strong manner the conscience rights of the
taxpayer whose funds eventually make their way, pursuant to many
intervening decisions, to the religious school's coffers, why should we
think there is a substantial burden on the employer's obligations of
conscience in this case?


On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 2:11 PM, Rick Garnett rgarn...@nd.edu wrote:

 Dear Marty,

 ** **

 I agree with you that a religious institution (which, I think, should
 include most of the institution-plaintiffs challenging the
 preventive-services mandate -- Catholic Charities, EWTN, the University of
 Notre Dame, etc.) is better positioned to frame the “substantial burden” in
 terms of its institutional “mission”, though I also think that the better
 way to handle the objection of, say, the owner of a commercial business is
 by asking about feasibility (tailoring, alternatives, etc.) and not by
 asserting (as the court here did) that there is no burden because employees
 often do things with their salaries to which employers object on moral
 grounds, etc.  (I do agree that, generally speaking, there isn’t a strong
 “substantial burden on conscience” objection to expenditures by the
 government from funds raised through taxes, but also think that the problem
 presented by the mandate, even for commercial employers, is different.)***
 *

 ** **

 Also, I’d like to hear more from those who support the court’s reasoning
 in response to Alan Brownstein’s as-per-usual thoughtful e-mail, in which
 he expressed concerns about the “no burden here” assertion, given what
 would seem to be the tension between that assertion and claims that, say,
 allowing school-voucher recipients to send their kids to Catholic schools
 burdens the conscience of one who objects to such funding.  If this
 decision were right, then wouldn’t we have a(nother) reason to overrule
 Flast?

 ** **

 Best,

 ** **

 Rick

 ** **

 Richard W. Garnett

 Professor of Law and Associate Dean

 Notre Dame Law School

 P.O. Box 780

 Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780

 ** **

 574-631-6981 (w)

 574-276-2252 (cell)

 ** **

 SSRN page http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=342235
 

 ** **

 Blogs:

 ** **

 Prawfsblawg http://prawfsblawg.blogs.com/

 Mirror of Justice http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/ 

 ** **

 *From:* religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:
 religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] *On Behalf Of *Marty Lederman
 *Sent:* Monday, October 01, 2012 1:48 PM

 *To:* Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 *Subject:* Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 ** **

 Rob's thoughts are well worth reading -- he puts his finger on a bunch of
 questions that are sure to be central to these cases going forward.

 One caveat on the equivalence point raised by Rob and Rick:

 To the extent the court is rejecting a proximate cooperation with evil
 theory of substantial burden here, then yes, that same theory would
 presumably be subject to the same objections if the case involved a diocese
 and elective abortion coverage.  But the diocese would have a much stronger
 substantial burden argument on a different theory -- one of the
 institutional autonomy theories that Rick referred to earlier.  In
 particular, assuming the diocese exercises its title VII exemption, and
 prefers coreligionists in employment, then I'd assume one of its principal
 functions -- unlike that of the ceramics-processing O'Brien Industrial
 Company -- is to create and nurture a particular kind of 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Christopher Lund
Imagine an observant Jew wants a kosher meal in prison.  The prison
doesn't serve kosher food.  Our plaintiff says, This burdens my
religion.  The prison responds, No, it doesn't.  You're not responsible
for the food we choose to serve in prison.  That's a genuinely free and
independent choice that we made.  It has nothing to do with you.

 

So why is there a substantial burden there?  I think it's simple: The
state is requiring the religious observer to do something his religion
forbids.  Maybe Judaism has overly broad notions of responsibility.  But
those notions are what they are, I think.  The state can't say, Your
theological notions of 'responsibility' are absurd, any more than it can
say, Your theological notions about the food God requires you to eat are
absurd.

 

Best,

Chris

 

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 2:52 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

 

Rick, Alan:  Allow me to ask the flip-side question of the one Alan
raises:  For those of us -- myself included, and you, and most of the
members of this list -- who have long argued that the state is not
responsible for the genuinely free and independent choices of individuals
to use state $$ at a school of their choice, and that the state can surely
ameliorate any risk of misperceived endorsement by simply issuing a clear
disclaimer of neutrality and nonendorsement (see Pinette), is it really
fair to attribute to the employer here the employee's decision to use
contraception when (i) the coverage in the insurance plan is compelled by
law; (ii) the plan can be used for literally hundreds of different types
of medical goods and services, of which contraception is but one; (iii)
the decisions whether or not to use the plan for contraception are the
result of genuinely free and independent private choice and could not
reasonably be attributed to the employer; and (iv) the employer is free to
issue as many disclaimers as it wishes, explaining in no uncertain terms
that it thinks contraception is sinful, that it deplores the law in
question, that it would strongly urge its employees not to use
contraception, etc.?  

If we're going to argue -- as many of us have -- that the state's
involvement in the student's choice of a religious school is far too
attenuated to implicate in any strong manner the conscience rights of
the taxpayer whose funds eventually make their way, pursuant to many
intervening decisions, to the religious school's coffers, why should we
think there is a substantial burden on the employer's obligations of
conscience in this case?

 

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Responsibility for actions that you assist

2012-10-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Let me add that American law has very different views of when 
people are responsible for the acts of others, or when they can demand that 
they not assist in the acts of others.  For instance,

1.  Zelman sets forth one rule when it comes to taxpayers' 
right to object to the use of their money under the Establishment Clause.

2.  Abood and Keller set forth a different rule when it comes 
to fee payers' right to object to the use of their fees (as opposed to general 
taxes) under the Free Speech Clause.

3.  Criminal law in most jurisdictions holds people responsible 
for aiding and abetting only when they have the purpose of aiding conduct.

4.  Criminal law in some jurisdictions, or as to some crimes, 
holds people responsible for aiding and abetting when they have the knowledge 
that they are aiding the conduct.

5.  In some jurisdictions, e.g., in New York, the standard for 
responsibility under special-purpose statutes is close to recklessness (e.g., 
believing it probable under the New York statute).

6.  Special purpose criminal laws (as opposed to general aiding 
and abetting law) sometimes have special rules for holding people responsible 
for doing things that assist certain kinds of misconduct based; consider, for 
instance, the federal ban on providing material assistance to designated 
terrorist organizations, or the laws in some states that criminalize recklessly 
facilitate escape from criminal custody.

7.  Tort law may in some situations hold people liable for 
aiding and abetting others' misconduct so long as the person was negligent 
about the possibility that the other person would use the person's help for bad 
purposes.  (Consider negligent entrustment claims, for instance, whether as to 
cars, guns, or what have you.)

I tend to agree with Chris and the others who take the view 
that the RFRA substantial burden question ought not be influenced by this, but 
rather by whether the claimant sincerely believes that he is asked to do 
something that he sees as sinful.  But the fact that our own legal system has 
such a complex view of when assistance is enough to make the assister 
responsible should further counsel in favor of focusing on the claimant's 
beliefs about responsibility, rather than trying to impose some rule of its own 
about responsibility.

None of this, of course, deals with whether the law could still 
be applied to objectors because (1) such an application passes strict scrutiny, 
or (2) the legislature carves out the relevant statute from RFRA.

Eugene

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Christopher Lund
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 12:37 PM
To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

I don't mean to speak for Alan or Rick.  I guess a first response to Marty is 
that Zelman only states a rule about the Establishment Clause.  It doesn't 
create some universal principle that we are not responsible for the choices of 
others.  It seems to me that the latter would go too far; tort, for example, 
sometimes imposes liability on people for acts of others that they enable even 
if they don't choose.

But there are two better responses:


(1)The Catholic Church might simply have a different view of 
responsibility (i.e., when we should think ourselves 'responsible' for the 
acts of others) than the Court in Zelman.  As Marty noted earlier, the church 
indeed has theological doctrines about responsibility which long predated 
Zelman.  Why would the Catholic Church be bound in its theological views by the 
Court's ideas of responsibility in Zelman?  Why would that be the natural limit 
of our toleration?



(2) Maybe the Catholic Church feels a need not only to not endorse 
abortion, but to affirmatively discourage it-whenever the Church is involved, 
the church has a duty to single abortion out for disfavored treatment.  If 
that's the church's position, why isn't that a substantial burden?

