Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-23 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Juho wrote:

Many of the criteria would be nice to have. One must however remember 
that often they have two sides. Winning something in some area may mean 
losing something in another area (e.g. the LNH property of IRV has been 
discussed widely on this list recently) especially when trying to fix 
the last remaining problems of the Condorcet methods. And if one assumes 
that strategic voting will not be meaningful in the planned elections 
then one should pay attention also to performance with sincere votes, 
not only to the resistance against strategies. Different elections may 
also have different requirements, so the question of which one of the 
methods is best may depend also on what kind of winner one wants to get 
(e.g. in some cases the best winner could be found outside the Smith set).


That's true. Some of the criteria are mutually exclusive, yet others are 
not. By picking criteria of worth, one might build a Pareto front: 
those methods on the front are those that fulfill as many criteria as 
possible subject to that some are mutually exclusive.


If we didn't forget notable criteria (and thus exclude from the Pareto 
front methods that by all means should be there), then the front 
provides the best methods we can get. It's up to one's judgement which 
of the criteria count more, i.e. which method on the Pareto front one 
should pick.


For convenience's sake, I've ignored the problem that criterion 
compliance might degrade the method's goodness when given honest 
votes, and that we don't know which criteria are mutually exclusive. For 
the former, we (E-M members) disagree about how to go about measuring 
how good results a method provides on honest votes, and for the latter, 
we can still build a Pareto front based on the methods we know so far - 
but it might be incomplete.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-23 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Kathy Dopp wrote:

Thanks Kristofer for the explanations.  Do you know a good place that
discusses the Ranked Pairs method of resolving cycles, or all the
methods of resolving cycles?  I would still like an example of  a
spoiler in Condorcet no matter how unlikely if possible.  Thank you.


Wikipedia explains Ranked Pairs well enough: 
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ranked_Pairs


It doesn't explain River, because that method is less known. In both 
Ranked Pairs and River, you first sort the majorities (A beats B) by 
magnitude, greatest first.
In Ranked Pairs, you then go down the list, locking majorities except 
those that lead to a contradiction with what you've already locked (e.g. 
if you lock A beats B and B beats C, you can't lock C beats A), 
and at the end you have an ordering, and the candidate at the top of 
this ordering is the winner.
In River, you do the same, except that you're also forbidden from 
locking a victory against someone who has already had a victory locked 
against him (e.g. A beats B, then you can't lock C beats B). The 
root of the tree diagram (base of the river) is the winner.


As for a spoiler in your terms, consider this very simple election 
(showing the Condorcet paradox):


10: ABC
10: BCA
11: CAB

If the method picks A, then B is a spoiler for C, because removing B 
leads C to win:


21: CA
10: AC

If the method picks B, then C is a spoiler for A, because removing C 
leads A to win:


21: AB
10: BA

If the method picks C, then A is a spoiler for B, because removing A 
leads B to win:


20: BC
11: CB.

That should work for any election method that reduces to a majority vote 
when there are only two candidates, because, as I've shown, it doesn't 
matter which candidate is elected - you can still show there's a spoiler.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-23 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Juho wrote:

On Jan 22, 2010, at 12:05 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:


Jonathan Lundell wrote:

In that case it might be a good starting point to define spoiler,
so we know what we've found when we find it.
What's an example of an IRV spoiler who's not a pretty strong
candidate?


A very abstract concept of spoiler might be: denote f(X) the minimal 
number of ballot changes/additions required to make X the winner. Then 
a spoiler is a candidate with a high f-value relative to the number of 
ballots (thus hard to get to win), who, by his presence, still 
changes who wins.


Determining f(x) for the various candidates would be very hard, 
though, and one also runs into the question of what threshold to say 
above this f-value, spoiler, below it, not a spoiler.


Maybe one should add also the requirement that the spoiler makes the 
result worse from spoiler's or spoiler's supporters' point of view.


Yes, although that cannot be mechanically tested. For some very strange 
methods, it might be true that adding a candidate changes the winner to 
someone who everybody who voted for the winner ranked ahead of him, but 
that would be a very strange method indeed.


Another possible modification is not to require f(X) to be high. One 
would just see what would have happened with and without the spoiler. 
According to that definition also strong candidates (but not actual 
winners) could be spoilers. (Typically term spoiler refers to minor 
candidates since these discussions typically refer to a two-party 
set-up, but the corresponding scientific term might or might not be 
limited to minor candidates and/or this particular set-up.)


Then a spoiler is just a candidate whose presence shows IIA failure, 
subject to that this IIA failure must happen in first place (the winner 
changes, not lower in the ranking). The definition of IIA implies that 
the candidate (spoiler) can't be the winner.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-23 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Kathy Dopp wrote:

Jonathan,

Monotonicity is a mathematical concept that is fairly simple to
describe. There is non-decreasing monotonicity, strictly increasing
monotonicity, non-increasing monotonicity, etc.  Arrow describes the
concept re. elections fairly well in one of his fairness conditions.

IRV/STV are the only alternative voting methods I am aware of that
fail this monotonicity condition that Arrow's fairness condition
requires but I have not studied all alternative methods so there must
be others that fail Arrow's monotonicity criteria.  Plurality
elections do *not* fail this criteria which is why IRV/STV fail more
of Arrow's fairness criteria than plurality does.

The simplest way to state it in English is that the act of voting in
any one election should be monotonically increasing by giving the
voter the right to know that voting for a candidate always increases
that candidate's chances of winning holding all other things constant
(given the votes of other voters).  In other words, mathematically,
increasing the input or x value, always increases the output or y
value in a monotonically increasing function.


That could be interpreted in two ways. Do you mean that a voter adding a 
ballot that ranks A above B should not cause A to lose to B, or that if 
a ballot were replaced by one where A is moved further towards top rank, 
A shouldn't lose? Or both?


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-23 Thread Juho

On Jan 23, 2010, at 1:55 PM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:


Juho wrote:

On Jan 22, 2010, at 12:05 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

Jonathan Lundell wrote:

In that case it might be a good starting point to define spoiler,
so we know what we've found when we find it.
What's an example of an IRV spoiler who's not a pretty strong
candidate?


A very abstract concept of spoiler might be: denote f(X) the  
minimal number of ballot changes/additions required to make X the  
winner. Then a spoiler is a candidate with a high f-value relative  
to the number of ballots (thus hard to get to win), who, by his  
presence, still changes who wins.


Determining f(x) for the various candidates would be very hard,  
though, and one also runs into the question of what threshold to  
say above this f-value, spoiler, below it, not a spoiler.
Maybe one should add also the requirement that the spoiler makes  
the result worse from spoiler's or spoiler's supporters' point of  
view.


Yes, although that cannot be mechanically tested. For some very  
strange methods, it might be true that adding a candidate changes  
the winner to someone who everybody who voted for the winner ranked  
ahead of him, but that would be a very strange method indeed.


Yes. And there are also situations where some of the supporters of the  
spoiler are happy with the changes but some are not. A theoretical  
definition of the spoiler property might require all supporters to be  
unhappy (if simpler that way).


I was thinking also about methods like Borda where in 60: AB, 40: BA  
A wins but addition of B2 (= 60: ABB2, 40: BB2A) means that B  
wins. B2 in a way spoils the election in general (and from A point of  
view) but from B point of view B2 saves the election. B and B2 are  
maybe from the same party but B2 is just worse. The B party may make  
the decision on if B2 will be nominated as a candidate (not the A  
party (that would spoil the election from their point of view if they  
did so)).




Another possible modification is not to require f(X) to be high.  
One would just see what would have happened with and without the  
spoiler. According to that definition also strong candidates (but  
not actual winners) could be spoilers. (Typically term spoiler  
refers to minor candidates since these discussions typically refer  
to a two-party set-up, but the corresponding scientific term might  
or might not be limited to minor candidates and/or this particular  
set-up.)


Then a spoiler is just a candidate whose presence shows IIA failure,  
subject to that this IIA failure must happen in first place (the  
winner changes, not lower in the ranking). The definition of IIA  
implies that the candidate (spoiler) can't be the winner.


...plus the spoiling (not just changing) requirement.

Juho






Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-23 Thread Kathy Dopp
Thanks again Kristofer for the explanations.  Terrific.

On Sat, Jan 23, 2010 at 10:41 AM,
election-methods-requ...@lists.electorama.com wrote:
 From: Kristofer Munsterhjelm km-el...@broadpark.no
 To: kathy.d...@gmail.com

 Kathy Dopp wrote:
 Thanks Kristofer for the explanations.  Do you know a good place that
 discusses the Ranked Pairs method of resolving cycles, or all the
 methods of resolving cycles?  I would still like an example of  a
 spoiler in Condorcet no matter how unlikely if possible.  Thank you.

 Wikipedia explains Ranked Pairs well enough:
 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ranked_Pairs

 It doesn't explain River, because that method is less known. In both
 Ranked Pairs and River, you first sort the majorities (A beats B) by
 magnitude, greatest first.
 In Ranked Pairs, you then go down the list, locking majorities except
 those that lead to a contradiction with what you've already locked (e.g.
 if you lock A beats B and B beats C, you can't lock C beats A),
 and at the end you have an ordering, and the candidate at the top of
 this ordering is the winner.
 In River, you do the same, except that you're also forbidden from
 locking a victory against someone who has already had a victory locked
 against him (e.g. A beats B, then you can't lock C beats B). The
 root of the tree diagram (base of the river) is the winner.

 As for a spoiler in your terms, consider this very simple election
 (showing the Condorcet paradox):

 10: ABC
 10: BCA
 11: CAB

 If the method picks A, then B is a spoiler for C, because removing B
 leads C to win:

 21: CA
 10: AC

 If the method picks B, then C is a spoiler for A, because removing C
 leads A to win:

 21: AB
 10: BA

 If the method picks C, then A is a spoiler for B, because removing A
 leads B to win:

 20: BC
 11: CB.

 That should work for any election method that reduces to a majority vote
 when there are only two candidates, because, as I've shown, it doesn't
 matter which candidate is elected - you can still show there's a spoiler.


 Maybe one should add also the requirement that the spoiler makes the
 result worse from spoiler's or spoiler's supporters' point of view.

 Yes, although that cannot be mechanically tested. For some very strange
 methods, it might be true that adding a candidate changes the winner to
 someone who everybody who voted for the winner ranked ahead of him, but
 that would be a very strange method indeed.

 Another possible modification is not to require f(X) to be high. One
 would just see what would have happened with and without the spoiler.
 According to that definition also strong candidates (but not actual
 winners) could be spoilers. (Typically term spoiler refers to minor
 candidates since these discussions typically refer to a two-party
 set-up, but the corresponding scientific term might or might not be
 limited to minor candidates and/or this particular set-up.)

