Jon S, List,

JD:  In order to interpret "μ is the surrender by A of B" and "ν is the 
acquisition by A of D" as triadic and not merely dyadic relations, my hunch is 
that he is considering these actions as intentional in character.

JS:  Maybe, but then how would you restate them as explicitly having three 
correlates, perhaps by presenting each as an EG?  And would they then be 
genuine or degenerate triadic relations?

JD: The relation of surrendering, considered as formally ordered dynamical 
dyadic relation, is a relation that can be expressed in the beta system of the 
EG. If μ is understood to involve an intention on the part of A, then it can't 
be expressed in those terms. In the Prolegomena, Peirce uses the modal tincture 
of Fur as a means of expressing intentions in the gamma system. The pattern of 
ermine (or the color yellow), is used to represent iconically that the area 
shaded expresses an intention on the part of the agent (see Don Roberts, 
92-102). Understanding the character of the triadic relations that hold between 
the areas that are patterned or shaded one way to the other areas of the graph 
is not a simple matter. Hence the difficulties of sorting out the modal 
relations using the tinctures (or colors). In his monograph, Don Roberts 
attempts to revise the tinctures in order to overcome some of the concerns that 
Peirce raised about this manner of expressing modal relations in the gamma 
system. Given the complexities involved, I won't try to answer the question of 
whether the triadic relations involved are genuine or degenerate in some 
respects.

JD:  The case that you cite of an object being sold involves a transfer of 
money and a contract. The simpler case of exchange as barter with no contract 
is illustrative of how other kinds of relations may be involved when more 
general things, such as property laws and legal systems, are governing the 
intentional acts.

JS: There is no reference to a contract in the initial proposition, "S sells T 
to B for M"; and it is isomorphic with the allegedly simpler case, "A gives up 
B to C in exchange for D."  In other words, it seems to me that "sells X for Y" 
is logically the same relation as "gives up X in exchange for Y."  Do you 
disagree?  Again, is an essential element somehow omitted if we analyze the 
tetradic relation of selling (or bartering) as a combination of only four 
triadic relations, two of giving (genuine) and two of exchanging (degenerate)?

JD: The initial description is underdetermined. The analysis he provides shows 
that Peirce was thinking of a transfer involving money and a contract, which 
means that the transfer was not simultaneous. Barter, as a form of exchange, is 
often simultaneous. When it is, that makes the exchange considerably simpler in 
character. That is one reason that exchange by barter may have preceded the 
development of formal systems of law.

JD:  How many triadic relations are involved in this process of a young child 
learning? Well, it appears to grow according to a power law. As such, it grows 
into a multitude that exceeds any system of numbers that is numerable or even 
any system that is abnumerable.

JS: Of course it does, because real semeiosis is continuous--it is not composed 
of discrete relations (prescinded predicates) and their discrete correlates 
(abstracted subjects) as expressed in definite propositions; those are all 
artificial creations of thought for the purposes of description and analysis.

JD:  It does not follow from the simple fact that the analyses involve entia 
rationis that such creations of the mind may not represent something real. 
Notice how Peirce puts the point. In a tetradic relation, there are at most 10 
triadic relations involved, whereas in a pentadic relation, there are at most 
100 triadic relations involved. It does not follow from the claim that semiosis 
is continuous that there are, somehow, an unlimited number of triadic relations 
involved. Inserting a real triadic relation where, before, one was only a 
potentiality, can be done any number of times. In doing so, however, you've 
made a new relation.

Yours,

Jeff
<http://twitter.com/JonAlanSchmidt>

On Fri, May 10, 2019 at 10:44 PM Jeffrey Brian Downard 
<jeffrey.down...@nau.edu<mailto:jeffrey.down...@nau.edu>> wrote:

Jon S., List,

My strategy for interpreting these passages is to take Peirce at his word when 
he refers to the triadic relations that are involved. In order to interpret "μ 
is the surrender by A of B" and "ν is the acquisition by A of D" as triadic and 
not merely dyadic relations, my hunch is that he is considering these actions 
as intentional in character. The object surrendered and the agent who 
surrenders it are existing individuals in the relation of agent and patient, 
but that existential description of the individuals is part of an intentional 
action by A. As a general sort of thing, the intention makes the action of 
surrendering triadic in character--and so too with the action of A acquiring 
object D.