Best,
Chris

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 2:52 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Rick, Alan:  Allow me to ask the flip-side question of the one Alan raises:  
For those of us -- myself included, and you, and most of the members of this 
list -- who have long argued that the state is not responsible for the 
genuinely free and independent choices of individuals to use state $$ at a 
school of their choice, and that the state can surely ameliorate any risk of 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread hamilton02
Chris--  I take it you are arguing that for every religious prisoner with a 
dietary restriction, all of them can prove substantial burden,
but the state may or may not win under RLUIPA based on the state's evidence of 
compelling interest?   


Is it a substantial burden where the believer can obtain 50% of the foods 
he/she seeks?  I'm broadening this from the kosher
food context, obviously.


Marci


 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Mon, Oct 1, 2012 3:39 pm
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA  
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



Imagine an observant Jew wants a kosher meal in prison.  The prison doesn’t 
serve kosher food.  Our plaintiff says, “This burdens my religion.”  The prison 
responds, “No, it doesn’t.  You’re not responsible for the food we choose to 
serve in prison.  That’s a genuinely free and independent choice that we made.  
It has nothing to do with you.”
 
So why is there a “substantial burden” there?  I think it’s simple: The state 
is requiring the religious observer to do something his religion forbids.  
Maybe Judaism has overly broad notions of “responsibility.”  But those notions 
are what they are, I think.  The state can’t say, “Your theological notions of 
‘responsibility’ are absurd,” any more than it can say, “Your theological 
notions about the food God requires you to eat are absurd.”
 
Best,
Chris
 
From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 2:52 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
 
Rick, Alan:  Allow me to ask the flip-side question of the one Alan raises:  
For those of us -- myself included, and you, and most of the members of this 
list -- who have long argued that the state is not responsible for the 
genuinely free and independent choices of individuals to use state $$ at a 
school of their choice, and that the state can surely ameliorate any risk of 
misperceived endorsement by simply issuing a clear disclaimer of neutrality and 
nonendorsement (see Pinette), is it really fair to attribute to the employer 
here the employee's decision to use contraception when (i) the coverage in the 
insurance plan is compelled by law; (ii) the plan can be used for literally 
hundreds of different types of medical goods and services, of which 
contraception is but one; (iii) the decisions whether or not to use the plan 
for contraception are the result of genuinely free and independent private 
choice and could not reasonably be attributed to the employer; and (iv) the 
employer is free to issue as many disclaimers as it wishes, explaining in no 
uncertain terms that it thinks contraception is sinful, that it deplores the 
law in question, that it would strongly urge its employees not to use 
contraception, etc.?  

If we're going to argue -- as many of us have -- that the state's involvement 
in the student's choice of a religious school is far too attenuated to 
implicate in any strong manner the conscience rights of the taxpayer whose 
funds eventually make their way, pursuant to many intervening decisions, to the 
religious school's coffers, why should we think there is a substantial burden 
on the employer's obligations of conscience in this case?
 

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

 
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Sanford Levinson
Must the prison supply kosher meat (and build a kosher kitchen) or is it enough 
that it supplies nutritious vegetarian food, even though other prisoners get 
meat?

sandy

From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 4:28 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Chris--  I take it you are arguing that for every religious prisoner with a 
dietary restriction, all of them can prove substantial burden,
but the state may or may not win under RLUIPA based on the state's evidence of 
compelling interest?

Is it a substantial burden where the believer can obtain 50% of the foods 
he/she seeks?  I'm broadening this from the kosher
food context, obviously.

Marci

Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.commailto:hamilto...@aol.com

-Original Message-
From: Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edumailto:l...@wayne.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics 
religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Mon, Oct 1, 2012 3:39 pm
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
Imagine an observant Jew wants a kosher meal in prison.  The prison doesn’t 
serve kosher food.  Our plaintiff says, “This burdens my religion.”  The prison 
responds, “No, it doesn’t.  You’re not responsible for the food we choose to 
serve in prison.  That’s a genuinely free and independent choice that we made.  
It has nothing to do with you.”

So why is there a “substantial burden” there?  I think it’s simple: The state 
is requiring the religious observer to do something his religion forbids.  
Maybe Judaism has overly broad notions of “responsibility.”  But those notions 
are what they are, I think.  The state can’t say, “Your theological notions of 
‘responsibility’ are absurd,” any more than it can say, “Your theological 
notions about the food God requires you to eat are absurd.”

Best,
Chris

From: 
religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu?]
 On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 2:52 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Rick, Alan:  Allow me to ask the flip-side question of the one Alan raises:  
For those of us -- myself included, and you, and most of the members of this 
list -- who have long argued that the state is not responsible for the 
genuinely free and independent choices of individuals to use state $$ at a 
school of their choice, and that the state can surely ameliorate any risk of 
misperceived endorsement by simply issuing a clear disclaimer of neutrality and 
nonendorsement (see Pinette), is it really fair to attribute to the employer 
here the employee's decision to use contraception when (i) the coverage in the 
insurance plan is compelled by law; (ii) the plan can be used for literally 
hundreds of different types of medical goods and services, of which 
contraception is but one; (iii) the decisions whether or not to use the plan 
for contraception are the result of genuinely free and independent private 
choice and could not reasonably be attributed to the employer; and (iv) the 
employer is free to issue as many disclaimers as it wishes, explaining in no 
uncertain terms that it thinks contraception is sinful, that it deplores the 
law in question, that it would strongly urge its employees not to use 
contraception, etc.?

If we're going to argue -- as many of us have -- that the state's involvement 
in the student's choice of a religious school is far too attenuated to 
implicate in any strong manner the conscience rights of the taxpayer whose 
funds eventually make their way, pursuant to many intervening decisions, to the 
religious school's coffers, why should we think there is a substantial burden 
on the employer's obligations of conscience in this case?


___

To post, send message to 
Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edumailto:Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu

To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see

http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw



Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.

Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can

read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the

messages to others.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Steven Jamar
No.  The logic of the decision could be pushed that far in a parallel universe 
or by faculty like us who may indeed inhabit a parallel universe, but such a 
case is so easily distinguishable from a commercial business as to be 
essentially irrelevant.

Steve

On Oct 1, 2012, at 11:57 AM, Rick Garnett wrote:

 Dear colleagues,
  
 Rob Vischer (St. Thomas – MN) has a reaction – one that identifies well the 
 decision’s many flaws -- to the decision we’re discussing, at the “Mirror of 
 Justice” blog:  
 http://mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/mirrorofjustice/2012/10/forcing-a-church-to-pay-for-its-employees-abortions-would-not-create-a-substantial-burden-on-religio.html
  
 As Prof. Vischer reads the decision, its reasoning – i.e., no “substantial 
 burden” -- would apply to a RFRA challenge brought by a Catholic diocese to 
 an exemption-less requirement that the diocese provide insurance coverage for 
 elective abortions.  Do those who have been welcoming this decision agree 
 that RFRA would not / should not protect the diocese in such a case?
  
 Best, R
  
 Richard W. Garnett
 Professor of Law and Associate Dean
 Notre Dame Law School
 P.O. Box 780
 Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-0780
  
 574-631-6981 (w)
 574-276-2252 (cell)
  
 SSRN page
  
 Blogs:
  
 Prawfsblawg
 Mirror of Justice
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
 Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 10:55 AM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: FW: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
  
 Lyng and Bowen involved no regulation of religious behavior. Lee expressly 
 found a burden on free exercise (455 U.S. at 257); the case was decided on 
 compelling interest grounds. None of these cases have any relevance to the 
 burden issue in the ACA cases.
  
 And by the way, I think that all three were rightly decided.
  
 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA  22903
  434-243-8546
  
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
 [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
 Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 8:34 AM
 To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
 Mandate--interpreting substantial burden
  
 Religious groups and their supporters have been trying to water down 
 substantial
 for years.   The Alabama rfra doesn't include substantial and neither did 
 the failed North Dakota or Colorado
 initiatives.  One of the reasons the latter failed is overreaching, though it 
 is also attributable to the fact
 that the Rutherford Institute and others lobbying for rfras have met their 
 match in a number of opposing groups.
  