 Then a spoiler is just a candidate whose presence shows IIA failure,
 subject to that this IIA failure must happen in first place (the winner
 changes, not lower in the ranking). The definition of IIA implies that
 the candidate (spoiler) can't be the winner.


 From: Kristofer Munsterhjelm km-el...@broadpark.no
 To: kathy.d...@gmail.com

 As a note: some methods (most discussed here, actually) also permit both
 truncation and equal-ranking. If one takes that into account, the
 formulas become more complex still.

 Yet, on another level, this may not really matter. On the one hand, if

From an election administration and public verifiability of the
outcomes point of view, the complexity always matters.

 there'll ever just be a few candidates, the amount of information to
 transmit is managable. On the other, setting a hard limit to, say, no
 more than 5 candidates may participate in this election is rather
 inelegant, and I would say, unfair, and if the potential number of
 candidates can grow to any number, it doesn't matter what formula is
 being used as long as it's superpolynomial (and so the values grow very
 large very quickly). Truncation or no truncation, equal rank or not, the
 number of unique orderings grow in that manner.

 From: Kristofer Munsterhjelm km-el...@broadpark.no
 To: kathy.d...@gmail.com

 Monotonicity is a mathematical concept that is fairly simple to
 describe. There is non-decreasing monotonicity, strictly increasing
 monotonicity, non-increasing monotonicity, etc.  Arrow describes the
 concept re. elections fairly well in one of his fairness conditions.

 IRV/STV are the only alternative voting methods I am aware of that
 fail this monotonicity condition that Arrow's fairness condition
 requires but I have not studied all alternative methods so there must
 be others that fail Arrow's monotonicity criteria.  Plurality
 elections do *not* fail this criteria which is why IRV/STV fail more
 of Arrow's fairness criteria than plurality does.

 The simplest way to state it in English is that the act of voting in
 any one election 

Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-22 Thread Terry Bouricius
Kathy,

Arrow never uses the word spoiler in his theorem (original nor revised 
version). You may be thinking about his independence of irrelevant 
alternatives (IIA) criterion. While this could be expanded to have some 
bearing on the concept of spoilers, it is not the same thing. Firstly, 
Arrow used IIA (as well as Pareto consistency and non-dictatorship) as 
desirable characteristics of a social ranking of options, not finding a 
single winner (or winning set). having a vote processing algorithm ignore 
rankings of irrelevant options, is not the same as ignoring non-winning 
options. Arrow himself gave examples of irrelevant options such as, an 
option that was not available at all (such as instantaneous teleportation, 
when establishing a social ordering of transportation options), or in the 
case of an election, a person who was not a candidate at all, or a 
candidate who died between the time ballots are cast, and tallied. While 
some election method experts may choose to give a broader interpretation 
of IIA by including non-winning candidates, Kathy, don't claim validity 
by pretending to cite Arrow for your non-standard definition of spoiler, 
which he never used.

Terry Bouricius

- Original Message - 
From: Kathy Dopp kathy.d...@gmail.com
To: Terry Bouricius ter...@burlingtontelecom.net
Cc: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
Sent: Friday, January 22, 2010 12:03 AM
Subject: Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected


Start telling the truth about IRV at Fairytale Vote, and then when
people speak the truth about Fairytale Vote, it won't sound like a
smear.

If you don't like the sound of your own behavior when retold, try some
different behavior, rather than falsely accusing others of smearing
you when they tell the truth. The list of deliberate misinformation
told by the Fairytale Vote group, if put together in one place, would
reach to the moon most likely, as this one youtube video alludes to.
Experts in election methods have had occasions to debunk the
disinformation by Fairytale Vote sufficiently to know that.

http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=bPCS-zWuel8

So continue to alter the definitions of commonly used words in order
to make yourself right because that's the only way you can do that
Terry.

Your definition of spoiler alters the definition that was given by
Arrow's theorem which is the one I choose to use, not the narrower one
your organization uses in order to make the false claim that IRV
solves the spoiler problem even though it obviously does not, and the
Republican candidate acted as a spoiler to knock out the most popular
Democratic candidate so that their least favorite, the left wing
Progressive could win.

Terry, just do not imagine that people do not see the trick you use
of redefining words that have had a common meaning for decades.

Cheers,
Kathy



On Thu, Jan 21, 2010 at 8:58 PM, Terry Bouricius
ter...@burlingtontelecom.net wrote:
 Kathy,

 I ask that you stop smearing me on this (and other) discussion lists. I
 did not alter any standard definition of spoilers. Webster's online 
 for
 example defines it as:
 1. A candidate with no chance of winning but who may draw enough votes 
 to
 prevent one of the leading candidates from winning.


 This means a spoiler is a non-leading candidate with almost no chance of
 winning (I think the term minor is a fair way of stating that 
 concisely)
 and not one of the leading candidates. Note also that the concept of
 having a chance to win suggests the term can be applied prospectively,
 prior to knowing what the ballots reveal. Kurt Wright, being perceived 
 as
 a likely winners and who was in first place in the initial tally had an
 EXCELLENT chance of winning, and almost did in the runoff, and thus does
 not meet the standard definition of a spoiler.

 I will refrain from the majority discussion, as that is off topic.

 Terry Bouricius

 - Original Message -
 From: Kathy Dopp kathy.d...@gmail.com
 To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
 Sent: Thursday, January 21, 2010 4:32 PM
 Subject: Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected


 From: Terry Bouricius ter...@burlingtontelecom.net
 To: Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com, Juho
 juho4...@yahoo.co.uk

 Jonathan makes an important point. The term spoiler means a minor
 candidate with a small percentage of the vote, who changes which of the
 other candidates wins by running. But Kathy and some others wish to
 expand
 the definition to include a front-runner. (Note that these IRV 
 opponents
 refer to the top plurality vote-getter who narrowly lost the runoff in
 Burlington, Kurt Wright, as a spoiler who prevented the candidate in
 third place from winning. This is a dynamic worthy of analysis, but the
 word spoiler is never used by the media or political scientists when
 describing the plurality leader.

 Terry Bouricius


 Thanks for all the information re. Condorcet cycles and the unlikely
 cases of spoilers in Condorcet

Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-22 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Jan 22, 2010, at 5:32 AM, Kathy Dopp wrote:

 On Fri, Jan 22, 2010 at 12:55 AM, Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com wrote:
 
 Arrow never used, never mind defined, the word spoiler.
 
 
 
 That is true. Back in Arrow's day,

Back in Arrow's day? Like, um, today?

 the word spoiler was not used, but
 Arrow exactly and broadly describes the spoiler condition as one of
 his fairness criteria.  

Arrow defines IIA precisely. 

Spoiler, on the other hand, is a word in casual English defined, as are most 
such words, by its usage, which is generally a candidate with little or no 
chance of winning who affects the outcome negatively relative to their 
supporters' preferences--a restricted, somewhat fuzzy, subset of IIA violations.


 Study this to understand and was easy to find
 using google on Arrow's Fairness Criteria
 
 http://www.ctl.ua.edu/math103/Voting/whatdowe.htm#The%20Independence%20of%20Irrelevant%20Alternatives%20Criterion
 
 This reminds me of one of the plethora of other deliberately
 misleading claims of Fairytale Vote

Stop. You're killing me. 

 , they constantly cite Arrow's
 theorem as if that is a logical reason to support IRV when IRV fails
 more of Arrow's Fairness criteria than even plurality voting does
 because IRV fails the nonmonotoncity criteria in addition to the
 spoiler criteria described above which both IRV and plurality fail.
 
 Fairytale Vote might be able to fool some of the people all the time,
 but cannot fool all of the people all of the time like it would like
 to.  Fairytale Vote redefines the spoiler condition to be only
 spoilers (nonwinning candidates whose presence in the election change
 who would otherwise win) who have small support among voters --
 another very clever trick on their part to mislead the public into
 thinking that IRV is an improvement over plurality, even though it is
 much much worse and deprives voters of fundamental fairness and voting
 rights and eviscerates the ability of the public to oversee the
 integrity and accuracy of election outcomes.



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-22 Thread Kathy Dopp
I meant back in the days when Arrow came up with his theorem
concerning rank choice votes failing at least one of his fairness
criteria. (IRV fails more of Arrow's fairness criteria than plurality
and fails more of Arrow's criteria than all other alternative methods
I've heard recommended.)

Arrow, Kenneth J. (1951). Social Choice and Individual Values. Wiley,
New York. ISBN 0-300-01364-7.  2nd ed. 1963

Back in 1951, although I see he has republished his book as late as 1963.

Thassal. spoiler was not a common word back then. However nowadays
most people think of a spoiler, just like Arrow's fairness criteria
does, as a nonwinning candidate who spoils the election by causing a
different candidate (less popular candidate) to win due to his
presence in the election -- just like happened due to using IRV in
Burlington's last mayoral election where Republican voters were fooled
into thinking that their votes wouldn't be wasted and that they
could vote sincerely and other Fairytales spread by the misnomered
Fair Vote in order to promote IRV which eviscerates the ability of the
public to oversee electoral integrity in addition to eviscerating
voter rights and fairness.

Fairytale Vote has truly been one of the most successful misleaders on
the facts in recent years.

Cheers,

Kathy



On Fri, Jan 22, 2010 at 10:46 AM, Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com wrote:
 On Jan 22, 2010, at 5:32 AM, Kathy Dopp wrote:

 On Fri, Jan 22, 2010 at 12:55 AM, Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com 
 wrote:

 Arrow never used, never mind defined, the word spoiler.



 That is true. Back in Arrow's day,

 Back in Arrow's day? Like, um, today?

 the word spoiler was not used, but
 Arrow exactly and broadly describes the spoiler condition as one of
 his fairness criteria.

 Arrow defines IIA precisely.

 Spoiler, on the other hand, is a word in casual English defined, as are 
 most such words, by its usage, which is generally a candidate with little or 
 no chance of winning who affects the outcome negatively relative to their 
 supporters' preferences--a restricted, somewhat fuzzy, subset of IIA 
 violations.


 Study this to understand and was easy to find
 using google on Arrow's Fairness Criteria

 http://www.ctl.ua.edu/math103/Voting/whatdowe.htm#The%20Independence%20of%20Irrelevant%20Alternatives%20Criterion

 This reminds me of one of the plethora of other deliberately
 misleading claims of Fairytale Vote

 Stop. You're killing me.

 , they constantly cite Arrow's
 theorem as if that is a logical reason to support IRV when IRV fails
 more of Arrow's Fairness criteria than even plurality voting does
 because IRV fails the nonmonotoncity criteria in addition to the
 spoiler criteria described above which both IRV and plurality fail.