The case that you cite of an object being sold involves a transfer of money and 
a contract. The simpler case of exchange as barter with no contract is 
illustrative of how other kinds of relations may be involved when more general 
things, such as property laws and legal systems, are governing the intentional 
acts. As a historical point, it is reasonable to suppose that social 
conventions governing exchanges by barter developed prior to any contracts or 
legal systems. Consequently, I think that the proper analysis of every genuine 
triadic relation involves a correlate that, itself, has the character of a 
general rule. As a correlate, that intention, or property law, or what have 
you, may involve a general rule that is part of a larger system of rules (such 
as a legal system).

Having said that, the reason the number of triadic relations involved in 
tetradic, pentadic and higher order relations goes up by a power of 10 is not 
obvious to me.  While it isn't obvious, here is a conjecture:  Peirce may be 
thinking about the operation of general laws and intentions as conforming to a 
general model that applies to all genuinely triadic relations.

One such model is articulated in "The Logic of Mathematics, an attempt to 
develop my categories from within". In that account of genuinely triadic 
relations, the law of quality and most general laws of fact each involves three 
clauses. The first clause governs each correlate considered in itself. The 
second clause governs the dyadic relations between pairs of correlates. The 
third clause governs the triadic relations between the three correlates. It is 
possible that the operation of the three clauses involved in such law might 
multiply the number of relations that may be involved in tetradic, pentadic, 
sextadic (etc.) relations by a power of ten in each case. The long explanations 
that he provides in this essay of the triadic relations that are part of the 
laws of space and the laws of physics may be illustrative of this general 
pattern.

Generalizing on these points, I think that the principles of logic that govern 
self-controlled acts of inference are, similarly, parts of larger systems of 
logical rules. Something as straightforward as the rule governing the first 
figure of the syllogism (the nota notae) is a rule that is related, as part of 
a larger logical system, to the principles of identity, non-contradiction, 
excluded middle, etc. The systematic connections that hold between the 
underlying laws of logic are probably richer and deeper than anything we are 
able to express in our little theories of logic (logica utens or logica 
docens).  As a result, the analysis of the triadic relations that are involved 
in a symbolic argument must take into account the relations that hold between 
the guiding principle of the inference and the other rules that are essential 
to inferences of that form. Peirce is offering an outline of how this might 
work in his explanation of the three clauses that are part of the general law 
of logic.

In order to explain how our conceptions of the laws of logic--conceived as 
principles that govern self-controlled acts of reasoning--might have evolved in 
the human species, Peirce considers the simple case of a child learning that 
hot stoves should not be touched. In "Faculties", "Consequences" and "Further 
Consequences," Peirce starts with the child forming a more or less deliberate 
intention to touch the stove. When the child learns that it is not possible for 
him to hold his hand on the stove, he learns that his parents were correct and 
his supposition was incorrect. As such, it looks like there is a strategy that 
may be at work, which is to explain how relatively simpler cases of intentional 
actions might later give rise to new conceptions--including a conception of the 
leading principle that governs the type of inferences that were involved in the 
learning about the stove.

Consequently, I think that some clarity could be achieved by applying the 
analysis of the triadic relations that are involved in progressively more 
complicated tetradic, pentadic, sextadic, etc. relations to simple 
examples--such as that of a child learning how to engage more or less 
self-controlled patterns of logical reasoning. My assumption is that the child 
was already capable of thinking in a manner that conformed to the laws of logic 
from an early age. The instinctive patterns of inference were not subject to 
much self-control at the ages of 1 and 2, but the child was learning how to use 
a conventional system of symbols (i.e., a natural language) as a matter of 
habit. In time, what the child learned was how to represent those laws to 
himself as principles. In turn, the child learned to recognise what those 
principles, functioning as imperatives, might require of him in terms of the 
future conduct of his inquiry.

How many triadic relations are involved in this process of a young child 
learning? Well, it appears to grow according to a power law. As such, it grows 
into a multitude that exceeds any system of numbers that is numerable or even 
any system that is abnumerable. The upshot of what I am suggesting is that 
Peirce's observation that there may be a power law involved in richer relations 
would explain his earlier assertions about the sort of infinity and resulting 
continuity that is involved in the growth of our cognitions.

Yours,

Jeff

Jeffrey Downard
Associate Professor
Department of Philosophy
Northern Arizona University
(o) 928 523-8354
-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to