 The court in the ACA case did little more than apply existing law on the 
 interpretation of substantial.  Those arguing
 the case was wrongly decided on this issue are arguing for a new standard.  
 That is contrary to RFRA's (and RLUIPA's) legislative history, which indicate
 substantial burden was to be interpreted according to existing precedents 
 (as of 1993 and 2000).  In other words, Lyng, Bowen, and Lee are the
 governing interpretations for RFRA.  Subjective views of burden are not part 
 of the doctrine.  It would take the Supreme Court to overturn these
 decisions to grant a win to the religiously affiliated institutions.
  
 Marci
  
  
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003
 (212) 790-0215
 hamilto...@aol.com
  
 
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 
 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
 private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
 people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
 forward the messages to others.

-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Associate Director, Institute for Intellectual Property and Social Justice 
http://iipsj.org
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8567
http://iipsj.com/SDJ/

Education:  the path from cocky ignorance to miserable uncertainty.

Mark Twain




___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Alan Brownstein
Thanks for your post, Marty. Rick, of course, will have to speak for himself. 
But I don't believe that the independent choice of parents as to how they will 
spend education vouchers should end the Establishment Clause inquiry. And I 
also believe that the government's use of taxes to engage in activities that 
violate the taxpayer's religious beliefs burden the taxpayer's religious 
liberty. This doesn't mean that the individual's religious liberty interests 
should be always be vindicated in these kinds of cases. I support a religion 
clause jurisprudence that defines harm or burden or infringement fairly broadly 
so that claims can get on the constitutional playing field. I would assign most 
of the work in determining whether state action is constitutional to the 
adjudication of claims - not to a decision on burden that cuts off all other 
analysis. (I also think that while some burdens may not be sufficient to invoke 
judicial review standing alone, combined with other religious and equality 
interests they should be adjudicated on the merits.)

With regard to the several factors that Marty lists: To begin with, I would 
rephrase Marty's basic question this way. Is it really fair for religious 
liberty purposes to attribute to the employer here the employee's decision to 
use contraceptives when the employer sincerely believes that G-d prohibits him 
from facilitating the use of contraceptives in this way? I think the answer is 
Yes.

More specifically, as others have suggested, I don't see how the coverage being 
compelled by law alters the analysis.

The fact that a religious believer is compelled by a law to do hundreds of 
things that do not violate his faith does not alter the fact that one mandate 
requires him to do what his religion prohibits. One might argue that a broad 
law creates so many instances in which religious liberty might be abridged that 
the government has a strong administrative convenience justification for 
rejecting accommodations for everyone. But that argument goes to justification, 
not to burden.

As to disclaimers, I'm not persuaded that a disclaimer really resolves concerns 
about complicity with or facilitating wrongful acts. But let's assume that one 
of the concerns here has to do with perceptions of complicity by others. There 
are religious rules that are arguably prophylactic measures. There are rules 
that are designed to remind people of things they are supposed to do. There may 
be alternative ways to accomplish these religious goals. The question is 
whether religious individuals and institutions are permitted to follow the 
rules they believe are required by their faith to accomplish religious purposes 
or whether the state gets to require them to violate their beliefs because the 
state thinks that different means are available and preferable for furthering 
their religious purposes.

For example, one of the justifications for prohibiting Jews from eating chicken 
and cheese (milk and meat) even though a chicken obviously doesn't produce milk 
and doesn't really fit into the biblical prohibition is that people might see 
people eating a chicken and cheese sandwich, not understand that the meat in 
the sandwich is from a chicken, and begin to believe that it is OK to eat milk 
with meat. Obviously, there are alternative ways to avoid this 
misunderstanding.  I don't think that states or courts get to dismiss the way 
that Jewish tradition handles the problem because they think there is a better 
way to deal with the issue.

Alan



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 11:52 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Rick, Alan:  Allow me to ask the flip-side question of the one Alan raises:  
For those of us -- myself included, and you, and most of the members of this 
list -- who have long argued that the state is not responsible for the 
genuinely free and independent choices of individuals to use state $$ at a 
school of their choice, and that the state can surely ameliorate any risk of 
misperceived endorsement by simply issuing a clear disclaimer of neutrality and 
nonendorsement (see Pinette), is it really fair to attribute to the employer 
here the employee's decision to use contraception when (i) the coverage in the 
insurance plan is compelled by law; (ii) the plan can be used for literally 
hundreds of different types of medical goods and services, of which 
contraception is but one; (iii) the decisions whether or not to use the plan 
for contraception are the result of genuinely free and independent private 
choice and could not reasonably be attributed to the employer; and (iv) the 
employer is free to issue as many disclaimers as it wishes, explaining in no 
uncertain terms that it thinks contraception is sinful, that it deplores 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Christopher Lund
To Sandy, the “substantial burden” part of this will depend on what the 
plaintiff believes.  If the Jewish prisoner believes that he has a religious 
obligation to eat Kosher meat, then there will be a “substantial burden” if 
the prison doesn’t provide Kosher meat.  But by having such a broad view of 
what his religion requires, the prisoner creates other difficulties for 
himself.  A sincerity problem perhaps, and certainly a compelling interest 
problem.  I haven’t read many of these cases, but I have read some.  And my 
sense is that if the prison supplies nutritious vegetarian food, no court 
would require the prison to build a Kosher kitchen.



To Marci, to the extent that the prisoner can only eat something his 
religion forbids, that’s the clearest form of a substantial burden.  That 
kind of burden is what the Catholic Church claims here.  No doubt that there 
are harder cases.  The prison provides some Kosher foods, maybe enough to 
survive on, but not enough for the kind of diet that other prisoners have. 
I don’t have firm views about those situations, although I think it’s clear 
that the “government-requires-what-my-religion-forbids” situation is not the 
only case of a substantial burden.



Best,

Chris



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Sanford Levinson
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 4:36 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



Must the prison supply kosher meat (and build a kosher kitchen) or is it 
enough that it supplies nutritious vegetarian food, even though other 
prisoners get meat?



sandy



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of hamilto...@aol.com
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 4:28 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



Chris--  I take it you are arguing that for every religious prisoner with a 
dietary restriction, all of them can prove substantial burden,

but the state may or may not win under RLUIPA based on the state's evidence 
of compelling interest?



Is it a substantial burden where the believer can obtain 50% of the foods 
he/she seeks?  I'm broadening this from the kosher

food context, obviously.



Marci



Marci A. Hamilton

Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law

Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law

Yeshiva University

55 Fifth Avenue

New York, NY 10003

(212) 790-0215

hamilto...@aol.com



-Original Message-
From: Christopher Lund l...@wayne.edu
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Mon, Oct 1, 2012 3:39 pm
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

Imagine an observant Jew wants a kosher meal in prison.  The prison doesn’t 
serve kosher food.  Our plaintiff says, “This burdens my religion.”  The 
prison responds, “No, it doesn’t.  You’re not responsible for the food we 
choose to serve in prison.  That’s a genuinely free and independent choice 
that we made.  It has nothing to do with you.”



So why is there a “substantial burden” there?  I think it’s simple: The 
state is requiring the religious observer to do something his religion 
forbids.  Maybe Judaism has overly broad notions of “responsibility.”  But 
those notions are what they are, I think.  The state can’t say, “Your 
theological notions of ‘responsibility’ are absurd,” any more than it can 
say, “Your theological notions about the food God requires you to eat are 
absurd.”



Best,

Chris



From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
[mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu 
mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu? ] On Behalf Of Marty Lederman
Sent: Monday, October 01, 2012 2:52 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden



Rick, Alan:  Allow me to ask the flip-side question of the one Alan raises: 
For those of us -- myself included, and you, and most of the members of this 
list -- who have long argued that the state is not responsible for the 
genuinely free and independent choices of individuals to use state $$ at a 
school of their choice, and that the state can surely ameliorate any risk of 
misperceived endorsement by simply issuing a clear disclaimer of neutrality 
and nonendorsement (see Pinette), is it really fair to attribute to the 
employer here the employee's decision to use contraception when (i) the 
coverage in the insurance plan is compelled by law; (ii) the plan can be 
used for literally hundreds of different types of medical goods and 
services, of which contraception is but one; (iii) the decisions whether or 
not to use the plan for contraception are the result of genuinely free and 
independent private choice and could 

Re: Responsibility for actions that you assist

2012-10-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
One other variation: nuisance and related bodies of law generally hold 
landlords responsible for what tenants do on the property.