 Fairytale Vote might be able to fool some of the people all the time,
 but cannot fool all of the people all of the time like it would like
 to.  Fairytale Vote redefines the spoiler condition to be only
 spoilers (nonwinning candidates whose presence in the election change
 who would otherwise win) who have small support among voters --
 another very clever trick on their part to mislead the public into
 thinking that IRV is an improvement over plurality, even though it is
 much much worse and deprives voters of fundamental fairness and voting
 rights and eviscerates the ability of the public to oversee the
 integrity and accuracy of election outcomes.






-- 

Kathy Dopp

Town of Colonie, NY 12304
phone 518-952-4030
cell 518-505-0220

http://utahcountvotes.org
http://electionmathematics.org
http://kathydopp.com/serendipity/

Realities Mar Instant Runoff Voting
http://electionmathematics.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf

Voters Have Reason to Worry
http://utahcountvotes.org/UT/UtahCountVotes-ThadHall-Response.pdf

Checking election outcome accuracy --- Post-election audit sampling
http://electionmathematics.org/em-audits/US/PEAuditSamplingMethods.pdf

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-22 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Jan 22, 2010, at 7:57 AM, Kathy Dopp wrote:

 I meant back in the days when Arrow came up with his theorem
 concerning rank choice votes failing at least one of his fairness
 criteria. (IRV fails more of Arrow's fairness criteria than plurality
 and fails more of Arrow's criteria than all other alternative methods
 I've heard recommended.)
 
 Arrow, Kenneth J. (1951). Social Choice and Individual Values. Wiley,
 New York. ISBN 0-300-01364-7.  2nd ed. 1963
 
 Back in 1951, although I see he has republished his book as late as 1963.

And I have a copy on my desk.

He's been continuously publishing, with papers published in 2008 and 2009. None 
of them contain the word spoiler.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-22 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Jan 22, 2010, at 7:19 AM, Terry Bouricius wrote:

 Arrow never uses the word spoiler in his theorem (original nor revised 
 version). You may be thinking about his independence of irrelevant 
 alternatives (IIA) criterion. While this could be expanded to have some 
 bearing on the concept of spoilers, it is not the same thing. Firstly, 
 Arrow used IIA (as well as Pareto consistency and non-dictatorship) as 
 desirable characteristics of a social ranking of options, not finding a 
 single winner (or winning set).

It's a point worth keeping in mind. We toss Arrow's Possibility Theorem around 
pretty loosely, when strictly speaking we should be talking about 
Gibbard-Satterthwaite, or (better yet) Duggan-Schwartz.

There are, of course, family resemblances.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-22 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 12:03 AM 1/22/2010, Kathy Dopp wrote:


Terry, just do not imagine that people do not see the trick you use
of redefining words that have had a common meaning for decades.


The biggest is majority, which has been redefined to mean something 
very different, which is then justified on a bogus analogy with real runoffs.
majority has always been shorthand for containing a vote from a 
majority of ballots cast in an election, but this gets slipped into 
majority of ballots containing a vote for one of the top two 
remaining after eliminations.


And the dirty little secret is that in most elections where there is 
no majority in first preference, i.e., when the sequential 
elimination retabulation is done, there is no majority -- real 
majority of *voters* -- after retabulation.


If the Robert's Rules method is followed, the elimination continues 
one more step in that case, to find if there is a majority of votes 
who have ranked the candidate instead of refusing to vote for the 
candidate. Education on IRV doesn't say, unfortunately, that ranking 
a candidate is a form of vote for the candidate, and many or most 
voters imagine that ranking a candidate last is a vote against the 
candidate. Because it is actually a vote for the candidate against 
all the write-ins or minor candidates who can't be ranked, if the 
ranking is eliminated.


No, if you want to vote against a candidate without taking a stand on 
every possible write-in, don't rank the candidate at all.


That's why this majority redefinition is so pernicious; without 
realizing it, voters approving IRV have eliminated a majority 
requirement without being aware of it, having bought the propaganda 
that IRV guarantees a majority result. Top two runoff does 
guarantee a majority result (if write-ins are not allowed; if they 
are, it's possible for majority failure to occur, though rare).


The classic case is in San Francisco, where the voter information 
pamphlet panel gave a neutral description of the measure that 
claimed something like winners will be required to gain a majority 
of the votes.


It's very difficult to interpret that in a sane way to make it the 
truth, it's a deceptive statement, and it was, I'm sure, based on 
FairVote propaganda, and if the *accurate* statement had been made, 
the effect would have been very different.


Winning candidates will have gained more votes than the leading 
opponent after the rest of the candidates and ballots which don't 
rank them have been eliminated. Mathematically, this is a majority, 
not of the votes, but of votes remaining after all but two 
candidates are eliminated and the ballots not ranking those two are 
eliminated as well.


Will be required sounds like some standard which must be reached -- 
and thus which could fail -- and, since this redefined majority is 
a tautology, a mathematical construct of the method, that's deceptive.


As I've pointed out, use the Robert's Rules method of counting, which 
continues to the last elimination, not terminating when there are 
only two candidates left, but seeking to find a complete majority, 
and we could then make a parallel claim. Candidate must receive 
unanimous support from votes cast.


In Brown v. Smallwood, the Minnesota court noted, with approval, 
prior judgement in another state that wrote about the issue being a 
majority of voters rather than a majority of votes. Or was it 
plurality or language like that, I forget. It's too bad that they 
didn't follow what they apparently did not understand and failed to 
apply. Bucklin seeks to find a majority of *voters* who have approved 
a candidate. Not a majority of votes. The number of voters is the 
number of valid ballots. If the ballot is valid, votes on it are then 
considered, and if a majority is required, a winning threshold is 
established that then must be found or the election fails. Or the 
election is decided by plurality.


IRV, in every implementation so far in political elections, is being 
decided by plurality, in most of the elections that go to instant runoff.


But FairVote, even after all of this has been made abundantly clear, 
continues to promote the deceptive arguments, even if modified 
cleverly to make them not-exact-lies. That is, if you know the truth, 
you'd have to say that the FairVote propaganda is true, as to literal 
fact, but only deceptive as to impression created. And, of course, 
individual activists continue to promote the deceptive impression, 
probably not realizing that they are lying, or not caring. We will 
see that FairVote has turned the corner when it becomes willing to be 
fair. Thus Kathy's Fairytale Vote is quite on point. FairVote is 
selling false hopes, fairytales, based on a collection of 
misinformation and deceptive political argument, designed to play on 
voter ignorance of the complex issues of voting systems. And, long 
ago, Rob Richie indicated his contempt for the ivory-tower 
theorists who objected to his deceptions, on 

Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-22 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Jan 22, 2010, at 5:32 AM, Kathy Dopp wrote:

 This reminds me of one of the plethora of other deliberately
 misleading claims of Fairytale Vote, they constantly cite Arrow's
 theorem as if that is a logical reason to support IRV when IRV fails
 more of Arrow's Fairness criteria than even plurality voting does
 because IRV fails the nonmonotoncity criteria in addition to the
 spoiler criteria described above which both IRV and plurality fail.

 Arrow, Kenneth J. (1951). Social Choice and Individual Values. Wiley,
 New York. ISBN 0-300-01364-7.  2nd ed. 1963

Monotonicity, btw, doesn't appear as a criterion in Arrow's monograph on his 
Possibility Theorem, either.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-22 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 07:48 PM 1/21/2010, Kathy Dopp wrote:

On Thu, Jan 21, 2010 at 7:34 PM, Abd ul-Rahman Lomax
a...@lomaxdesign.com wrote:
 At 04:41 PM 1/21/2010, Jonathan Lundell wrote:

 On Jan 21, 2010, at 1:32 PM, Kathy Dopp wrote:

  Terry, You cleverly conveniently change all the definitions whenver it
  is necessary to make yourself and Fairytale Vote right on the facts.

 Define spoiler, please, unambiguously.

 The term has usage, and must be understood from that. A formal definition,
 nailing it down, would be arbitrary. But Kathy's definition is one
 reasonable one that matches common usage.

 But there is another which is broader and, to distinguish this from the

Abd ul, actually your definition below is *narrower* not broader,
because it narrows the number of cases that fit the definition.


That's correct. I wrote it backwards. Kathy is using the broader 
definition and my comment was confused, not in reality (that is, I 
wasn't confused myself) but in expression (I accidentally wrote it backwards).


To summarize, the IIA definition is broad (and fairly clear with pure 
preferential voting, though it gets muddy as hell when we try to 
apply it to methods allowing equal ranking), and the common political 
usage, which FairVote relies upon, doesn't think of the N-major 
candidates problem when N is greater than 2, because that is, in the 
U.S., a rare situation (in partisan elections). It's predictable, 
though, in Burlington.


In reality, both problems are serious. What I always called the 
first-order spoiler effect, to distinguish it from, say, center 
squeeze, however, only flips the result when the two leading 
candidates are close.


The second-order effect, where there are more than two major 
candidates, can flip a 2:1 result (pairwise) so that the 1/3 
candidate wins. I'd call that very serious.


And it is *roughly* what happened in Burlington. Single-winner IRV is 
insupportable in contexts where there are three major parties, all 
reasonbly viable. Plurality is better, because, then, at least, 
voters know what they are dealing with, and if the Progressive 
candidate there really wants to insist, he or she might indeed cause 
the Republican to win. It's called responsibility, a concept lost 
on Ralph Nader in 2000. Or, in fact, he believed his propaganda: 
there was no difference between Gore and Bush.


Really? Did you support Nader in 2000? Did you buy that argument? If 
you lived in Florida, where it was known to be a close election, and 
you voted for Nader, *you are responsible for what happened,* almost 
as much as those who voted for Bush. Call it half-responsible.


I understand and sympathize with the problem. But there are much 
better fixes than IRV. The simple, low-cost but not *fully 
satisfactory* option is just to count all the damn votes. Approval, it becomes.


But there is an obvious objection: if you supported Nader over Gore, 
you'd want to be able to express that. Hence a ranked approval method 
is actually quite on-point. And this was obvious a century ago, when 
it was tried extensively. Why was it stopped?


Well, why was IRV stopped in Ann Arbor, MI, immediately after an 
election where it's clear the IRV result (a Democratic mayor, the 
first black mayor in Ann Arbor history) was better than electing the 
Republican. Let's see ... who would benefit from dumping IRV there? 
Lucky guess. And they had the means to do it: arrange a special 
election to dump IRV at a point where the students were out of town. 
Ann Arbor is a college town, and the Human Rights Party, very popular 
with students, was splitting the vote. So IRV was dumped, and this 
had nothing to do with fairness, it was pure political maneuvering. 
And the Democrats and the Greens (which the HRP became) didn't have 
the balls to go back and pull the same trick, they didn't even try. 
My guess is that the Democrats didn't want to cooperate with the 
Greens, because if they had, they'd have had, collectively, a majority.


