List, Mary,

 

Lowell 2.14 introduces the spot (which must not be confused with either the
dot or the blot!), and in this connection is worth comparing with MS 439,
the third of the Cambridge Lectures of 1898 (RLT 146-164, NEM4 331-46). In
this lecture given five years before Lowell 2, Peirce began with a sketch of
his "categories" (Firstness, Secondness and Thirdness), then applied them to
formal logic (more specifically to the "Logic of Relatives"), which he then
explained "by means of Existential Graphs, which is the easiest method for
the unmathematical" (or so he claimed - RLT 151). In this post I'll include
two paragraphs from that 1898 lecture. First, from RLT 154:

 

 

Any part of a graph which only needs to have lines of identity attached to
it to become a complete graph, signifying an assertion, I call a verb. The
places at which lines of identity can be attached to the verb I call its
blank subjects. I distinguish verbs according to the numbers of their
subject blanks, as medads, monads, dyads, triads, etc. A medad, or
impersonal verb, is a complete assertion, like "It rains," "you are a good
girl." A monad, or neuter verb, needs only one subject to make it a complete
assertion, as 

-obeys mamma 
you obey-

A dyad, or simple active verb, needs just two subjects to complete the
assertion as 

-obeys- 
or -is identical with-

A triad needs just three subjects as 

-gives-to- 
-obeys both-and-

 

 

The main difference between this and Lowell 2 is the terminology: what
Peirce calls a "verb" here is called a "spot," "rheme" or "predicate" in the
Lowell lectures. (Compare the usage of "rheme" in the semiotic trichotomy
rheme/dicisign/argument as given in the Syllabus, EP2:292 or CP 2.250.) The
"subject blank" or "line of identity" here represents the individual
"subject of force," as does the "heavy dot" in Lowell 2, where the sheet of
assertion represents "the aggregate" of those "subjects of the complexus of
experience-forces well-understood between the graphist, or he who scribes
the graph, and the interpreter of it."

 

The other paragraph which I'll quote from the Cambridge lecture (RLT 155-6)
relates the existential graph system both to semiotics and to the Peircean
"categories" - and I think these relations also hold in the Lowell
presentation of the graphs. Notice here that the line of identity is classed
among "verbs" here, although the ends of the line (the "dots" of Lowell 2)
represent "individual objects" which would be the "subjects" of the "verbs"
in the graph. As a verb, though, all the line of identity can mean is "is
identical with," its subjects being those ends, which in Lowell 2 occupy the
"hooks" of the "spots."

 

 

In the system of graphs may be remarked three kinds of signs of very
different natures. First, there are the verbs, of endless variety. Among
these is the line signifying identity. But, second, the ends of the line of
identity (and every verb ought to [be] conceived as having such loose ends)
are signs of a totally different kind. They are demonstrative pronouns,
indicating existing objects, not necessarily material things, for they may
be events, or even qualities, but still objects, merely designated as this
or that. In the third place the writing of verbs side by side, and the ovals
enclosing graphs not asserted but subjects of assertion, which last is
continually used in mathematics and makes one of the great difficulties of
mathematics, constitute a third, entirely different kind of sign. Signs of
the first kind represent objects in their firstness, and give the
significations of the terms. Signs of the second kind represent objects as
existing,- and therefore as reacting,- and also in their reactions. They
contribute the assertive character to the graph. Signs of the third kind
represent objects as representative, that is in their Thirdness, and upon
them turn all the inferential processes. In point of fact, it was
considerations about the categories which taught me how to construct the
system of graphs. 

 

 

One last comment: the usage of the word "individual" in logic can be
confusing, but Peirce's definition of the term in Baldwin's Dictionary -
http://gnusystems.ca/BaldwinPeirce.htm#Individual -is helpful for
understanding Peirce's usage.

 

Gary f.

 


Sent: 23-Nov-17 16:38



Continuing from Lowell 2.13,

https://fromthepage.com/jeffdown1/c-s-peirce-manuscripts/ms-455-456-1903-low
ell-lecture-ii/display/13620

 

You will ask me what use I propose to make of this sign that something
exists, a fact that graphist and interpreter took for granted at the outset.
I will show you that the sign will be useful as long as we agree that
although different points on the sheet may denote the same individual, yet
different individuals cannot be denoted by the same point on the sheet. 

 

If we take any proposition, say 

A sinner kills a saint

and if we erase portions of it, so as to leave it a blank form of
proposition, the blanks being such that if every one of them is filled with
a proper name, a proposition will result, such as 

______ kills a saint 
A sinner kills ______ 
______ kills ______

where Cain and Abel might for example fill the blanks, then such a blank
form, as well as the complete proposition, is called a rheme (provided it be
neither [by] logical necessity true of everything nor true of nothing, but
this limitation may be disregarded). If it has one blank it is called a
monad rheme, if two a dyad, if three a triad, if none a medad (from μηδέν). 

 

Now such a rheme being neither logically necessary nor logically impossible,
as a [part of ?] a graph without being represented as a combination by any
of the signs of the system, is called a lexis and each replica of the lexis
is called a spot. (Lexis is the Greek for a single word and a lexis in this
system corresponds to a single verb in speech. The plural of lexis is
preferably lexeis rather than lexises.) 

 

Such a spot has a particular point on its periphery appropriated to each and
every one of its blanks. Those points, which, you will observe, are mere
places, and are not marked, are called the hooks of the spot. But if a
marked point, which we have agreed shall assert the existence of an
individual, be put in that place which is a hook of a graph, it must assert
that some thing is the corresponding individual whose name might fill the
blank of the rheme. 

 

Thus 

. gives . to . in exchange for .

will mean "something gives something to something in exchange for
something." 

 

http://gnusystems.ca/Lowell2.htm }{ Peirce's Lowell Lectures of 1903

https://fromthepage.com/jeffdown1/c-s-peirce-manuscripts/ms-455-456-1903-low
ell-lecture-ii

 

-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to