On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 12:55:45 -0700
 Volokh, Eugene vol...@law.ucla.edu wrote:
Let me add that American law has very different views of when 
 people are responsible for the acts of others, or when they can demand that 
 they not assist in the acts of others.  For instance,

1.  Zelman sets forth one rule when it comes to taxpayers' 
 right to object to the use of their money under the Establishment Clause.

2.  Abood and Keller set forth a different rule when it comes 
 to fee payers' right to object to the use of their fees (as opposed to 
 general taxes) under the Free Speech Clause.

3.  Criminal law in most jurisdictions holds people 
 responsible for aiding and abetting only when they have the purpose of aiding 
 conduct.

4.  Criminal law in some jurisdictions, or as to some crimes, 
 holds people responsible for aiding and abetting when they have the knowledge 
 that they are aiding the conduct.

5.  In some jurisdictions, e.g., in New York, the standard for 
 responsibility under special-purpose statutes is close to recklessness (e.g., 
 believing it probable under the New York statute).

6.  Special purpose criminal laws (as opposed to general 
 aiding and abetting law) sometimes have special rules for holding people 
 responsible for doing things that assist certain kinds of misconduct based; 
 consider, for instance, the federal ban on providing material assistance to 
 designated terrorist organizations, or the laws in some states that 
 criminalize recklessly facilitate escape from criminal custody.

7.  Tort law may in some situations hold people liable for 
 aiding and abetting others' misconduct so long as the person was negligent 
 about the possibility that the other person would use the person's help for 
 bad purposes.  (Consider negligent entrustment claims, for instance, whether 
 as to cars, guns, or what have you.)

I tend to agree with Chris and the others who take the view 
 that the RFRA substantial burden question ought not be influenced by this, 
 but rather by whether the claimant sincerely believes that he is asked to do 
 something that he sees as sinful.  But the fact that our own legal system has 
 such a complex view of when assistance is enough to make the assister 
 responsible should further counsel in favor of focusing on the claimant's 
 beliefs about responsibility, rather than trying to impose some rule of its 
 own about responsibility.

None of this, of course, deals with whether the law could 
 still be applied to objectors because (1) such an application passes strict 
 scrutiny, or (2) the legislature carves out the relevant statute from RFRA.

Eugene

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-10-01 Thread b...@jmcenter.org
Steve -- I agree with what you've said. I would point out that you used the term
burden, not substantial burden. My point is that I the contraceptive mandate
burden's an employer's free exercise if they are opposed to the mandate for
religious reasons -- but, importantly, they are not substantially burdened in my
view (as I believe Judge Jackson correctly analyzed the burden). The religious
burden is de minimis and remote. And there is no economic burden as the mandated
coverage is, in the aggregate, is a cost saver.

In addition, I believe a fair analogy would be to the Lemon test's excessive
entanglement prong. Mere entanglement doesn't constitute an Establishment
Clause violation just as a mere burden doesn't establish a Free Exercise
Clause violation here.

Bob Ritter

Jefferson Madison Center for Religious Liberty
A Project of the Law Office of Robert V. Ritter
Falls Church, VA
703-533-0236

On September 29, 2012 at 11:44 PM Steven Jamar stevenja...@gmail.com wrote:
 Of course the law burdens religious exercise -- if you take religious exercise
 to that extreme meaning. If you choose to take it to that extreme, then you
 cannot be in that line of work or you must pay the penalty for engaging in
 that kind of work.

 You can't simply ignore civil law because you don't like it. I didn't like my
 taxes going to the war in Iraq (and I can think of lots of other things I
 don't like. And I have moral objections to many things, though fewer things
 than those I don't like. And I think torture is violates just about every
 religion out there.

 And yet I must pay for these things I don't believe in.

 The social security cases and other cases were properly decided -- following
 the same economic rules as everyone else when you enter the market place is
 not a substantial burden on your exercise. If you can't do it, get out of the
 market and into something where you can follow your religion.

 Free exercise is not a free pass.

 Steve

 On Sep 29, 2012, at 10:52 PM, Walsh, Kevin wrote:

  The court appears to have recharacterized the allegations in the RFRA claim
  to make it easier to dismiss.
  
  From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
  [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] on behalf of Marty Lederman
  [lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
  Sent: Saturday, September 29, 2012 10:30 PM
  To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
  Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate
 
  For what it's worth, here are the allegations in the complaint relevant to
  establishing the alleged burden on religious exercise:
 
 
  Plaintiff O’Brien believes that he cannot pay for and provide coverage for
  contraceptives, sterilization, abortion or related education and counseling
  without violating his religious beliefs.
 
  Plaintiffs are . . . confronted with choosing between complying with [the
  HHS mandate] in violation of their religious beliefs, or paying ruinous
  fines that would have a crippling impact on their ability to survive
  economically.
 
  * * *
 
  The Mandate coerces Plaintiffs into complying with its requirements or
  abandoning integral components of the Plaintiffs’ religiously inspired
  mission and values.
 
  Plaintiffs’ sincerely held religious beliefs prevent them from providing
  coverage for “all FDA-approved contraceptive methods, sterilization
  procedures, and patient education and counseling related to such
  procedures.”
 
  The Mandate/Final Rule, by requiring Plaintiffs to provide said coverage,
  imposes a substantial burden on Plaintiffs’ free exercise of religion by
  coercing Plaintiffs to choose between conducting their business in
  accordance with their religious beliefs or paying substantial penalties to
  the government.
 
 
  On Sat, Sep 29, 2012 at 9:43 PM, Walsh, Kevin
  kwa...@richmond.edumailto:kwa...@richmond.edu wrote:
  The court's carelessness with respect to substantial burden prevented it
  from facing up to the more interesting legal question re: exercise of
  religion.
 
  I say that the court was careless because its analysis depends upon a
  tendentious characterization of the nature of the religious objection. How
  does someone run a business with 87 employees if his religion prohibits an
  outlay of funds that might eventually be used by a third party in a manner
  inconsistent with one's values? That kind of religious belief would make it
  difficult to gas up a car and head into work, or even just to stay home and
  surf the internet. Maybe, instead, the objection has something to do with
  being forced by the government to pay for a particular kind of policy
  (rather than pay taxes and have the government purchase the policy instead).
 
  In the law, there is such a thing as winning too much. I suspect that is the
  federal government's view of this sloppy decision.
  
  From:
  religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edumailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu
  

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
We have a long political tradition of treating objections to killing as a 
special claim, deserving special protection. We have exempted conscientious 
objectors in all our wars, even when national existence was on the line, and 
notwithstanding powerful incentives to dubious conversions or false claims. 

This protection has not been as broad as objectors would like; it is not immune 
to limitation when government chooses to assert its compelling interests. But 
it received very strong protection that grew stronger over time. 

In the war case, we all agree that draftees may be asked to kill other human 
beings, but the majority says these are lawful killings, and the minority says 
they are killings prohibited by God. 

In the abortion case, the majority believes it is not a killing of a human 
being; the conscientious objector believes it is. The disagreement over the 
nature of the killing comes at a slightly different point; I do not claim that 
the cases are identical. 

I do believe that there are sound reasons, reflected in our legal and political 
tradition, to give special deference to what the conscientious objector 
believes is a refusal to kill another human being.

The cases also differ in the weight of the government's interest; it is almost 
never essential that an abortion be performed or assisted by a particular 
medical provider.

On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 17:16:55 -0400 (EDT)
 hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
In response to Rick, the answer to the question from my perspective is that a 
religiously affiliated organization (not a church) could be required to provide
insurance that includes all possible medically feasible and advisable 
treatments.  That is a classic, neutral, generally applicable law.


Obviously, abortion is at times a medically feasible and medically advisable 
treatment.  The employer buys an ombnibus insurance plan, and employers, 
consistent with medical advice and their own religious and personal views, 
choose what treatments they obtain.  That seems to me constitutional.  This is 
not distinguishable
from the objections raised by Quakers having to pay taxes that support war or 
the Amish having to pay into social security that supports a set of 
relationships
they believe are religiously wrong.


I'm glad you asked this question, because it seems to indicate that the 
argument against the ACA at base appears to be that the belief against 
abortion is somehow more important than other beliefs.  I don't see how the 
Establishment Clause permits that kind of religious belief prioritizing, or 
any of the free exercise cases either.