So the Democrats, my guess, are responsible for what happened in Ann 
Arbor, collectively with the Greens. Being in the majority doesn't 
help if the majority is internally divided and can't cooperate.


If the method in Burlington goes back to a plurality method, say, the 
same applies. Progressives and Democrats, get it together and you 
will win. If you are divided, *they* will win. And you are 
collectively responsible for that. 



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-22 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 08:58 PM 1/21/2010, Terry Bouricius wrote:

Kathy,
I will refrain from the majority discussion, as that is off topic.


It is very much on-topic. The spoiler effect is a problem because it 
can shift results from a true majority result to one actually opposed 
by a majority of voters. And this is the case with both versions of 
the spoiler effect, and it is why the spoiler effect is consider a 
harm. Eliminating one kind of spoiler effect, while leaving in place 
another which is actually more pernicious, as seen in Burlington, is foolish.



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-22 Thread Terry Bouricius
Jonathan,

Yes and no...You are correct that Arrow never uses the term 
monotonicity, but the concept is embodied in his second condition, 
called positive association.

Terry

- Original Message - 
From: Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com
To: kathy.d...@gmail.com
Cc: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
Sent: Friday, January 22, 2010 12:47 PM
Subject: Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected


On Jan 22, 2010, at 5:32 AM, Kathy Dopp wrote:

 This reminds me of one of the plethora of other deliberately
 misleading claims of Fairytale Vote, they constantly cite Arrow's
 theorem as if that is a logical reason to support IRV when IRV fails
 more of Arrow's Fairness criteria than even plurality voting does
 because IRV fails the nonmonotoncity criteria in addition to the
 spoiler criteria described above which both IRV and plurality fail.

 Arrow, Kenneth J. (1951). Social Choice and Individual Values. Wiley,
 New York. ISBN 0-300-01364-7.  2nd ed. 1963

Monotonicity, btw, doesn't appear as a criterion in Arrow's monograph on 
his Possibility Theorem, either.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-22 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Jan 22, 2010, at 10:30 AM, Terry Bouricius wrote:

 Jonathan,
 
 Yes and no...You are correct that Arrow never uses the term 
 monotonicity, but the concept is embodied in his second condition, 
 called positive association.

Yes--I'm talking about terminology merely (that, and that monotonicity itself 
needs definition in a particular context).

 
 Terry
 
 - Original Message - 
 From: Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com
 To: kathy.d...@gmail.com
 Cc: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
 Sent: Friday, January 22, 2010 12:47 PM
 Subject: Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected
 
 
 On Jan 22, 2010, at 5:32 AM, Kathy Dopp wrote:
 
 This reminds me of one of the plethora of other deliberately
 misleading claims of Fairytale Vote, they constantly cite Arrow's
 theorem as if that is a logical reason to support IRV when IRV fails
 more of Arrow's Fairness criteria than even plurality voting does
 because IRV fails the nonmonotoncity criteria in addition to the
 spoiler criteria described above which both IRV and plurality fail.
 
 Arrow, Kenneth J. (1951). Social Choice and Individual Values. Wiley,
 New York. ISBN 0-300-01364-7.  2nd ed. 1963
 
 Monotonicity, btw, doesn't appear as a criterion in Arrow's monograph on 
 his Possibility Theorem, either.
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-22 Thread Kathy Dopp
 From: Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com
 To: Terry Bouricius ter...@burlingtontelecom.net
 Cc: kathy.d...@gmail.com, election-methods@lists.electorama.com
 Subject: Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being
        subjected
 Message-ID: acf2480e-5c32-4678-8e29-500f743f5...@pobox.com
 Content-Type: text/plain; charset=us-ascii

 On Jan 22, 2010, at 10:30 AM, Terry Bouricius wrote:

 Jonathan,

 Yes and no...You are correct that Arrow never uses the term
 monotonicity, but the concept is embodied in his second condition,
 called positive association.

 Yes--I'm talking about terminology merely (that, and that monotonicity 
 itself needs definition in a particular context).


Jonathan,

Monotonicity is a mathematical concept that is fairly simple to
describe. There is non-decreasing monotonicity, strictly increasing
monotonicity, non-increasing monotonicity, etc.  Arrow describes the
concept re. elections fairly well in one of his fairness conditions.

IRV/STV are the only alternative voting methods I am aware of that
fail this monotonicity condition that Arrow's fairness condition
requires but I have not studied all alternative methods so there must
be others that fail Arrow's monotonicity criteria.  Plurality
elections do *not* fail this criteria which is why IRV/STV fail more
of Arrow's fairness criteria than plurality does.

The simplest way to state it in English is that the act of voting in
any one election should be monotonically increasing by giving the
voter the right to know that voting for a candidate always increases
that candidate's chances of winning holding all other things constant
(given the votes of other voters).  In other words, mathematically,
increasing the input or x value, always increases the output or y
value in a monotonically increasing function.

IRV/STV are the only methods I know that fail the monotonicity test
and thus deprive the voters the right to know what effect, positive or
negative, their ballot will have on the candidates the voter votes
for, but I'm sure there must be others.

And please do not repeat the BS about plurality failing monotonicity
because you incorrectly think of general and primary elections as
being one election, because in each plurality election the voter
retains the right to help the candidates of their choosing to win each
election, so a voter can knowingly strategize effectively if the voter
chooses to, unlike with IRV/STV where, for instance in the recent
Aspen election if 75 fewer voters had voted for one of the city
council members, he would have won instead of losing.  What an insane
voting method!

-- 

Kathy Dopp

Town of Colonie, NY 12304
phone 518-952-4030
cell 518-505-0220

http://utahcountvotes.org
http://electionmathematics.org
http://kathydopp.com/serendipity/

Realities Mar Instant Runoff Voting
http://electionmathematics.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf

Voters Have Reason to Worry
http://utahcountvotes.org/UT/UtahCountVotes-ThadHall-Response.pdf

Checking election outcome accuracy --- Post-election audit sampling
http://electionmathematics.org/em-audits/US/PEAuditSamplingMethods.pdf

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-21 Thread Juho

On Jan 21, 2010, at 9:29 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:


robert bristow-johnson wrote:
i think that the answer is no, if a Condorcet winner exists and  
that all bets are off if a CW does not exist, except, perhaps for  
these strategy-resistant methods such as Markus Schulze's  
method.  i sorta understand it, but since he hangs here, i think  
Markus should address the question if the Schulze method is spoiler  
free.


Most Condorcet related problems occur only when there is no Condorcet  
winner (i.e. there is a top level cycle in the group preferences).  
Sincere or artificially generated cycles are the root cause of both  
problems with sincere votes (e.g. spoiler related problems) and  
strategic voting related problems in Condorcet.


Different Condorcet methods (e.g. Ranked Pairs, Schiulze) are quite  
similar in the sense that the basic vulnerabilities of Condorcet  
methods exist in all of them (e.g. the basic burial scenarios). Their  
differences between the most common Condorcet methods are quite small  
in the sense that in real life elections they almost always elect the  
same candidate. Their differences are mostly related to how well they  
can resist strategic voting. Another point of view is to compare which  
method elects the best/correct winner with sincere votes.


What is good in all the common Condorcet methods is that their  
vulnerabilities to strategies (and their differences in general) may  
very well be so small in typical real elections (large, public, with  
independent voter decision making, with changing opinions and less  
than perfect poll information) that strategic voting will not be a  
problem. Also their differences with sincere votes (e.g. spoiler  
related problems) are quite small in real life elections.


Here's one simple spoiler related example as a response to Kathy  
Dopp's request.


35: ABC
33: BCA
32: CAB

I this example there are three candidates in a top level cycle. If any  
of the candidates would not run that would mean that there is a  
Condorcet winner, and that winner would be different in each case.  
Let's say that the method we use will pick A as the winner. If B would  
not run then the votes would be 35: AC, 33: CA, 32: CA and C would  
win. B is thus a spoiler from C's point of view.


I note however that these spoiler cases in Condorcet are not as common  
as in many of the other methods. In practice it may be that there is  
no need to worry about these cases. Maybe Kathy Dopp's comparisons  
will reveal something about how problematic the spoiler effect is or  
is not in Condorcet. Not also that in the example above B was not a  
minor party candidate (often term spoiler refers to minor candidates)  
but a pretty strong candidate.




MAM/Ranked Pairs is also pretty strategy-resistant and is easier to  
understand. Schulze has the advantage of producing better results in  
some cases (closer to Minmax), but if ability to describe to the  
public is important, then Ranked Pairs wins there.


Could someone please provide me with an example of the spoiler  
effect occuring with the Condorcet method  of counting rank choice  
ballots or tell me why the spoiler effect doesn't happen with  
Condorcet in  a few words?


(...)


i would say that (with the CW existing), it's spoiler-proof.


Yes. If there's a CW and a candidate is added, and that candidate  
doesn't create a cycle, then the winner doesn't change. All the  
tricky stuff happens when there is a cycle, or the candidate makes  
one.


The advanced methods can claim further resistance: Schulze and  
Ranked Pairs both make their winner decision independent of  
candidates not in the Smith set. River is independent of Pareto- 
dominated alternatives - a candidate is Pareto-dominated if  
everybody who ranks both him and some other (specific) candidate,  
rank the other candidate above him (e.g. X is Pareto-dominated by Y  
if all voters who rank both X and Y say YX, and there's at least  
one such voter).


I imagine these resistances would mostly come into play in smaller  
elections. Still, they're nice to have, and their existence  
immediately tells parties not to try exploiting certain weaknesses  
(because it won't work).


Yes, in small elections (with few voters only) it may be possible to  
know the opinions of each voter and agree about the applied strategy  
with the strategizing voters. In typical large real life elections  
many of the vulnerabilities are not practical and sincere voting may  
be the best strategy to most if not all voters.


Many of the criteria would be nice to have. One must however remember  
that often they have two sides. Winning something in some area may  
mean losing something in another area (e.g. the LNH property of IRV  
has been discussed widely on this list recently) especially when  
trying to fix the last remaining problems of the Condorcet methods.  
And if one assumes that strategic voting will not be meaningful in the  
planned 

Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-21 Thread Kathy Dopp
Thanks Kristofer for the explanations.  Do you know a good place that
discusses the Ranked Pairs method of resolving cycles, or all the
methods of resolving cycles?  I would still like an example of  a
spoiler in Condorcet no matter how unlikely if possible.  Thank you.

Kathy

On Thu, Jan 21, 2010 at 2:29 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm
km-el...@broadpark.no wrote:
 robert bristow-johnson wrote:

 i think that the answer is no, if a Condorcet winner exists and that all
 bets are off if a CW does not exist, except, perhaps for these
 strategy-resistant methods such as Markus Schulze's method.  i sorta
 understand it, but since he hangs here, i think Markus should address the
 question if the Schulze method is spoiler free.

 MAM/Ranked Pairs is also pretty strategy-resistant and is easier to
 understand. Schulze has the advantage of producing better results in some
 cases (closer to Minmax), but if ability to describe to the public is
 important, then Ranked Pairs wins there.

 Could someone please provide me with an example of the spoiler effect
 occuring with the Condorcet method  of counting rank choice ballots or tell
 me why the spoiler effect doesn't happen with Condorcet in  a few words?

 (...)

 i would say that (with the CW existing), it's spoiler-proof.

 Yes. If there's a CW and a candidate is added, and that candidate doesn't
 create a cycle, then the winner doesn't change. All the tricky stuff
 happens when there is a cycle, or the candidate makes one.

 The advanced methods can claim further resistance: Schulze and Ranked Pairs
 both make their winner decision independent of candidates not in the Smith
 set. River is independent of Pareto-dominated alternatives - a candidate is
 Pareto-dominated if everybody who ranks both him and some other (specific)
 candidate, rank the other candidate above him (e.g. X is Pareto-dominated by
 Y if all voters who rank both X and Y say YX, and there's at least one such
 voter).

 I imagine these resistances would mostly come into play in smaller
 elections. Still, they're nice to have, and their existence immediately
 tells parties not to try exploiting certain weaknesses (because it won't
 work).




-- 

Kathy Dopp

Town of Colonie, NY 12304
phone 518-952-4030
cell 518-505-0220

http://utahcountvotes.org
http://electionmathematics.org
http://kathydopp.com/serendipity/

Realities Mar Instant Runoff Voting
http://electionmathematics.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf

Voters Have Reason to Worry
http://utahcountvotes.org/UT/UtahCountVotes-ThadHall-Response.pdf

Checking election outcome accuracy --- Post-election audit sampling
http://electionmathematics.org/em-audits/US/PEAuditSamplingMethods.pdf

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-21 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Jan 21, 2010, at 1:03 AM, Juho wrote:

 What is good in all the common Condorcet methods is that their 
 vulnerabilities to strategies (and their differences in general) may very 
 well be so small in typical real elections (large, public, with independent 
 voter decision making, with changing opinions and less than perfect poll 
 information) that strategic voting will not be a problem. Also their 
 differences with sincere votes (e.g. spoiler related problems) are quite 
 small in real life elections.
 
 Here's one simple spoiler related example as a response to Kathy Dopp's 
 request.
 
 35: ABC
 33: BCA
 32: CAB
 
 I this example there are three candidates in a top level cycle. If any of the 
 candidates would not run that would mean that there is a Condorcet winner, 
 and that winner would be different in each case. Let's say that the method we 
 use will pick A as the winner. If B would not run then the votes would be 35: 
 AC, 33: CA, 32: CA and C would win. B is thus a spoiler from C's point of 
 view.
 
 I note however that these spoiler cases in Condorcet are not as common as in 
 many of the other methods. In practice it may be that there is no need to 
 worry about these cases. Maybe Kathy Dopp's comparisons will reveal something 
 about how problematic the spoiler effect is or is not in Condorcet. Not also 
 that in the example above B was not a minor party candidate (often term 
 spoiler refers to minor candidates) but a pretty strong candidate.

In that case it might be a good starting point to define spoiler, so we know 
what we've found when we find it.

What's an example of an IRV spoiler who's not a pretty strong candidate?

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-21 Thread robert bristow-johnson


well, since no one else responded...

On Jan 21, 2010, at 9:21 AM, Kathy Dopp wrote:


Thanks Kristofer for the explanations.  Do you know a good place that
discusses the Ranked Pairs method of resolving cycles, or all the
methods of resolving cycles?


Wikipedia.  maybe start with http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/ 
Voting_systems and see what you find from there.



  I would still like an example of  a
spoiler in Condorcet no matter how unlikely if possible.


the spoiler would have to either push a nicely resolved election with  
a CW into a cycle and have the cycle resolved so that the earlier CW  
does not win or, if the election was in a cycle in the first place  
(but resolved to pick some winner), the spoiler would have to cause  
the election algorithm to choose a different winner (and not the  
spoiler).


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected tothe spoiler effect if any

2010-01-21 Thread Terry Bouricius
Jonathan makes an important point. The term spoiler  means a minor 
candidate with a small percentage of the vote, who changes which of the 
other candidates wins by running. But Kathy and some others wish to expand 
the definition to include a front-runner. (Note that these IRV opponents 
refer to the top plurality vote-getter who narrowly lost the runoff in 
Burlington, Kurt Wright, as a spoiler who prevented the candidate in 
third place from winning. This is a dynamic worthy of analysis, but the 
word spoiler is never used by the media or political scientists when 
describing the plurality leader.

Terry Bouricius

- Original Message - 
From: Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com
To: Juho juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
Cc: EM Methods election-methods@lists.electorama.com
Sent: Thursday, January 21, 2010 10:33 AM
Subject: Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected 
tothe spoiler effect if any


On Jan 21, 2010, at 1:03 AM, Juho wrote:

 What is good in all the common Condorcet methods is that their 
 vulnerabilities to strategies (and their differences in general) may 
 very well be so small in typical real elections (large, public, with 
 independent voter decision making, with changing opinions and less than 
 perfect poll information) that strategic voting will not be a problem. 
 Also their differences with sincere votes (e.g. spoiler related 
 problems) are quite small in real life elections.

 Here's one simple spoiler related example as a response to Kathy Dopp's 
 request.

 35: ABC
 33: BCA
 32: CAB

 I this example there are three candidates in a top level cycle. If any 
 of the candidates would not run that would mean that there is a 
 Condorcet winner, and that winner would be different in each case. Let's 
 say that the method we use will pick A as the winner. If B would not run 
 then the votes would be 35: AC, 33: CA, 32: CA and C would win. B is 
 thus a spoiler from C's point of view.

 I note however that these spoiler cases in Condorcet are not as common 
 as in many of the other methods. In practice it may be that there is no 
 need to worry about these cases. Maybe Kathy Dopp's comparisons will 
 reveal something about how problematic the spoiler effect is or is not 
 in Condorcet. Not also that in the example above B was not a minor party 
 candidate (often term spoiler refers to minor candidates) but a pretty 
 strong candidate.

In that case it might be a good starting point to define spoiler, so we 
know what we've found when we find it.

What's an example of an IRV spoiler who's not a pretty strong candidate?

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-21 Thread Kathy Dopp
 From: Terry Bouricius ter...@burlingtontelecom.net
 To: Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com,    Juho
        juho4...@yahoo.co.uk

 Jonathan makes an important point. The term spoiler  means a minor
 candidate with a small percentage of the vote, who changes which of the
 other candidates wins by running. But Kathy and some others wish to expand
 the definition to include a front-runner. (Note that these IRV opponents
 refer to the top plurality vote-getter who narrowly lost the runoff in
 Burlington, Kurt Wright, as a spoiler who prevented the candidate in
 third place from winning. This is a dynamic worthy of analysis, but the
 word spoiler is never used by the media or political scientists when
 describing the plurality leader.

 Terry Bouricius


Thanks for all the information re. Condorcet cycles and the unlikely
cases of spoilers in Condorcet method of counting rank choice votes
from Juho and Robert.


Terry, You cleverly conveniently change all the definitions whenver it
is necessary to make yourself and Fairytale Vote right on the facts.
 Let's see what some of them are:

A spoiler is *not* according to you, a nonwinning candidate whose
presence in the election changes who would otherwise be the winner,
but only a particular type of spoiler that is a minor candidate.

A majority of voters is *not* according to you, a majority out of all
voters who cast ballots, but only out of voters whose ballots have not
been exhausted by the time the final IRV counting round is done.

A majority candidate, according to you, is *not* the Condorcet winner
who a majority (and indeed the most#) of voters favor above all other
candidates, but only a candidate who wins a majority in round one, or
in the final IRV counting round out of unexhausted ballots after the
Condorcet winner and other more majority-favorite winners are
eliminated.

Terry, redefine any word you want to and you make yourself right, even
if most people do not agree with your definitions.  It's a good
strategy to mislead the public like Fairytale Vote has done.

Kathy
-- 

Kathy Dopp

Town of Colonie, NY 12304
phone 518-952-4030
cell 518-505-0220

http://utahcountvotes.org
http://electionmathematics.org
http://kathydopp.com/serendipity/

Realities Mar Instant Runoff Voting
http://electionmathematics.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf

Voters Have Reason to Worry
http://utahcountvotes.org/UT/UtahCountVotes-ThadHall-Response.pdf

Checking election outcome accuracy --- Post-election audit sampling
http://electionmathematics.org/em-audits/US/PEAuditSamplingMethods.pdf

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-21 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

robert bristow-johnson wrote:


so, we have a CW...  add a candidate, if that candidate does not become 
the winner, nor cause a cycle, then the Condorcet Winner we had before 
continues to be the CW with the added candidate.  (boy, i guess we're 
rephrasing the same thing multiple times!)


Yup.

River is independent of Pareto-dominated alternatives - a candidate is 
Pareto-dominated if everybody who ranks both him and some other 
(specific) candidate, rank the other candidate above him (e.g. X is 
Pareto-dominated by Y if all voters who rank both X and Y say YX, and 
there's at least one such voter).


i wouldn't mind if someone explains this.  i don't know what 
Pareto-dominated is about.  can someone expound?


A is Pareto-dominated by B if all voters who express any difference in 
preference between A and B, prefer B to A. Note that a voter may simply 
leave both unranked - that wouldn't count towards either's Pareto 
dominance. If all voters equal-rank B and A, that doesn't count towards 
any Pareto-dominance, either.


A is Pareto-dominated (period) if there's some other candidate by which 
it is Pareto-dominated.


The strong Pareto criterion states that Pareto-dominated candidates 
shouldn't win. This makes sense, because say X won and was 
Pareto-dominated. Then people could (rightly) complain that everybody 
who expressed some preference between X and some other candidate Y, 
preferred Y, and therefore Y should have won.


Independence from Pareto-dominated alternatives then simply means that 
Pareto-dominated candidates can't be spoilers either - they can't even 
change who wins.