No employer should be able to exclude blood transfusions, which are abhorrent 
to Jehovahs Witnesses, from medical coverage. I haven't heard anyone
get behind such an exemption.But those opposing the ACA's reproductive 
health care provisions seem to be suggesting that somehow abortion opposition 
is a superior belief that deserves extra constitutional protection.  


 
Marci A. Hamilton
Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
Yeshiva University
55 Fifth Avenue
New York, NY 10003
(212) 790-0215
hamilto...@aol.com




-Original Message-
From: Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Sent: Mon, Oct 1, 2012 1:49 pm
Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA 
Mandate--interpreting substantial burden


Rob's thoughts are well worth reading -- he puts his finger on a bunch of 
questions that are sure to be central to these cases going forward.

One caveat on the equivalence point raised by Rob and Rick:

To the extent the court is rejecting a proximate cooperation with evil 
theory of substantial burden here, then yes, that same theory would presumably 
be subject to the same objections if the case involved a diocese and elective 
abortion coverage.  But the diocese would have a much stronger substantial 
burden argument on a different theory -- one of the institutional autonomy 
theories that Rick referred to earlier.  In particular, assuming the diocese 
exercises its title VII exemption, and prefers coreligionists in employment, 
then I'd assume one of its principal functions -- unlike that of the 
ceramics-processing O'Brien Industrial Company -- is to create and nurture a 
particular kind of religious community, one in which its employees are 
expected to advance its Catholic mission, and to adhere to Catholic tenets in 
their own conduct.  The HHS rule would arguably have a significant impact on 
the ability of the diocese to so shape its community and to ensure that its 
emplo
 yees act
in accordance with Catholic precepts.  In that respect, the diocese is very 
differently situated for RFRA purposes from the O'Brien Industrial Company, 
which hires many non-Catholics and that does not endeavor to require its 
employees to conform their conduct to Catholic precepts.


On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 11:57 AM, Rick Garnett 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-10-01 Thread b...@jmcenter.org
Mark,

Barnette is direct and we can agree that compelled recitation violated
Barnette's Free Exercise of religion (and I hope we could agree that the current
Pledge with under God violates the Establishment Clause).

However, I believe that the court was correct in noting that once employment is
introduced to the equation, we start getting degrees of separation and a
reduction of the burden (i.e., becomes remote). Personally, I don't find your
direct payment scenario a substantial burden either. An employer pays thousands
(or millions for a large employer) of invoices each year. If they want to stay
in business, they pay their bills.

Bob Ritter

On September 30, 2012 at 1:36 AM Scarberry, Mark
mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 
  So suppose the law specifically required the employer to pay directly to a
 clinic its charges for an employee’s abortion. The employee has an abortion at
 a clinic, tells the clinic to send the bill to the employer, and the employer
 then must pay the bill on pain of fines that will put the employer out of
 business. The employer is a practicing Catholic who follows the Church’s
 teachings. Is this a substantial burden on the employer’s exercise of
 religion? Will anyone argue that this is not?
 
 
 
  Now what if the law is changed to require the employer to buy insurance for
 employees that specifically and only covers abortion procedures?
 
 
 
  And now what if the law is changed to require the employer to buy health
 insurance that covers lots of health costs and also covers abortions? Can we
 say that there no longer is a substantial burden on the employer’s exercise of
 religion because now the employer is required to do more?
 
 
 
  Of course there is a long history of careful, thoughtful moral analysis that
 treats the directness of a person’s involvement in an action as a key
 indicator of  the person’s moral responsibility for it. It is not
 idiosyncratic at all for the employer to believe that he or she is being
 coerced into violating religious conscience by being required specifically to
 subsidize an activity that he or she believes is wrong, and, even worse, by
 being required to agree specifically to subsidize that activity by entering
 into a contract providing for it to be subsidized.
 
 
 
  This is not at all the same thing as paying a salary that an employee may use
 in a way that the is contrary to the employer’s religious beliefs (for
 example, obtaining an abortion). The payment of the salary does not require
 the employer to agree specifically to subsidize that activity. But by entering
 into a health insurance contract that specifically covers abortions, the
 employer does so agree and is, according to a very reasonable moral analysis,
 complicit.
 
 
 
  If you pay taxes, you do not have to enter into an agreement that your money
 may be used to wage war or to pay for other things that you could not, as a
 matter of religious conscience, be involved in. The government requires you to
 pay the taxes, and then the government decides what to do with the money, with
 no need for you to agree at all. Same for payment of a salary that the
 employee may use as the employee chooses. You do not have to agree that the
 employee may obtain an abortion, nor do you pay the salary to allow the
 employee to obtain the abortion; you are not complicit.
 
 
 
  The court in this case in effect chose its own version of moral casuistry,
 and decided that an action that would not, on the court’s view, create
 complicity in an action, could not as a matter of law burden the employer’s
 exercise of religion. That is the same as the court deciding that a tenet of
 the employer’s religion is false, because the moral analysis that leads to the
 conclusion of complicity is part of the employer’s religious beliefs.
 
 
 
  Of course the finding of a substantial burden does not end the analysis. If
 we assume that the govt interest is compelling, we have to ask whether the
 govt can accomplish its purposes without violating the religious conscience of
 the employer (or the taxpayer); is the government using an approach that
 minimizes the imposition on religious conscience (the least restrictive means
 requirement of RFRA)? The government could not function if every taxpayer had
 a veto over how his or her taxes were used. But a health care system can cover
 abortions or whatever procedures the govt wants to cover without requiring
 religious people to agree specifically to subsidize what they consider to be
 religiously prohibited. Employers who refuse to buy health insurance for
 employees that cover such procedures can be taxed for not doing so, in an
 amount that is sufficient to allow the govt to provide supplemental insurance
 policies to employees who want them. The employer may not like having to pay a
 tax that could be seen to subsidize an activity with which he or she disagrees
 on religious grounds (though money is fungible and thus it isn’t clear that
 this 

Re: Sebelius query

2012-10-01 Thread Steven Jamar
CJ Roberts is correct to look at the substance and not the word.  In substance 
it is a tax.  It is not a penalty.

On Oct 1, 2012, at 7:28 PM, Ilya Somin wrote:

 This argument ignores the fact that the problem with the tax argument for the 
 mandate was never that it was not for the general welfare but that the 
 mandate was not a tax at all, but a penalty. If the mandate is not a tax, it 
 cannot be authorized by the Tax Clause, no matter how much it benefits the 
 general welfare.
 
 That's what the lower courts that ruled on the issue unanimously concluded. 
 Even those judges who accepted the broadest possibly interpretation of the 
 Commerce Clause still rejected the tax argument.
 
 I also don't see any way that rejecting the Commerce Clause somehow 
 strengthens the tax argument, except in the political sense that decision 
 endorsing the latter might be more palatable to conservatives if it also 
 rejects the former.
 
 Ilya Somin
 Professor of Law
 Editor, Supreme Court Economic Review
 George Mason University School of Law
 3301 Fairfax Dr.
 Arlington, VA 22201
 ph: 703-993-8069
 fax: 703-993-8124
 e-mail: iso...@gmu.edu
 Website: http://mason.gmu.edu/~isomin/
 SSRN Page: http://ssrn.com/author=39
 
 

-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Associate Director, Institute for Intellectual Property and Social Justice 
http://iipsj.org
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8567
http://iipsj.com/SDJ/






___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Substantial burden and the merit of RFRAs

2012-10-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
As one of the few people on this list who both supports Smith and 
supports jurisdiction-by-jurisdiction RFRAs, let me put in a plug for my 
theory.  The worry (expressed, for instance, by Sandy) that religious 
objections, both sincere and insincere, can undermine an important law is a 
serious worry.  But the substantial burden test is the wrong place to take that 
worry into account.  The substantial burden test should be about whether the 
law sufficiently interferes with people's ability to comply with their felt 
religious obligations.  The place for considering the government interest in 
uniformity is elsewhere.