I imagine these resistances would mostly come into play in smaller 
elections. Still, they're nice to have, and their existence 
immediately tells parties not to try exploiting certain weaknesses 
(because it won't work).


yes, that's the whole point.  this is why i am not yet afraid of someone 
strategically voting to push a Condorcet election into a cycle.  it 
would be an unsafe way to accomplish a political goal.  how could anyone 
predict what would happen?


A party might still try, thinking they could pull it off; but complying 
with a strategic criterion stops that dead, because there's no way it's 
going to work. It doesn't even have to entertain the thought of trying. 
With advanced methods, the barrier imposed by these criteria might be so 
steep that the only remaining strategies are those where a sizable 
fraction of the electorate has to cooperate, and then it's practically 
strategy-proof in large public elections (barring disorganized 
strategy like the a sizable fraction goes on a Burial spree because 
each individual voter thinks they have nothing to lose of Warren's DH3).


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-21 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Jonathan Lundell wrote:

In that case it might be a good starting point to define spoiler,
so we know what we've found when we find it.

What's an example of an IRV spoiler who's not a pretty strong
candidate? 


A very abstract concept of spoiler might be: denote f(X) the minimal 
number of ballot changes/additions required to make X the winner. Then a 
spoiler is a candidate with a high f-value relative to the number of 
ballots (thus hard to get to win), who, by his presence, still changes 
who wins.


Determining f(x) for the various candidates would be very hard, though, 
and one also runs into the question of what threshold to say above this 
f-value, spoiler, below it, not a spoiler.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-21 Thread Juho

On Jan 21, 2010, at 5:33 PM, Jonathan Lundell wrote:


On Jan 21, 2010, at 1:03 AM, Juho wrote:

What is good in all the common Condorcet methods is that their  
vulnerabilities to strategies (and their differences in general)  
may very well be so small in typical real elections (large, public,  
with independent voter decision making, with changing opinions and  
less than perfect poll information) that strategic voting will not  
be a problem. Also their differences with sincere votes (e.g.  
spoiler related problems) are quite small in real life elections.


Here's one simple spoiler related example as a response to Kathy  
Dopp's request.


35: ABC
33: BCA
32: CAB

I this example there are three candidates in a top level cycle. If  
any of the candidates would not run that would mean that there is a  
Condorcet winner, and that winner would be different in each case.  
Let's say that the method we use will pick A as the winner. If B  
would not run then the votes would be 35: AC, 33: CA, 32: CA and  
C would win. B is thus a spoiler from C's point of view.


I note however that these spoiler cases in Condorcet are not as  
common as in many of the other methods. In practice it may be that  
there is no need to worry about these cases. Maybe Kathy Dopp's  
comparisons will reveal something about how problematic the spoiler  
effect is or is not in Condorcet. Not also that in the example  
above B was not a minor party candidate (often term spoiler refers  
to minor candidates) but a pretty strong candidate.


In that case it might be a good starting point to define spoiler,  
so we know what we've found when we find it.


What's an example of an IRV spoiler who's not a pretty strong  
candidate?


In Plurality a typical spoiler scenario is one where the spoiler is a  
minor candidate (e.g. Nader in the US presidential elections). In IRV  
the spoilers are typically stronger.


Here's one IRV example where the centrist candidate (C) wins.

30: RCL
35: CLR
35: LCR

Then we add one more candidate (C2, spoiler) that the R and L  
supporters strongly dislike.


30: RCLC2
15: CC2LR
20: C2CLR
35: LCRC2

As a result C will be eliminated first, R next, and since C2 is not a  
strong candidate L will win. C2 thus was a spoiler from C's point of  
view.


C2 is not fully a minor candidate. Although C2 has no chances to win  
C2 has more first preference votes than C. In IRV this kind of chains  
of influence could be also longer (5 candidates, 6 candidates etc.),  
and as a result the spoilers could be more and more minor. But on the  
other hand the probability of such minor candidates spoiling the  
election is very low. So, in theory also very minor spoilers are  
possible but they don't seem probable in practice.


This is related to the observation that while Plurality may be in  
trouble already when there are only two major candidates, main  
problems of IRV (and Approval and Range) seem to appear only when  
there are at least three credible candidates.


Juho





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-21 Thread Juho

On Jan 22, 2010, at 12:05 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:


Jonathan Lundell wrote:

In that case it might be a good starting point to define spoiler,
so we know what we've found when we find it.
What's an example of an IRV spoiler who's not a pretty strong
candidate?


A very abstract concept of spoiler might be: denote f(X) the minimal  
number of ballot changes/additions required to make X the winner.  
Then a spoiler is a candidate with a high f-value relative to the  
number of ballots (thus hard to get to win), who, by his presence,  
still changes who wins.


Determining f(x) for the various candidates would be very hard,  
though, and one also runs into the question of what threshold to say  
above this f-value, spoiler, below it, not a spoiler.


Maybe one should add also the requirement that the spoiler makes the  
result worse from spoiler's or spoiler's supporters' point of view.


Another possible modification is not to require f(X) to be high. One  
would just see what would have happened with and without the spoiler.  
According to that definition also strong candidates (but not actual  
winners) could be spoilers. (Typically term spoiler refers to minor  
candidates since these discussions typically refer to a two-party set- 
up, but the corresponding scientific term might or might not be  
limited to minor candidates and/or this particular set-up.)


Juho






Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-21 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 04:41 PM 1/21/2010, Jonathan Lundell wrote:

On Jan 21, 2010, at 1:32 PM, Kathy Dopp wrote:

 Terry, You cleverly conveniently change all the definitions whenver it
 is necessary to make yourself and Fairytale Vote right on the facts.

Define spoiler, please, unambiguously.


The term has usage, and must be understood from that. A formal 
definition, nailing it down, would be arbitrary. But Kathy's 
definition is one reasonable one that matches common usage.


But there is another which is broader and, to distinguish this from 
the common usage, I call the common usage the first order spoiler 
effect. It refers to minor candidates, with hopelessly low support, 
who alter the outcome between two major candidates by drawing away 
votes preferentially from one, from voters who would otherwise vote 
for that one. The application most common is with plurality, but also 
top-two runoff and, similarly, IRV, where as little as one vote and 
some back luck in the resolution of a tie can cause the effect.


To define this l.e. spoiler effect more crisply would be arbitrary.

But then there is a more generalized spoiler effect, more commonly 
referred to as center squeeze. It's a spoiler effect, all right, in 
substance, because an extremist candidates, who would lose in a 
direct contest between either the centrist or the other extremist, 
draws enough higher preference votes away from the centrist to reduce 
that centrist below second rank in first preference. So this is an IIA problem. 



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-21 Thread Kathy Dopp
On Thu, Jan 21, 2010 at 7:34 PM, Abd ul-Rahman Lomax
a...@lomaxdesign.com wrote:
 At 04:41 PM 1/21/2010, Jonathan Lundell wrote:

 On Jan 21, 2010, at 1:32 PM, Kathy Dopp wrote:

  Terry, You cleverly conveniently change all the definitions whenver it
  is necessary to make yourself and Fairytale Vote right on the facts.

 Define spoiler, please, unambiguously.

 The term has usage, and must be understood from that. A formal definition,
 nailing it down, would be arbitrary. But Kathy's definition is one
 reasonable one that matches common usage.

 But there is another which is broader and, to distinguish this from the

Abd ul, actually your definition below is *narrower* not broader,
because it narrows the number of cases that fit the definition.  I
simply took my broader definition that includes all cases of
nonwinning candidates who alter election outcomes by their presence,
from Arrow's fairness criteria which is describes less simply here:

Arrow's Fairness Criteria

http://www.ctl.ua.edu/math103/Voting/whatdowe.htm#The%20Independence%20of%20Irrelevant%20Alternatives%20Criterion

So you see that my definition is actually Arrow's definition of
spoiler, not my own original definition.

Kathy

 common usage, I call the common usage the first order spoiler effect. It
 refers to minor candidates, with hopelessly low support, who alter the
 outcome between two major candidates by drawing away votes preferentially
 from one, from voters who would otherwise vote for that one. The application
 most common is with plurality, but also top-two runoff and, similarly, IRV,
 where as little as one vote and some back luck in the resolution of a tie
 can cause the effect.

 To define this l.e. spoiler effect more crisply would be arbitrary.

 But then there is a more generalized spoiler effect, more commonly
 referred to as center squeeze. It's a spoiler effect, all right, in
 substance, because an extremist candidates, who would lose in a direct
 contest between either the centrist or the other extremist, draws enough
 higher preference votes away from the centrist to reduce that centrist below
 second rank in first preference. So this is an IIA problem.




-- 

Kathy Dopp

Town of Colonie, NY 12304
phone 518-952-4030
cell 518-505-0220

http://utahcountvotes.org
http://electionmathematics.org
http://kathydopp.com/serendipity/

Realities Mar Instant Runoff Voting
http://electionmathematics.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf

Voters Have Reason to Worry
http://utahcountvotes.org/UT/UtahCountVotes-ThadHall-Response.pdf

Checking election outcome accuracy --- Post-election audit sampling
http://electionmathematics.org/em-audits/US/PEAuditSamplingMethods.pdf

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-21 Thread Terry Bouricius
Kathy,

I ask that you stop smearing me on this (and other) discussion lists. I 
did not alter any standard definition of spoilers.  Webster's online for 
example defines it as:
1. A candidate with no chance of winning but who may draw enough votes to 
prevent one of the leading candidates from winning.


This means a spoiler is a non-leading candidate with almost no chance of 
winning (I think the term minor is a fair way of stating that concisely) 
and not one of the leading candidates.  Note also that the concept of 
having a chance to win suggests the term can be applied prospectively, 
prior to knowing what the ballots reveal. Kurt Wright, being perceived as 
a likely winners and who was in first place in the initial tally had an 
EXCELLENT chance of winning, and almost did in the runoff, and thus does 
not meet the standard definition of a spoiler.

I will refrain from the majority discussion, as that is off topic.

Terry Bouricius

- Original Message - 
From: Kathy Dopp kathy.d...@gmail.com
To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
Sent: Thursday, January 21, 2010 4:32 PM
Subject: Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected


 From: Terry Bouricius ter...@burlingtontelecom.net
 To: Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com, Juho
 juho4...@yahoo.co.uk

 Jonathan makes an important point. The term spoiler means a minor
 candidate with a small percentage of the vote, who changes which of the
 other candidates wins by running. But Kathy and some others wish to 
 expand
 the definition to include a front-runner. (Note that these IRV opponents
 refer to the top plurality vote-getter who narrowly lost the runoff in
 Burlington, Kurt Wright, as a spoiler who prevented the candidate in
 third place from winning. This is a dynamic worthy of analysis, but the
 word spoiler is never used by the media or political scientists when
 describing the plurality leader.

 Terry Bouricius


Thanks for all the information re. Condorcet cycles and the unlikely
cases of spoilers in Condorcet method of counting rank choice votes
from Juho and Robert.


Terry, You cleverly conveniently change all the definitions whenver it
is necessary to make yourself and Fairytale Vote right on the facts.
 Let's see what some of them are:

A spoiler is *not* according to you, a nonwinning candidate whose
presence in the election changes who would otherwise be the winner,
but only a particular type of spoiler that is a minor candidate.

A majority of voters is *not* according to you, a majority out of all
voters who cast ballots, but only out of voters whose ballots have not
been exhausted by the time the final IRV counting round is done.

A majority candidate, according to you, is *not* the Condorcet winner
who a majority (and indeed the most#) of voters favor above all other
candidates, but only a candidate who wins a majority in round one, or
in the final IRV counting round out of unexhausted ballots after the
Condorcet winner and other more majority-favorite winners are
eliminated.

Terry, redefine any word you want to and you make yourself right, even
if most people do not agree with your definitions.  It's a good
strategy to mislead the public like Fairytale Vote has done.

Kathy
-- 

Kathy Dopp

Town of Colonie, NY 12304
phone 518-952-4030
cell 518-505-0220

http://utahcountvotes.org
http://electionmathematics.org
http://kathydopp.com/serendipity/

Realities Mar Instant Runoff Voting
http://electionmathematics.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf

Voters Have Reason to Worry
http://utahcountvotes.org/UT/UtahCountVotes-ThadHall-Response.pdf

Checking election outcome accuracy --- Post-election audit sampling
http://electionmathematics.org/em-audits/US/PEAuditSamplingMethods.pdf

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-21 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Jan 21, 2010, at 8:58 PM, Terry Bouricius wrote:


Kathy,

I ask that you stop smearing me on this (and other) discussion lists.


rots o' ruk.

I did not alter any standard definition of spoilers.  Webster's  
online

for example defines it as:
1. A candidate with no chance of winning but who may draw enough  
votes to

prevent one of the leading candidates from winning.


This means a spoiler is a non-leading candidate with almost no  
chance of
winning (I think the term minor is a fair way of stating that  
concisely)
and not one of the leading candidates.  Note also that the  
concept of
having a chance to win suggests the term can be applied  
prospectively,
prior to knowing what the ballots reveal. Kurt Wright, being  
perceived as
a likely winners and who was in first place in the initial tally  
had an
EXCELLENT chance of winning, and almost did in the runoff, and thus  
does

not meet the standard definition of a spoiler.



Terry, you may have read that i take some responsibility for also  
associating Wright as the spoiler by replacing almost no chance of  
winning to having lost in the definition.  and i know that they  
are not the same thing.


strictly speaking, Kurt Wright was not a spoiler because it is  
uncontroversial whether or not he had a chance of winning.


that said, i believe that a spoiler-lite (a candidate who loses and  
whose presence in an election changes who the winner is) problem is  
still a problem.  i think, in these parts, we call it Independence  
of irrelevant alternatives.  IIA is spoiler-lite even if it is not  
always the spoiler scenario.


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-21 Thread Kathy Dopp
Start telling the truth about IRV at Fairytale Vote, and then when
people speak the truth about Fairytale Vote, it won't sound like a
smear.

If you don't like the sound of your own behavior when retold, try some
different behavior, rather than falsely accusing others of smearing
you when they tell the truth. The list of deliberate misinformation
told by the Fairytale Vote group, if put together in one place, would
reach to the moon most likely, as this one youtube video alludes to.
Experts in election methods have had occasions to debunk the
disinformation by Fairytale Vote sufficiently to know that.

http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=bPCS-zWuel8

So continue to alter the definitions of commonly used words in order
to make yourself right because that's the only way you can do that
Terry.

Your definition of spoiler alters the definition that was given by
Arrow's theorem which is the one I choose to use, not the narrower one
your organization uses in order to make the false claim that IRV
solves the spoiler problem even though it obviously does not, and the
Republican candidate acted as a spoiler to knock out the most popular
Democratic candidate so that their least favorite, the left wing
Progressive could win.

Terry, just do not imagine that people do not see the trick you use
of redefining words that have had a common meaning for decades.

Cheers,
Kathy



On Thu, Jan 21, 2010 at 8:58 PM, Terry Bouricius
ter...@burlingtontelecom.net wrote:
 Kathy,

 I ask that you stop smearing me on this (and other) discussion lists. I
 did not alter any standard definition of spoilers.  Webster's online for
 example defines it as:
 1. A candidate with no chance of winning but who may draw enough votes to
 prevent one of the leading candidates from winning.


 This means a spoiler is a non-leading candidate with almost no chance of
 winning (I think the term minor is a fair way of stating that concisely)
 and not one of the leading candidates.  Note also that the concept of
 having a chance to win suggests the term can be applied prospectively,
 prior to knowing what the ballots reveal. Kurt Wright, being perceived as
 a likely winners and who was in first place in the initial tally had an
 EXCELLENT chance of winning, and almost did in the runoff, and thus does
 not meet the standard definition of a spoiler.

 I will refrain from the majority discussion, as that is off topic.

 Terry Bouricius

 - Original Message -
 From: Kathy Dopp kathy.d...@gmail.com
 To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
 Sent: Thursday, January 21, 2010 4:32 PM
 Subject: Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected


 From: Terry Bouricius ter...@burlingtontelecom.net
 To: Jonathan Lundell jlund...@pobox.com, Juho
 juho4...@yahoo.co.uk

 Jonathan makes an important point. The term spoiler means a minor
 candidate with a small percentage of the vote, who changes which of the
 other candidates wins by running. But Kathy and some others wish to
 expand
 the definition to include a front-runner. (Note that these IRV opponents
 refer to the top plurality vote-getter who narrowly lost the runoff in
 Burlington, Kurt Wright, as a spoiler who prevented the candidate in
 third place from winning. This is a dynamic worthy of analysis, but the
 word spoiler is never used by the media or political scientists when
 describing the plurality leader.

 Terry Bouricius


 Thanks for all the information re. Condorcet cycles and the unlikely
 cases of spoilers in Condorcet method of counting rank choice votes
 from Juho and Robert.


 Terry, You cleverly conveniently change all the definitions whenver it
 is necessary to make yourself and Fairytale Vote right on the facts.
  Let's see what some of them are:

 A spoiler is *not* according to you, a nonwinning candidate whose
 presence in the election changes who would otherwise be the winner,
 but only a particular type of spoiler that is a minor candidate.

 A majority of voters is *not* according to you, a majority out of all
 voters who cast ballots, but only out of voters whose ballots have not
 been exhausted by the time the final IRV counting round is done.

 A majority candidate, according to you, is *not* the Condorcet winner
 who a majority (and indeed the most#) of voters favor above all other
 candidates, but only a candidate who wins a majority in round one, or
 in the final IRV counting round out of unexhausted ballots after the
 Condorcet winner and other more majority-favorite winners are
 eliminated.

 Terry, redefine any word you want to and you make yourself right, even
 if most people do not agree with your definitions.  It's a good
 strategy to mislead the public like Fairytale Vote has done.

 Kathy
 --

 Kathy Dopp

 Town of Colonie, NY 12304
 phone 518-952-4030
 cell 518-505-0220

 http://utahcountvotes.org
 http://electionmathematics.org
 http://kathydopp.com/serendipity/

 Realities Mar Instant Runoff Voting
 http://electionmathematics.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV

Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected

2010-01-21 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Jan 21, 2010, at 9:03 PM, Kathy Dopp wrote:

 Start telling the truth about IRV at Fairytale Vote, and then when
 people speak the truth about Fairytale Vote, it won't sound like a
 smear.

Ha ha! I've been meaning to compliment you, Ms Dopp, on that sidesplitting 
line. It was really funny the first time, and it's gotten more hilarious each 
time you've used it since. How many times? I've lost count, to tell the truth, 
but please keep it up. Fairytale! Fantastic! I can't get enough.

 
 If you don't like the sound of your own behavior when retold, try some
 different behavior, rather than falsely accusing others of smearing
 you when they tell the truth. The list of deliberate misinformation
 told by the Fairytale Vote group, if put together in one place, would
 reach to the moon most likely, as this one youtube video alludes to.
 Experts in election methods have had occasions to debunk the
 disinformation by Fairytale Vote sufficiently to know that.

Three times in one post. Just in case we readers don't get it the first or 
second time--the mark of a master comic. Thanks!

 
 http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=bPCS-zWuel8
 
 So continue to alter the definitions of commonly used words in order
 to make yourself right because that's the only way you can do that
 Terry.
 
 Your definition of spoiler alters the definition that was given by
 Arrow's theorem which is the one I choose to use,

Arrow never used, never mind defined, the word spoiler.

 not the narrower one
 your organization uses in order to make the false claim that IRV
 solves the spoiler problem even though it obviously does not, and the
 Republican candidate acted as a spoiler to knock out the most popular
 Democratic candidate so that their least favorite, the left wing
 Progressive could win.
 
 Terry, just do not imagine that people do not see the trick you use
 of redefining words that have had a common meaning for decades.



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-20 Thread Kathy Dopp
If the Condorcet method is susceptible to the phenomena of a
nonwinning candidate whose presence in the election changes who would
otherwise win the election, all else being equal.

Could someone please provide me with an example of the spoiler effect
occuring with the Condorcet method  of counting rank choice ballots or
tell me why the spoiler effect doesn't happen with Condorcet in  a few
words?

Thanks. I'm devising an experiment to compare the Condorcet method
with the IRV method of counting rank choice ballots and would like, if
possible, to introduce subjects to the spoiler effect to see under
what conditions they notice it occurs.  I can easily generate spoiler
scenarios with IRV but do not know how to generate spoiler scenarios
with the Condorcet method and if it's not too much trouble, would
appreciate an example if Condorcet is susceptible to spoilers.

Thank you.