One obvious place where the government interest can be considered is 
the compelling interest test.  But another -- available under the RFRA model 
but not under the Sherbert/Yoder model -- is in the legislature.  If a 
legislature thinks that some law must be applied uniformly, notwithstanding 
religious objections, it can just exempt that law from RFRA's purview, either 
at the time it enacts the law or after an exception is carved out by a court.  
(Of course, there could be political difficulties with that, but that would 
just reflect a political judgment against the proposition that the law must 
indeed be applied without any room for objections.)  Given this power, I don't 
see why we need to depart from the Thomas v. Review Board vision of the 
substantial burden threshold, and jeopardize the equality and nonentanglement 
values that this Thomas vision embodies.

Eugene
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Marty Lederman
Fortunately, the question here is far, far removed from whether the state
can or should require anyone to perform an abortion, or to kill in battle.
It is, instead, whether the state can require employers to take some of the
money they would have used to pay employee salaries, or taxes -- some of
which would foreseeably have been used to pay for contraception (or even
abortions, in the case of salaries), anyway -- and instead use it to
partially subsidize an insurance plan that, like salaries and taxes, is
used to pay for countless goods and services, some of which involve
contraception, but only when someone else (the employee) chooses to use it
for that purpose.  (FWIW, I believe the law does not allow HHS to require
plans to cover abortions, and the Rule therefore does not do so.)

Doug, a couple of your posts here have suggested that even in the cases of
salaries and taxes being used for contraception, there is a substantial
burden on the religious exercise of objectors, but one that might be
overcome by a compelling government interest.  For anyone who starts from
that view, the HHS would certainly raise a harder question.  But I am not
aware of any employer, or Catholic theologian, who takes the view that the
payment of taxes or salaries is wrongful just because the employer knows
that they will be put to use for contraception and (in the case of
salaries) abortions . . . and many other things, besides, that are wrongful
in the eyes of the employer.

Thus the question here is whether the state ought to take at face value the
assertions of some employers that the moral obligation changes dramatically
when the money is used for partial subsidization of an insurance plan,
rather than for taxes or salaries.  I actually think this is a complex
question, as to which I deeply appreciate the many thoughtful views others
have contributed to this thread.  But whatever the merits of that
distinction, the case is a far cry from compelling the employer to kill
another human being.

On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 7:27 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 We have a long political tradition of treating objections to killing as a
 special claim, deserving special protection. We have exempted conscientious
 objectors in all our wars, even when national existence was on the line,
 and notwithstanding powerful incentives to dubious conversions or false
 claims.

 This protection has not been as broad as objectors would like; it is not
 immune to limitation when government chooses to assert its compelling
 interests. But it received very strong protection that grew stronger over
 time.

 In the war case, we all agree that draftees may be asked to kill other
 human beings, but the majority says these are lawful killings, and the
 minority says they are killings prohibited by God.

 In the abortion case, the majority believes it is not a killing of a human
 being; the conscientious objector believes it is. The disagreement over the
 nature of the killing comes at a slightly different point; I do not claim
 that the cases are identical.

 I do believe that there are sound reasons, reflected in our legal and
 political tradition, to give special deference to what the conscientious
 objector believes is a refusal to kill another human being.

 The cases also differ in the weight of the government's interest; it is
 almost never essential that an abortion be performed or assisted by a
 particular medical provider.

 On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 17:16:55 -0400 (EDT)
  hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 In response to Rick, the answer to the question from my perspective is
 that a religiously affiliated organization (not a church) could be required
 to provide
 insurance that includes all possible medically feasible and advisable
 treatments.  That is a classic, neutral, generally applicable law.
 
 
 Obviously, abortion is at times a medically feasible and medically
 advisable treatment.  The employer buys an ombnibus insurance plan, and
 employers, consistent with medical advice and their own religious and
 personal views, choose what treatments they obtain.  That seems to me
 constitutional.  This is not distinguishable
 from the objections raised by Quakers having to pay taxes that support
 war or the Amish having to pay into social security that supports a set of
 relationships
 they believe are religiously wrong.
 
 
 I'm glad you asked this question, because it seems to indicate that the
 argument against the ACA at base appears to be that the belief against
 abortion is somehow more important than other beliefs.  I don't see how the
 Establishment Clause permits that kind of religious belief prioritizing, or
 any of the free exercise cases either.
 
 
 No employer should be able to exclude blood transfusions, which are
 abhorrent to Jehovahs Witnesses, from medical coverage. I haven't heard
 anyone
 get behind such an exemption.But those opposing the ACA's
 reproductive health care provisions seem to be suggesting that somehow
 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and exemption 
from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be nothing 
special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim than just the 
ACA issue.  And there are people in the pro-choice movement pushing against 
conscience protections for medical providers.

As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays salary, and 
the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer considers immoral. 
The salary payments could have been used for anything.

I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the government 
will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral, is highly 
attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's compelling interest in 
paying taxes.

The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because the money 
is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer buys a package 
of services that includes the services the employer believes to be immoral, 
including the morning-after and week-after pills that the employer believes 
sometimes kill human beings. The employer contracts for those services and pays 
for those services, and these employers say they cannot in conscience do those 
things.

On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400
 Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
Fortunately, the question here is far, far removed from whether the state
can or should require anyone to perform an abortion, or to kill in battle.
It is, instead, whether the state can require employers to take some of the
money they would have used to pay employee salaries, or taxes -- some of
which would foreseeably have been used to pay for contraception (or even
abortions, in the case of salaries), anyway -- and instead use it to
partially subsidize an insurance plan that, like salaries and taxes, is
used to pay for countless goods and services, some of which involve
contraception, but only when someone else (the employee) chooses to use it
for that purpose.  (FWIW, I believe the law does not allow HHS to require
plans to cover abortions, and the Rule therefore does not do so.)

Doug, a couple of your posts here have suggested that even in the cases of
salaries and taxes being used for contraception, there is a substantial
burden on the religious exercise of objectors, but one that might be
overcome by a compelling government interest.  For anyone who starts from
that view, the HHS would certainly raise a harder question.  But I am not
aware of any employer, or Catholic theologian, who takes the view that the
payment of taxes or salaries is wrongful just because the employer knows
that they will be put to use for contraception and (in the case of
salaries) abortions . . . and many other things, besides, that are wrongful
in the eyes of the employer.

Thus the question here is whether the state ought to take at face value the
assertions of some employers that the moral obligation changes dramatically
when the money is used for partial subsidization of an insurance plan,
rather than for taxes or salaries.  I actually think this is a complex
question, as to which I deeply appreciate the many thoughtful views others
have contributed to this thread.  But whatever the merits of that
distinction, the case is a far cry from compelling the employer to kill
another human being.

On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 7:27 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 We have a long political tradition of treating objections to killing as a
 special claim, deserving special protection. We have exempted conscientious
 objectors in all our wars, even when national existence was on the line,
 and notwithstanding powerful incentives to dubious conversions or false
 claims.

 In the abortion case, the majority believes it is not a killing of a human
 being; the conscientious objector believes it is. The disagreement over the
 nature of the killing comes at a slightly different point; I do not claim
 that the cases are identical.

 I do believe that there are sound reasons, reflected in our legal and
 political tradition, to give special deference to what the conscientious
 objector believes is a refusal to kill another human being.

 The cases also differ in the weight of the government's interest; it is
 almost never essential that an abortion be performed or assisted by a
 particular medical provider.

 On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 17:16:55 -0400 (EDT)
  hamilto...@aol.com wrote:
 
 
 I'm glad you asked this question, because it seems to indicate that the
 argument against the ACA at base appears to be that the belief against
 abortion is somehow more important than other beliefs.  I don't see how the
 Establishment Clause permits that kind of religious belief prioritizing, or
 any of the free exercise cases either.
 
 
 Marci A. Hamilton
 Paul R. Verkuil Chair in Public Law
 Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law
 Yeshiva University
 55 Fifth Avenue
 New York, NY 10003
 (212) 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-10-01 Thread b...@jmcenter.org
About 45 years ago I left the Catholic Church and don't keep up with its
teachings. This being said, it is my understanding that the Catholic Church has
not always opposed abortion. If this true, is long tradition true?

I also take exception to characterizing the Affordable Care Act and/or the
contraceptive mandate as trampling on someone's religion. In a just society,
multiple interests have to be weighed. The employer is not the only person in
interest. I appears to me that those who disagreed with Judge Jackson's
reasoning ignore that (1) employment in a commercial setting is nonreligious and
(2) the purpose of the mandate is to provide health care for women, including
making it on par with health care for men. Like the judge, I find Smith rather
than RFRA controlling.

Bob Ritter


On September 30, 2012 at 11:56 AM Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.edu wrote:
 Mark references a long tradition of religious thought about cooperation with
 evil, and how close is too close -- a tradition that is found in both
 Christian and Jewish teachings (and probably other faiths too, but I know less
 about those).

 This tradition was probably not explained to the court. It may or may not have
 made any difference. Judges have been attracted to no-burden holdings since
 RFRA was enacted, I think because it seems to make a hard case go away. They
 don't have to limit the reach of the government's program, they don't announce
 that some modest government interest is actually compelling, and they don't
 have to admit that they are letting the government trample on someone's
 religion.

 Intense believers in these cases are often represented by intensely believing
 attorneys, and they too often treat the burden on religion as obvious, and do
 a lousy job of developing the issue. I don't know if that happened here, but I
 suspect that it did, and of course I don't know whether it would have
 mattered.

 A substantial secular business as plaintiff likely affected the initial
 judicial reaction to this case. But the reasoning appears to be equally
 applicable to religious non-profits controlled by bishops or other religious
 authorities.


 On Sat, 29 Sep 2012 22:36:44 -0700
 Scarberry, Mark mark.scarbe...@pepperdine.edu wrote:

 Of course there is a long history of careful, thoughtful moral analysis that
 treats the directness of a person's involvement in an action as a key
 indicator of the person's moral responsibility for it. It is not
 idiosyncratic at all for the employer to believe that he or she is being
 coerced into violating religious conscience by being required specifically to
 subsidize an activity that he or she believes is wrong, and, even worse, by
 being required to agree specifically to subsidize that activity by entering
 into a contract providing for it to be subsidized.

 Douglas Laycock
 Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
 University of Virginia Law School
 580 Massie Road
 Charlottesville, VA 22903
 434-243-8546
 ___
 To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

 Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.
 Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can
 read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the
 messages to others.___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Marty Lederman
Thanks for the clarification, Doug.  I had missed that particular part of
the exchange.

On the distinction you suggest, I think that the characterization of the
requirement as purchasing a package of services does not fairly describe
what's going on here.  Or at the very least, this is nothing like what
comes to mind when one hears that phrase -- such as the employer hiring a
contractor to paint the walls, install new fixtures, etc.

The Rule requires the employer to *make available* to its employees a group
health plan.  (In fact, not even that -- the employer can instead make a
payment to the government, a payment that Robin Wilson suggested at our
Conference would typically be much *less* than the cost of the employer's
portion of the plan premiums.)  The law does not even require the employer
to pay premiums into the plan, although that might end up being a practical
necessity, since the plan must be one that is affordable to the
employees, which in most cases will presumably not include a plan
subsidized entirely by employee premiums.

So let's assume for sake of argument that as a practical matter the Rule
requires employers to pay a certain premium to the insurance company.  (I'm
putting aside here the serious question of whether the alternative payment
to the Fed changes the burden analysis.)  That premium does not pay for a
package of services *to the employer*.  It pays to partly subsidize (in
part) an enormously wide range of goods and services -- virtually any
related to health -- that will be used only if and when the employees need
them and choose to use them.  (And even then, the employer will never know
which services were used.)

That feels to me quite a bit different from an employer purchasing a
package of services.  Imagine, for instance, that the Rule instead
required employers to pay the same amount of money to a *government* *agency
* (rather than to a private insurance company) for the specific purpose of
funding a government-provided health insurance plan . . . a plan that works
*exactly like the plans in question here*, covering the exact same goods
and services, including contraceptive services.

In the case of such a Medicare tax -- one that these same employers
probably pay currently -- would you describe it as the employer being
forced to purchase a package of services?  Would Catholic employers claim
that it forces them to cooperate with evil in a way that their religion
forbids?


On Mon, Oct 1, 2012 at 8:01 PM, Douglas Laycock dlayc...@virginia.eduwrote:

 My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and
 exemption from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be
 nothing special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim
 than just the ACA issue.  And there are people in the pro-choice movement
 pushing against conscience protections for medical providers.

 As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays salary,
 and the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer considers
 immoral. The salary payments could have been used for anything.

 I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the
 government will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral,
 is highly attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's
 compelling interest in paying taxes.

 The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because the
 money is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer buys
 a package of services that includes the services the employer believes to
 be immoral, including the morning-after and week-after pills that the
 employer believes sometimes kill human beings. The employer contracts for
 those services and pays for those services, and these employers say they
 cannot in conscience do those things.

 On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400
  Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
 Fortunately, the question here is far, far removed from whether the state
 can or should require anyone to perform an abortion, or to kill in battle.
 It is, instead, whether the state can require employers to take some of
 the
 money they would have used to pay employee salaries, or taxes -- some of
 which would foreseeably have been used to pay for contraception (or even
 abortions, in the case of salaries), anyway -- and instead use it to
 partially subsidize an insurance plan that, like salaries and taxes, is
 used to pay for countless goods and services, some of which involve
 contraception, but only when someone else (the employee) chooses to use it
 for that purpose.  (FWIW, I believe the law does not allow HHS to require
 plans to cover abortions, and the Rule therefore does not do so.)
 
 Doug, a couple of your posts here have suggested that even in the cases of
 salaries and taxes being used for contraception, there is a substantial
 burden on the religious exercise of objectors, but one that might be
 overcome by a compelling government 

RE: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

2012-10-01 Thread b...@jmcenter.org
The beliefs can be serious and strong. But that alone is not sufficient to make
the burden substantial.

Reminds me of taxpayer standing cases. A federal taxpayer generally doesn't have
standing to challenge appropriations because his or her tax dollars cannot be
specifically traced to the objection expenditure. De minimis. So no standing.

On the other end is Barnette -- where Barnette was compelled to salute the
American flag.

The contraceptive mandate is somewhere in between. The employer isn't forced to
use contraceptives. Isn't even forced to say their use is morally OK. In fact,
as Judge Jackson notes, can even suggest to employees not to use them. The line
unfortunately must be drawn somewhere on the slippery slope.

A lot of what I'm reading on the is blog written by those who oppose Judge
Jackson's decision sounds more like disguised whining than sound arguments that
the mandate imposes a substantial burden on employers with a religious viewpoint
opposed to contraception.

Bob Ritter


On September 30, 2012 at 2:30 PM Berg, Thomas C. tcb...@stthomas.edu wrote:
 Marty,



 The fact that services must be covered in the plan by virtue of legal
 mandate (are required by law) can't be enough to counter the asserion of a
 burden, can it--or even be a significant factor in countering it? That would
 do away with virtually every free exercise claim (I'm only providing
 facilities for an abortion, or I'm only receiving a blood transfusion, under
 legal compulsion).



 You place a lot of weight on the claim that most Catholic theologians say this
 isn't cooperation with evil, and that no one has articulated a serious
 argument that distinguishes this and paying salaries or taxes. I don't think
 those things are true (can one conference show it?): consider, for example,
 Robbie George and Sharif Girgis's exchange with you a few months ago, or
 Mark's argument here about inclusion of the services in the plan language. You
 and others may not find those arguments convincing. But rejecting the burden
 claim based on finding the distinction unconvincing, or on the existence of a
 great deal of skepticism among [Catholic] theologians, can't be squared--can
 it?--with Thomas v. Review Board, where the Court said that Thomas's judgment
 on what work would cooperate with the evil of arms production should be
 deferred to even though other Jehovah's Witnesses disagreed. Courts are not
 arbiters of scriptural interpretation; the court can't dismiss the!
 claim at the threshold because it concludes the asserted belief is not
 logical, not consistent, etc.



 Occasionally you seem to be treating this as a question of remoteness of
 facilitation for burden purposes independent of Catholic moral thought; but
 more often you return (as I think one must in assessing burden) to asking why
 claimants believe this is material cooperation with evil, from a Catholic
 moral perspective. That latter question, it seems to me, falls squarely
 within the restrictions of Thomas v. Review Board not to second-guess the
 claimant's understanding of its obligations.