-- 

Kathy Dopp

Town of Colonie, NY 12304
phone 518-952-4030
cell 518-505-0220

http://utahcountvotes.org
http://electionmathematics.org
http://kathydopp.com/serendipity/

Realities Mar Instant Runoff Voting
http://electionmathematics.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf

Voters Have Reason to Worry
http://utahcountvotes.org/UT/UtahCountVotes-ThadHall-Response.pdf

Checking election outcome accuracy --- Post-election audit sampling
http://electionmathematics.org/em-audits/US/PEAuditSamplingMethods.pdf

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-20 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Jan 20, 2010, at 7:10 PM, Kathy Dopp wrote:


Is the Condorcet method susceptible to the phenomena of a
nonwinning candidate whose presence in the election changes who would
otherwise win the election, all else being equal?



i changed the sentence form into a question.  i hope that was okay,  
Kathy.  don't wanna misquote anyone.


i think that the answer is no, if a Condorcet winner exists and  
that all bets are off if a CW does not exist, except, perhaps for  
these strategy-resistant methods such as Markus Schulze's method.   
i sorta understand it, but since he hangs here, i think Markus should  
address the question if the Schulze method is spoiler free.



Could someone please provide me with an example of the spoiler  
effect occuring with the Condorcet method  of counting rank choice  
ballots or tell me why the spoiler effect doesn't happen with  
Condorcet in  a few words?


in the ranked-order ballot, no matter what their absolute ranks are,  
if A is ranked above B (or A is ranked while B is not), that counts  
as a vote for A.  likewise for B ranked above A.  doesn't matter if  
they were ranked 4th and 5th.


just like the IRV final round between A and B, Condorcet will total  
how many votes with AB and compare that to votes where BA.  whether  
C is in the race or not, for each individual ballot, if AB with C on  
the ballot, A would continue to be ranked above B (whether C is  
higher than either, in between, or below either).  with the meaning  
of every ballot, regarding A and B, unchanged (whether C is there or  
not), the vote counts for AB and BA do not change.  so every  
Condorcet tally not involving candidate C will remain unchanged, the  
tallies involving C are not there if C is removed.


if A (or whoever is not C) was the Condorcet winner before C was  
removed, then the AX tally exceeds XA for any X.   then A would  
continue to be ranked over all of the other remaining candidates with  
the same tallies as before even with C removed, because every tally  
not involving C would remain unchanged.


i would say that (with the CW existing), it's spoiler-proof.



Thanks. I'm devising an experiment to compare the Condorcet method
with the IRV method of counting rank choice ballots and would like, if
possible, to introduce subjects to the spoiler effect to see under
what conditions they notice it occurs.


do you want me to tell you how it occurred in Burlington in 2009?

--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-20 Thread Kathy Dopp
Thanks Robert,

My question was strictly about Condorcet and I know already how to
generate IRV and spoiler cases, as I said.

Are you claiming that Condorcet methods are never subjected to a case
of a nonwinning candidate changing who would otherwise win?

This seems logical, given the method and what you say below. However,...

Do any others on this list agree though or if not, please provide an example?

Thanks.

Kathy

On Wed, Jan 20, 2010 at 7:34 PM, robert bristow-johnson
r...@audioimagination.com wrote:

 On Jan 20, 2010, at 7:10 PM, Kathy Dopp wrote:

 Is the Condorcet method susceptible to the phenomena of a
 nonwinning candidate whose presence in the election changes who would
 otherwise win the election, all else being equal?


 i changed the sentence form into a question.  i hope that was okay, Kathy.
  don't wanna misquote anyone.

 i think that the answer is no, if a Condorcet winner exists and that all
 bets are off if a CW does not exist, except, perhaps for these
 strategy-resistant methods such as Markus Schulze's method.  i sorta
 understand it, but since he hangs here, i think Markus should address the
 question if the Schulze method is spoiler free.


 Could someone please provide me with an example of the spoiler effect
 occuring with the Condorcet method  of counting rank choice ballots or tell
 me why the spoiler effect doesn't happen with Condorcet in  a few words?

 in the ranked-order ballot, no matter what their absolute ranks are, if A is
 ranked above B (or A is ranked while B is not), that counts as a vote for A.
  likewise for B ranked above A.  doesn't matter if they were ranked 4th and
 5th.

 just like the IRV final round between A and B, Condorcet will total how many
 votes with AB and compare that to votes where BA.  whether C is in the
 race or not, for each individual ballot, if AB with C on the ballot, A
 would continue to be ranked above B (whether C is higher than either, in
 between, or below either).  with the meaning of every ballot, regarding A
 and B, unchanged (whether C is there or not), the vote counts for AB and
 BA do not change.  so every Condorcet tally not involving candidate C will
 remain unchanged, the tallies involving C are not there if C is removed.

 if A (or whoever is not C) was the Condorcet winner before C was removed,
 then the AX tally exceeds XA for any X.   then A would continue to be
 ranked over all of the other remaining candidates with the same tallies as
 before even with C removed, because every tally not involving C would remain
 unchanged.

 i would say that (with the CW existing), it's spoiler-proof.


 Thanks. I'm devising an experiment to compare the Condorcet method
 with the IRV method of counting rank choice ballots and would like, if
 possible, to introduce subjects to the spoiler effect to see under
 what conditions they notice it occurs.

 do you want me to tell you how it occurred in Burlington in 2009?

 --

 r b-j                  ...@audioimagination.com

 Imagination is more important than knowledge.








-- 

Kathy Dopp

Town of Colonie, NY 12304
phone 518-952-4030
cell 518-505-0220

http://utahcountvotes.org
http://electionmathematics.org
http://kathydopp.com/serendipity/

Realities Mar Instant Runoff Voting
http://electionmathematics.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf

Voters Have Reason to Worry
http://utahcountvotes.org/UT/UtahCountVotes-ThadHall-Response.pdf

Checking election outcome accuracy --- Post-election audit sampling
http://electionmathematics.org/em-audits/US/PEAuditSamplingMethods.pdf

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-20 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Jan 20, 2010, at 7:54 PM, Kathy Dopp wrote:


Thanks Robert,

My question was strictly about Condorcet and I know already how to
generate IRV and spoiler cases, as I said.

Are you claiming that Condorcet methods are never subjected to a case
of a nonwinning candidate changing who would otherwise win?


i said only if there is a Condorcet winner.  even though i don't  
think it would be at all commonplace, much of the discussion between  
the geeks here sometimes is about exactly what to do for Condorcet  
cycles.  i'm less invested (hell, perhaps if there is a cycle we  
decide by IRV rules, or pick the candidate with the plurality 1st- 
choice vote, i really don't care that much) in whatever happens if  
there is no CW since i don't think it will happen often in real life.


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-20 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

robert bristow-johnson wrote:


i think that the answer is no, if a Condorcet winner exists and that 
all bets are off if a CW does not exist, except, perhaps for these 
strategy-resistant methods such as Markus Schulze's method.  i sorta 
understand it, but since he hangs here, i think Markus should address 
the question if the Schulze method is spoiler free.


MAM/Ranked Pairs is also pretty strategy-resistant and is easier to 
understand. Schulze has the advantage of producing better results in 
some cases (closer to Minmax), but if ability to describe to the 
public is important, then Ranked Pairs wins there.


Could someone please provide me with an example of the spoiler effect 
occuring with the Condorcet method  of counting rank choice ballots or 
tell me why the spoiler effect doesn't happen with Condorcet in  a few 
words?


(...)


i would say that (with the CW existing), it's spoiler-proof.


Yes. If there's a CW and a candidate is added, and that candidate 
doesn't create a cycle, then the winner doesn't change. All the tricky 
stuff happens when there is a cycle, or the candidate makes one.


The advanced methods can claim further resistance: Schulze and Ranked 
Pairs both make their winner decision independent of candidates not in 
the Smith set. River is independent of Pareto-dominated alternatives - a 
candidate is Pareto-dominated if everybody who ranks both him and some 
other (specific) candidate, rank the other candidate above him (e.g. X 
is Pareto-dominated by Y if all voters who rank both X and Y say YX, 
and there's at least one such voter).


I imagine these resistances would mostly come into play in smaller 
elections. Still, they're nice to have, and their existence immediately 
tells parties not to try exploiting certain weaknesses (because it won't 
work).


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] I need an example of Condorcet method being subjected to the spoiler effect if any

2010-01-20 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Jan 21, 2010, at 2:29 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:


robert bristow-johnson wrote:
i think that the answer is no, if a Condorcet winner exists and  
that all bets are off if a CW does not exist, except, perhaps for  
these strategy-resistant methods such as Markus Schulze's  
method.  i sorta understand it, but since he hangs here, i think  
Markus should address the question if the Schulze method is  
spoiler free.


MAM/Ranked Pairs is also pretty strategy-resistant and is easier to  
understand. Schulze has the advantage of producing better results  
in some cases (closer to Minmax), but if ability to describe to  
the public is important, then Ranked Pairs wins there.


Could someone please provide me with an example of the spoiler  
effect occuring with the Condorcet method  of counting rank  
choice ballots or tell me why the spoiler effect doesn't happen  
with Condorcet in  a few words?


(...)


i would say that (with the CW existing), it's spoiler-proof.


Yes. If there's a CW and a candidate is added, and that candidate  
doesn't create a cycle, then the winner doesn't change.


and if that candidate that is added doesn't *win*.  a spoiler is  
*not* a winner that when removed from the election and all ballots  
does not change who the winner is.  a spoiler must be a loser to the  
election, whose presence changes who the winner is.  i remember  
reading someone's poor attack on IRV (in local Burlington blogs) that  
claimed that Bob Kiss (who won Burlington's IRV election) was a  
spoiler.  they were misusing or misunderstanding the concept of a  
3rd-party candidate.  (maybe somewhere else, a 3rd-party candidate  
can only hope to be a spoiler, but in Burlington a 3rd-party  
candidate can expect to win office once in a while.  that's a little  
different.)


so, we have a CW...  add a candidate, if that candidate does not  
become the winner, nor cause a cycle, then the Condorcet Winner we  
had before continues to be the CW with the added candidate.  (boy, i  
guess we're rephrasing the same thing multiple times!)


All the tricky stuff happens when there is a cycle, or the  
candidate makes one.


yup.

The advanced methods can claim further resistance: Schulze and  
Ranked Pairs both make their winner decision independent of  
candidates not in the Smith set.


this, i understand...

River is independent of Pareto-dominated alternatives - a candidate  
is Pareto-dominated if everybody who ranks both him and some other  
(specific) candidate, rank the other candidate above him (e.g. X is  
Pareto-dominated by Y if all voters who rank both X and Y say YX,  
and there's at least one such voter).


i wouldn't mind if someone explains this.  i don't know what Pareto- 
dominated is about.  can someone expound?


I imagine these resistances would mostly come into play in smaller  
elections. Still, they're nice to have, and their existence  
immediately tells parties not to try exploiting certain weaknesses  
(because it won't work).


yes, that's the whole point.  this is why i am not yet afraid of  
someone strategically voting to push a Condorcet election into a  
cycle.  it would be an unsafe way to accomplish a political goal.   
how could anyone predict what would happen?


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info