 Tom



 -
 Thomas C. Berg
 James L. Oberstar Professor of Law and Public Policy
 University of St. Thomas School of Law
 MSL 400, 1000 LaSalle Avenue
 Minneapolis, MN 55403-2015
 Phone: 651 962 4918
 Fax: 651 962 4881
 E-mail: tcb...@stthomas.edumailto:tcb...@stthomas.edu
 SSRN: http://ssrn.com/author='261564
 Weblog:
 http://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.comhttp://www.mirrorofjustice.blogs.com/
 
 
 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu]
 on behalf of Marty Lederman [lederman.ma...@gmail.com]
 Sent: Sunday, September 30, 2012 11:56 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate

 My post bounced, apparently because of the number of recipients! Resending
 without so many cc's. Sorry for any duplicate receipts.

 On Sun, Sep 30, 2012 at 12:52 PM, Marty Lederman
 lederman.ma...@gmail.commailto:lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
 For what it's worth, at our Georgetown Conference on this issue last week (a
 video of which should be posted soon), there appeared to be a great deal of
 skepticism among the Catholic theologians and other scholars present (some of
 whom I am copying here, along with some others at the conference) that where
 an employer provides employees with access to a health-insurance plan on
 compulsion of law; the services in question are part of the plan virtue of
 legal mandate; and the use of the plan to pay for any particular heath care
 service is entirely within the discretion of the employee and her physician,
 the employer does not thereby engage in material cooperation with evil just
 because some employees might choose to use the plan (unbeknownst to the
 employer) to subsidize the use of 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Steven Jamar
So it is just a question of line drawing after all.  
A.  Is it at taxation with taxes paying for things you don't like? 
B.  Or is it paying a salary or wages that will be used by some for things 
you don't like?  
C.  Or is it providing mandated benefits for things you don't like? 
D.  Or is it paying out of pocket for the thing you don't like?  
E.  Or is it being required to actually do the thing you don't like 
(administer the pill, do the abortion yourself)?  

I understand the distinction some want to make, but don't agree with it.  The 
requirement to provide health insurance vitiates the erstwhile agreement.  I 
get that some don't see it that way.  But it is not for the individual to 
decide where to draw the line for substantial burden -- that is a legal 
standard to be applied by the courts and drawing the line in the ACA case 
between C and D above is fully defensible on all grounds, philosophical and 
legal and practical -- though one can curtail the causal link elsewhere for 
other purposes.

Thus the substantial burden is the right place to decide this and many other 
cases, rather than compelling interest and least restrictive alternative test.  
As we have seen in the EP cases, least restrictive alternative can be a 
nearly insurmountable bar since a decent lawyer can always find some 
alternative that, upon reflection and analysis is less restrictive, and there 
is no telling what a compelling interest would be in this setting.  There 
simply are no standards for that yet.  If the court had ruled that there was a 
compelling interest here the same people would be attacking the decision on the 
grounds that ACA's provisions are not a compelling state interest and even if 
they are, the use of ACA to accomplish the provisions of those benefits is not 
the least restrictive alternative because less restrictive would be to have an 
exception granted to religious claimants, even those engaged in ordinary 
commerce as employers.

Steve



On Oct 1, 2012, at 8:01 PM, Douglas Laycock wrote:

 My post on the analogy between exemption from military service and exemption 
 from abortion was addressed to Marci's claim that there should be nothing 
 special about objection to abortion. That is a much broader claim than just 
 the ACA issue.  And there are people in the pro-choice movement pushing 
 against conscience protections for medical providers.
 
 As to ACA, I do not think there is a burden when an employer pays salary, and 
 the employee then uses the money for purposes the employer considers immoral. 
 The salary payments could have been used for anything.
 
 I think the burden on the taxpayer who pays taxes, knowing that the 
 government will use the money for purposes the taxpayer considers immoral, is 
 highly attenuated, and uniformly outweighed by the government's compelling 
 interest in paying taxes.
 
 The ACA looks different to those objecting, and plausibly so, because the 
 money is not paid to the employees or to the government. The employer buys a 
 package of services that includes the services the employer believes to be 
 immoral, including the morning-after and week-after pills that the employer 
 believes sometimes kill human beings. The employer contracts for those 
 services and pays for those services, and these employers say they cannot in 
 conscience do those things.
 
 On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 19:46:50 -0400
 Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
 Fortunately, the question here is far, far removed from whether the state
 can or should require anyone to perform an abortion, or to kill in battle.
 It is, instead, whether the state can require employers to take some of the
 money they would have used to pay employee salaries, or taxes -- some of
 which would foreseeably have been used to pay for contraception (or even
 abortions, in the case of salaries), anyway -- and instead use it to
 partially subsidize an insurance plan that, like salaries and taxes, is
 used to pay for countless goods and services, some of which involve
 contraception, but only when someone else (the employee) chooses to use it
 for that purpose.  (FWIW, I believe the law does not allow HHS to require
 plans to cover abortions, and the Rule therefore does not do so.)
 
 Doug, a couple of your posts here have suggested that even in the cases of
 salaries and taxes being used for contraception, there is a substantial
 burden on the religious exercise of objectors, but one that might be
 overcome by a compelling government interest.  For anyone who starts from
 that view, the HHS would certainly raise a harder question.  But I am not
 aware of any employer, or Catholic theologian, who takes the view that the
 payment of taxes or salaries is wrongful just because the employer knows
 that they will be put to use for contraception and (in the case of
 salaries) abortions . . . and many other things, besides, that are wrongful
 in the eyes of the employer.
 
 Thus the question 

Re: Court Rejects Religious Liberty Challenges To ACA Mandate--interpreting substantial burden

2012-10-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
On the law we have, the employer buys the insurance policy.  Different policies 
cover different packages of benefits. These employers feel morally responsible 
for the package they buy. 

Of course they are generally entitled to define their own religious beliefs. 
But in any event, that sense of moral responsibility for the package they buy 
does not strike me as at all unreasonable. They are contracting with the 
insurer, and paying the insurer, to assume a contractual obligation to pay for 
contraception, emergency contraception, and (I think) sterilization. 

And of course, many of these plans are self-insured. In those cases, the 
connection is even more direct; the employer is commiting itself to pay for 
these services whenever asked, and it is paying for them.

 

On Mon, 1 Oct 2012 20:28:06 -0400
 Marty Lederman lederman.ma...@gmail.com wrote:
Thanks for the clarification, Doug.  I had missed that particular part of
the exchange.

On the distinction you suggest, I think that the characterization of the
requirement as purchasing a package of services does not fairly describe
what's going on here.  Or at the very least, this is nothing like what
comes to mind when one hears that phrase -- such as the employer hiring a
contractor to paint the walls, install new fixtures, etc.

The Rule requires the employer to *make available* to its employees a group
health plan.  (In fact, not even that -- the employer can instead make a
payment to the government, a payment that Robin Wilson suggested at our
Conference would typically be much *less* than the cost of the employer's
portion of the plan premiums.)  The law does not even require the employer
to pay premiums into the plan, although that might end up being a practical
necessity, since the plan must be one that is affordable to the
employees, which in most cases will presumably not include a plan
subsidized entirely by employee premiums.

So let's assume for sake of argument that as a practical matter the Rule
requires employers to pay a certain premium to the insurance company.  (I'm
putting aside here the serious question of whether the alternative payment
to the Fed changes the burden analysis.)  That premium does not pay for a
package of services *to the employer*.  It pays to partly subsidize (in
part) an enormously wide range of goods and services -- virtually any
related to health -- that will be used only if and when the employees need
them and choose to use them.  (And even then, the employer will never know
which services were used.)

That feels to me quite a bit different from an employer purchasing a
package of services.  Imagine, for instance, that the Rule instead
required employers to pay the same amount of money to a *government* *agency
* (rather than to a private insurance company) for the specific purpose of
funding a government-provided health insurance plan . . . a plan that works
*exactly like the plans in question here*, covering the exact same goods
and services, including contraceptive services.

In the case of such a Medicare tax -- one that these same employers
probably pay currently -- would you describe it as the employer being
forced to purchase a package of services?  Would Catholic employers claim
that it forces them to cooperate with evil in a way that their religion
forbids?



Douglas Laycock
Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Virginia Law School
580 Massie Road
Charlottesville, VA  22903
 434-243-8546
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.